A World of Appearances: Sperone Speroni and the Debate Over

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

A World of Appearances: Sperone Speroni and the Debate Over A WORLD OF APPEARANCES: SPERONE SPERONI AND THE DEBATE OVER SOPHISTRY IN THE ITALIAN RENAISSANCE by Teodoro Katinis A dissertation submitted to Johns Hopkins University in conformity with the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy Baltimore, Maryland February, 2015 © 2015 Teodoro Katinis All Rights Reserved ABSTRACT This dissertation analyzes the works of Sperone Speroni degli Alvarotti (Padua 1500–1588), his re-evaluation of ancient sophistic perspectives and his legacy in the early modern age. Although international studies on the subject are taken into consideration, this research is mainly conducted through a systematic exploration of ancient and early modern primary sources. The rigorous and direct analysis of the texts is a consistent practice for determining results. The subject of this research, at the intersection of Italian literature and philosophy, requires an interdisciplinary approach throughout the dissertation. Speroni was one of the most important protagonists of the Renaissance debate on language and logic as well as civil and speculative philosophy. Educated as an Aristotelian, he eventually developed a distinctive literary and philosophical production and was the first to challenge Plato’s (327-447 BCE) condemnation of sophists. Still, despite the fact that Speroni was a central figure of Renaissance philosophy and literature in the vernacular, he is one of the most neglected authors in international scholarship. Furthermore, scholars have considered Speroni’s interest in ancient sophists as a marginal aspect of his oeuvre and have disregarded the paramount role of the period’s vernacular writing on sophistry that began with his works and spread throughout sixteenth-century Italy. This four-chapter dissertation fills the gap in international studies, being the first monograph dedicated to Speroni written in English and the first work written in any language investigating the fundamental role of the ancient sophistic tradition in the Italian Renaissance. The first chapter analyzes fifteenth-century authors’ translation and comments on works related to sophistry. The second examines Speroni’s works that argue for the rehabilitation of the ancient Greek ii sophists. The third explores Speroni’s sophistic writing in the form of double arguments and paradoxical dialogues. The fourth chapter focuses on the debate about sophistry and its relationship with literature and arts in Italy at the end of the sixteenth century, which also involves the quarrel about Dante’s poetry. The conclusions summarize the most relevant aspect of the dissertation and present further paths for research in different fruitful direction. Christopher Celenza and Walter Stephens have been the advisors for this dissertation. iii PREFACE Between my first doctoral degree earned in Italy and my current doctoral research project at Johns Hopkins University, I taught history and philosophy in Italian licei for several years. As a teacher I realized that Renaissance culture is not an easy subject to both teach and learn. Antiquity and modernity fitted into the yearly program as a sequence of very manageable philosophical systems. My students and I could go through them fluidly, knowing, ultimately, where the path would lead. Even the complex thinkers, the monumental ones, could be reduced within a clear structure so that students could have a distinct idea of their literary style and major theories. For authors such as Plato, Aristotle, Kant, and Hegel, a larger project was necessary at the beginning for mastering the lexicon of key concepts, but then it was only a matter of following a clear path, paralleling my teaching and students’ learning. However, when it came time to approach the fifteenth and sixteenth century, both the students and I had to leave the quiet streaming waters to face the most perilous and exciting falls called Renaissance. For the very same reason, since my graduation I have chosen to work on the Renaissance era and I hope I have been able to contribute to recovering one of the most fascinating periods of Western culture. For my first doctoral research, at the University of Rome, I studied the medical works of Marsilio Ficino to demonstrate how fruitful a study of the most Platonic author of the fifteenth century could be from the perspective of history of medicine and natural philosophy. Throughout my four-year research in the Department of German and Romance Languages and Literatures at Johns Hopkins University I have wanted to prove how the Aristotelian Sperone Speroni, writing in the age of Reformation and Counter- iv Reformation and considered an inoffensive author, could be the spring for the rebirth of one of the most ‘heritical’ movements of antiquity, sophistry. Both my doctoral projects have benefited from a strong interdisciplinary approach and have been situated at the intersection of different fields: history of philosophy and history of medicine in the first case, Italian literature and history of philosophy in the second. To avoid any misunderstanding from ambiguous meaning of the term “sophistry,” I would like to clarify that this word does not have a derogatory connotation in this dissertation. Unlike the ordinary meaning in non-academic discussions, which refer to “sophistry,” “sophistic art,” “sophism,” “sophist” mostly in order to blame something or someone, in this dissertation these expressions will be always used within the specific meaning that they have in the field. The same type of misunderstanding might affect the word “appearance” in the title of this dissertation (A World of Appearances), although reading this study on the sophistic Renaissance will reveal how much the term “appearance” actually enables connecting philosophy, rhetoric, poetry, and painting in the unique cultural environment that was the Italian Renaissance. v ACKNOWLEDGMENTS I am grateful to many colleagues and friends for their suggestions on several aspects of this work. Special thanks are owed to my advisors, Christopher Celenza and Walter Stephens, and to John Monfasani, Richard Blum, Eric MacPhail, Pier Massimo Forni, Mario Pozzi, and Valerio Vianello. I thank the staff of the Department and Library for their work and help during my years at Johns Hopkins University, particularly Kathy Loehmer who is not only wonderful but also the most organized person I have ever met. Many friends have had an essential role in my life in the US. Special thanks go to Miryam Yardumian, and Anthony and Maryann Villa, who have warmly welcomed my family as a part of their own. I dedicate this work to my wife Monica and my son Giulio, with whom I have shared all the difficulties and exciting moments of our American life. vi TABLE OF CONTENTS Introduction………………………………………………………………………………………….1 Chapter I: Fifteenth-century perspectives on ancient sophists………………………………10 1. Introduction…………………………………………………………………………………..…10 2. Gorgias redivivus………………………………………………………………………………13 3. Protagoras and humanist literature…………………………………………………………19 4. Marsilio Ficino’s interpretation of sophists……………………………………………...24 Chapter II: Speroni and the sophists………………………………………………………..42 1. Orator et philosophus………………………………………………………………………..42 2. Speroni’s defense and reevaluation of sophistry…………………………………………45 2.1. Rhetoric: an imperfect science for an imperfect world…………………………………46 2.2. The defense of sophists……………………………………………………………………..67 2.3. The condemnation of Socrates………………………………………………………….71 3. The Dialogo della retorica……………………………………………………………………74 Chapter III: Speroni’s practice of sophistic rhetoric………………………………………..86 1. Antilogies……………………………………………………………………………………..87 1.1. Against the sophists………………………………………………………………………...89 1.2. What is virtue? ……………………………………………………………………………..94 1.3. Condemning and praising moderation……………………………………………………97 vii 2. Rhetoric in dialogues ……………………………………………………………………….106 2.1. Dialogo della Discordia…………………………………………………………………...109 2.2. Dialogo dell’Usura………………………………………………………………………..121 Chapter IV: The debate on Dante and sophistic poetry……………………………………126 1. Tasso’s concern about poetry: an overview of the late Cinquecento………………….127 2. Crafting idols: Jacopo Mazzoni’s poetics……………………………………………….133 3. Dante among sophists and skeptics……………………………………………………...142 4. Ut pictura poesis: Mazzoni, Speroni, Comanini…………………………………………151 Conclusions and possible aftermath…………………………………………………………..168 Bibliography……………………………………………………………………………………...185 viii Introduction Sperone Speroni degli Alvarotti (Padua 1500–1588) was Pietro Pomponazzi’s (1462–1525) pupil at the University of Bologna where he was educated as an Aristotelian. He was one of the main members of the “Accademia degli Infiammati” (“Academy of the Burning Ones”) in Padua and “Accademia delle notti vaticane” (“Academy of the Vatican Nights”) in Rome. He taught logic and philosophy at the University of Padua. His extraordinary rhetorical ability and performances were well known in the Italian political and cultural environment. Being an advocate of the use of Italian language for any and all disciplines, he was presented as one of the fathers of the vernacular in Bernardino Tomitano’s (1517-1576) Ragionamenti della lingua toscana (1546). He was also in contact with the most important protagonists of the sixteenth century, including Pietro Aretino (1492-1556), Bernardo Tasso (1493-1569), Torquato Tasso (1544-1595), Gasparo Contarini (1483-1542), Jacopo Mazzoni (1548-1598), Pope Pius IV (1499- 1565), and the Duke of Urbino Guidobaldo II della Rovere (1514-1574), among others.1
Recommended publications
  • 3 a Martyr of Painting
    The social lives of paintings in Sixteenth-Century Venice Kessel, E.J.M. van Citation Kessel, E. J. M. van. (2011, December 1). The social lives of paintings in Sixteenth-Century Venice. Retrieved from https://hdl.handle.net/1887/18182 Version: Not Applicable (or Unknown) Licence agreement concerning inclusion of doctoral License: thesis in the Institutional Repository of the University of Leiden Downloaded from: https://hdl.handle.net/1887/18182 Note: To cite this publication please use the final published version (if applicable). 3 A Martyr of Painting Irene di Spilimbergo, Titian, and Venetian Portraiture between Life and Death Pygmalion’s love for the figure of ivory, which was made by his own hands, gives us an example of those people who try to circumvent the forces of nature, never willing to en- joy that sweet and soft love that regularly occurs between man and woman. While we are naturally always inclined to love, those people give themselves over to love things that are hardly fruitful, only for their own pleasure, such as Paintings, Sculptures, medals, or similar things. And they love them so dearly that those same things manage to satisfy their desires, as if their desire had been satisfied by real Love that has to be between man and woman.1 Giuseppe Orologi, comment on Ovid’s Metamorphoses (1578) As Giuseppe Orologi, a writer with connections to Titian, makes clear in his commentary on Ovid’s story of the sculptor Pygmalion, some people of his 1 ‘L’amore di Pigmaleone, alla figura di Avorio fatta da le sue mani, ci da essempio
    [Show full text]
  • «Legato Con Amore in Un Volume, Ciò Che Per L'universo Si Squaderna»
    FLORILEGIO DI EDIZIONI DANTESCHE «legato con amore in un volume, ciò che per l’universo si squaderna» LIBRERIA PHILOBIBLON - LIBRERIA PREGLIASCO «legato con amore in un volume, ciò che per l’universo si squaderna» (Paradiso XXXIII, 86-87) Et per mia opinione questo commento e di un Jacopo Bolognese, che secondo il medesimo Landino scrisse nella patria lingua: per che ci sono molte parole Bolognesi, et si mostra molto informato delle cose di Bologna. V. B. (Postilla manoscritta di Vincenzo Buonanni apposta all’esemplare dell’edizione di Venezia, Vindelino da Spira, 1477; cfr scheda n. 1) Questo Florilegio dantesco, realizzato in collaborazione tra la Libreria Philobiblon e la Libreria Pregliasco, non è che una scelta dei libri di maggior pregio di una collezione dantesca di oltre mille opere, il cui catalogo completo vedrà senz’altro la luce prima del 690° anniversario della morte del Poeta. Comprenderà quasi tutte le edizioni critiche del Poema e delle opere cosiddette “minori”, nonché quattrocento volumi monografici ed opuscoli in varie lingue sui più variegati aspetti della figura di Dante. N.B. L’illustrazione in copertina si riferisce al n. 32, Suite acquerellata di Zatta. 1 Libreria PHILOBIBLON Libreria Antiquaria PREGLIASCO Piazza S. Simpliciano, 7 Via Accademia Albertina, 3 bis 20121 Milano 10123 Torino Tel. (+39) 02 89076643 Tel. (+39) 011.8177114 - Telefax (+39) Fax (+39) 02 89076644 011.8179214 Palazzo Massimo - Piazza dei Massimi, 3 e-mail: [email protected] 00186 Roma www.preliber.com Tel. (+39) 06 45555970 Fax (+39) 06 45555991 e-mail: [email protected] www.philobiblon.org redazione e responsabilità - Arturo e Umberto Pregliasco - Filippo Rotundo grafica - Francesco Pregliasco stampa - GRAFART CONDIZIONI DI VENDITA I libri sono garantiti completi e in buono stato, salvo indicazione contraria.
    [Show full text]
  • Pomponazzi on Identity and Individuation Han Thomas Adriaenssen Abstract. Aristotle Defines Growing As a Process in Which An
    Final version forthcoming in Journal of the History of Philosophy Pomponazzi on Identity and Individuation Han Thomas Adriaenssen Abstract. Aristotle defines growing as a process in which an individual living being persists as it accumulates new matter. This definition raises the question of what enables an individual to persist as its material composition continuously changes over time. This paper provides a systematic account of Pietro Pomponazzi’s answer to this question. In his De nutritione et augmentatione, Pomponazzi argues that individuals persist in virtue of their forms. Forms are individuated in part by their material, causal, and temporal origins, which commits Pomponazzi to the view that individuals necessarily have the material, causal, and temporal origins they do. I provide an account of why Pomponazzi was willing to this view. While his opponents remain unnamed, I argue that his arguments for this view are best read as addressing, among others, Paul of Venice and Gregory of Rimini. In On Generation and Corruption, Aristotle describes growing as a process in which “any and every part of the growing magnitude is made bigger . by the accession of something, and thirdly in such a way that the growing thing is preserved and persists” (321a18–22).1 For instance, when an animal grows as the result of the intake of food, all of its limbs grow larger as the result of the intake of new matter, in such a way that the same individual animal persists throughout the process. 1 All Aristotle translations are taken from the Jonathan Barnes edition of the Complete Works. 1 Final version forthcoming in Journal of the History of Philosophy Simple though it may perhaps appear, this definition confronted Aristotle’s later followers and commentators with a problem.
    [Show full text]
  • James Ker-Lindsay Paper
    Preventing the Emergence of Self-Determination as a Norm of Secession: An Assessment of the Kosovo 'Unique Case' Argument James Ker-Lindsay London School of Economics European Institute, London School of Economics and Political Science, Houghton Street, London WC2A 2AE +44 20 7955 6815 (Tel) / +44 20 7955 6497 (fax) [email protected] Abstract When Kosovo declared independence, in February 2008, it was stated that the move was not an act of self-determination. Instead, the key states that supported the decision insisted that the case for statehood arose from a unique set of circumstances. Kosovo was not a precedent; it was a sui generis case in international politics. This article considers the arguments underpinning this claim to exclusivity and argues that, taken either individually or collectively, the main justifications used to support Kosovo‟s „unique‟ statehood – such as the abuse of human rights - in fact have serious consequences for other separatist conflicts elsewhere. Introduction On 19 December 2007, Sir John Sawers, the then permanent representative of the United Kingdom to the United Nations made one of the most extraordinary statements of modern British diplomacy. Emerging from a meeting of the Security Council, which had been discussing efforts to find a final status settlement for Kosovo, the diplomat stated: „You have the principle of territorial integrity. You also have the principle of self-determination. There are times when those principles are in tension with one another, and the principle of territorial integrity is qualified by the principle of self-determination.‟1 This was an astounding statement. A senior British official appeared to be contradicting the long- standing principle of international relations sanctifying the territorial integrity of states, and endorsing the right of a group of people, albeit under certain conditions, to pursue secession and independence.
    [Show full text]
  • The Aeolipile As Experimental Model in Early Modern Natural Philosophy
    7KH$HROLSLOHDV([SHULPHQWDO0RGHOLQ(DUO\0RGHUQ1DWXUDO3KLORVRSK\ &UDLJ0DUWLQ 3HUVSHFWLYHVRQ6FLHQFH9ROXPH1XPEHU0D\-XQHSS $UWLFOH 3XEOLVKHGE\7KH0,73UHVV )RUDGGLWLRQDOLQIRUPDWLRQDERXWWKLVDUWLFOH KWWSVPXVHMKXHGXDUWLFOH Access provided by Oakland University (22 Aug 2016 16:29 GMT) The Aeolipile as Experimental Model in Early Modern Natural Philosophy Craig Martin Oakland University What causes winds was regarded as one of the most difficult questions of early modern natural philosophy. Vitruvius, the ancient Roman architectural au- thor, put forth an alternative to Aristotle’s theory by likening the generation of wind to the actions of the aeolipile, which he believed made artificial winds. As Vitruvius’s work proliferated during the sixteenth and seventeenth centu- ries, numerous natural philosophers, including Descartes, used the aeolipile as a model for nature. Yet, interpretations of Vitruvius’s text and of the relation of the aeolipile to natural winds varied according to definitions and concep- tions of air, wind, rarefaction, condensation, and vapor. 1. Introduction Numerous early modern natural philosophers, Aristotelians as well as their detractors, invoked the workings of the aeolipile to explain the origin and matter of winds. An aeolipile, in its simplest form, is a hollow metal ball or vessel that has one or two small openings. An external fire, or other source of heat, warms water placed within the ball until jets of steam and air shoot forth from the aperture or apertures. From antiquity to the seventeenth century, natural philosophers referred to this artificial device as evidence for specific theories of the wind. These writings typically cited Vitruvius, the ancient Roman author of De architectura, who gave the earliest Prelimary versions of the paper were presented at seminars sponsored by the Department of History and Science and Technology at Johns Hopkins University and by the Graduate School Field Committee in Medieval and Early Modern Studies at the University of Maryland, College Park.
    [Show full text]
  • 1 This Translation of Book III Distinctions 1 to 17 of the Ordinatio (Aka Opus Oxoniense ) of Blessed John Duns Scotus Is Comple
    1 This translation of Book III Distinctions 1 to 17 of the Ordinatio (aka Opus Oxoniense) of Blessed John Duns Scotus is complete. These distinctions fill volume nine of the Vatican critical edition of the Latin text edited by the Scotus Commission in Rome and published by Quarrachi. [Note that distinctions 18 to 25 are lacking in Scotus’ Ordinatio. Their place is filled here in an appendix from Antonius Andreas, one of Scotus’ more faithful followers.] Scotus’ Latin is tight and not seldom elliptical, exploiting to the full the grammatical resources of the language to make his meaning clear (especially the backward references of his pronouns). In English this ellipsis must, for the sake of intelligibility, often be translated with a fuller repetition of words and phrases than Scotus himself gives. The possibility of mistake thus arises if the wrong word or phrase is chosen for repetition. The only check to remove error is to ensure that the resulting English makes the sense intended by Scotus. Whether this sense has always been captured in the translation that follows must be judged by the reader. In addition there are passages where not only the argumentation but the grammar too is obscure, and I cannot vouch for the success of my attempts to penetrate the obscurity. So, for these and the like reasons, comments and notice of errors from readers are most welcome. Peter L.P. Simpson April, 2018 2 THE ORDINATIO OF BLESSED JOHN DUNS SCOTUS Book Three First Distinction First Part (Page 12) On the Possibility of the Incarnation Question 1: Whether it was Possible for Human Nature to be United to the Word in Unity of Supposit Num.
    [Show full text]
  • Pietro Pomponazzi – the Most Representative Aristotelian of the Italian Renaissance
    188 PIETRO POMPONAZZI – THE MOST REPRESENTATIVE ARISTOTELIAN OF THE ITALIAN RENAISSANCE Anna MAKOLKIN1 ABSTRACT. In European cultural history, the name of Pietro Pomponazzi (1462-1525) is associated with the re-birth of the ancient pagan Graeco-Roman cultural legacy and the revival of the ancient natural philosophy, as well with the debate over the power of Man and God. He is also one of the most prominent neo-Aristotelians of the Renaissance who promoted Aristotle’s natural philosophy, contrasted with the thought of Plato, thus continuing the ongoing comparative analysis of Platonism and Aristotelianism. Pomponazzi who claimed that “a philosopher has to be a heretic” entered European cultural history as a truly radical thinker, having turned his advocacy of Aristotle into a weapon against the Church dogma, Mediaeval scholasticism, theological main arguments, and religion in general. The Renaissance neo-Aristotelianism is unthinkable without Pomponazzi’s battle for the materiality of cosmos and human body, without his denunciation of the immortality of the soul – the main premise of Christian ideology and mythology – that was going on nearly a100 years prior to the burning of Giordano Bruno. This paper brings to the surface of the current philosophical discourse this less known but an extremely significant Renaissance thinker, an alumnus of the University of Padua, “the cradle of Aristotelianism” during the High Renaissance. KEY WORDS: Aristotle, Aristotelianism, natural philosophy, organic essence, Faith, Reason, heresy, heretic, Plato(nism), immortality of the soul, religious myth, Cosmos Contents Introduction 1. Biography of a Heretic 2. Italy – the most Preserved Archive of Aristotelianism 3. Padua – Pomponazzi’s Alma Mater 4.
    [Show full text]
  • AELIANUS TACTICUS, Translated from the Greek Into Latin By
    AELIANUS TACTICUS, translated from the Greek into Latin by FRANCESCO ROBORTELLO and THEODORUS GAZA, Περὶ Στρατηγικῶν Τάξεων Ἑλληνικῶν [Latin translation: De militaribus ordinibus instituendis more græcorum and De instruendis aciebus], with a manuscript fragment of SIGEBERT OF GEMBLOUX [SIGEBERT GEMBLACENSIS], Chronica, and manuscript fragments from a Glossary and a Grammar In Latin (with some Greek), imprint on paper, with three manuscript fragments in Latin (with some Low German in one fragment) Venice, Andreas and Jacobus Spinellus, 1552 (imprint); Western Germany(?), c. 1140-60; Northwestern Germany(?), c. 1300-1350; Northwestern Germany(?), c. 1400-1450 In-4o format, preceded by one manuscript flyleaf (medieval fragment) and followed one paper flyleaf and two small manuscript flyleaves (both medieval fragments), printed [8 pp.], pp. 1-64, 73-77, [78], [24 pp.], incomplete (collation, sig. *4, A-G4, H4? [sig. H on outer sheet and sig. I ii on inner sheet, but with no disruption to pagination; a quire does appear to be lacking following this one, with loss of text], K3 [last leaf cancelled], A-C4), printed in Roman and Italic type, printer’s device on sig. K3 verso (U104 in EDIT16; see Online Resources), two engraved ornamental initials, numerous printed diagrams and tables, some of which incorporate woodcuts of soldiers alone or in formation, slight staining in the margins, some small losses to the outer edges of individual leaves, sig. K1 (pp. 73-74) is loose. Bound in sixteenth-century leather, blind-tooled with four concentric rectangular
    [Show full text]
  • Celinda, a Tragedy
    Celinda, A Tragedy VALERIA MIANI • Edited with an introduction by VALERIA FINUCCI Translated by JULIA KISACKY Annotated by VALERIA FINUCCI & JULIA KISACKY Iter Inc. Centre for Reformation and Renaissance Studies Toronto 2010 Iter: Gateway to the Middle Ages and Renaissance Tel: 416/978–7074 Fax: 416/978–1668 Email: [email protected] Web: www.itergateway.org CRRS Publications, Centre for Reformation and Renaissance Studies Victoria University in the University of Toronto Toronto, Ontario M5S 1K7 Canada Tel: 416/585–4465 Fax: 416/585–4430 Email: [email protected] Web: www.crrs.ca © 2010 Iter Inc. & the Centre for Reformation and Renaissance Studies All Rights Reserved Printed in Canada Iter and the Centre for Reformation and Renaissance Studies gratefully acknowledge the generous sup- port of the Gladys Krieble Delmas Foundation toward the publication of this book. Iter and the Centre for Reformation and Renaissance Studies gratefully acknowledge the generous sup- port of James E. Rabil, in memory of Scottie W. Rabil, toward the publication of this book. Library and Archives Canada Cataloguing in Publication Miani, Valeria Celinda : a tragedy / Valeria Miani ; edited and with an introduction by Valeria Finucci ; tranlated by Julia Kisacky ; annotated by Valeria Finucci & Julia Kisacky. (The other voice in early modern Europe : the Toronto series ; 8) Translation of the Italian play by the same title. Co-published by: Centre for Reformation and Renaissance Studies. Includes bibliographical references and index. Issued also in electronic format. Text in Italian with English translation on facing pages. ISBN 978–07727–2075–7 I. Finucci, Valeria II. Kisacky, Julia, 1965– III.
    [Show full text]
  • Virgil, Aeneid 11 (Pallas & Camilla) 1–224, 498–521, 532–96, 648–89, 725–835 G
    Virgil, Aeneid 11 (Pallas & Camilla) 1–224, 498–521, 532–96, 648–89, 725–835 G Latin text, study aids with vocabulary, and commentary ILDENHARD INGO GILDENHARD AND JOHN HENDERSON A dead boy (Pallas) and the death of a girl (Camilla) loom over the opening and the closing part of the eleventh book of the Aeneid. Following the savage slaughter in Aeneid 10, the AND book opens in a mournful mood as the warring parti es revisit yesterday’s killing fi elds to att end to their dead. One casualty in parti cular commands att enti on: Aeneas’ protégé H Pallas, killed and despoiled by Turnus in the previous book. His death plunges his father ENDERSON Evander and his surrogate father Aeneas into heart-rending despair – and helps set up the foundati onal act of sacrifi cial brutality that caps the poem, when Aeneas seeks to avenge Pallas by slaying Turnus in wrathful fury. Turnus’ departure from the living is prefi gured by that of his ally Camilla, a maiden schooled in the marti al arts, who sets the mold for warrior princesses such as Xena and Wonder Woman. In the fi nal third of Aeneid 11, she wreaks havoc not just on the batt lefi eld but on gender stereotypes and the conventi ons of the epic genre, before she too succumbs to a premature death. In the porti ons of the book selected for discussion here, Virgil off ers some of his most emoti ve (and disturbing) meditati ons on the tragic nature of human existence – but also knows how to lighten the mood with a bit of drag.
    [Show full text]
  • Sperone Speroni (1500-1588) and the Rebirth of Sophistry in the Italian Renaissance Call: H2020-MSCA-IF-2014 - Grant Number: 659644
    ASSEGNISTA : Teodoro Katinis TITOLO DEL PROGETTO DI RICERCA: Sperone Speroni (1500-1588) and the Rebirth of Sophistry in the Italian Renaissance Call: H2020-MSCA-IF-2014 - Grant number: 659644 PERIODO: era previsto un periodo di 24 mesi dal 01/09/2015 al 31/08/2017. NB: Il contratto è stato concluso prima, il 30/09/2016 dopo 13 mesi, essendo l’Assegnista stato assunto presso University of Ghent (Belgium) TUTOR: prof. Marco Sgarbi TIPOLOGIA DI ASSEGNO: MSCA-IF-2014 - Grant number: 659644 – CUP H72I15000550006 Breve presentazione del progetto: This two-year research project aimed to analyze the works of Sperone Speroni degli Alvarotti (Padua 1500–1588), his re-evaluation of ancient sophistic perspectives and his legacy in the early modern age. Speroni was one of the most important protagonists of the Renaissance debate on language and logic as well as civil and speculative philosophy. Educated as an Aristotelian, he eventually developed a distinctive philosophy and was the first to challenge Plato’s (327-447 BCE) condemnation of sophists. Despite the fact that Speroni was a central figure of Renaissance philosophy and literature in the vernacular, he is one of the most neglected authors in scholarly production. Furthermore, scholars have considered Speroni’s interest in ancient sophists as a marginal aspect of his philosophy and have disregarded the paramount role of the period’s vernacular writing on sophistry that began with his works and spread throughout sixteenth-century Italy. This project not only contributed to the research on vernacular Aristotelianism funded by an ERC Starting Grant 2013 (ARISTOTLE – 335949) and led by Marco Sgarbi but also filled the gap in international studies with a comprehensive analysis of the subject.
    [Show full text]
  • Justifying Religious Freedom: the Western Tradition
    Justifying Religious Freedom: The Western Tradition E. Gregory Wallace* Table of Contents I. THESIS: REDISCOVERING THE RELIGIOUS JUSTIFICATIONS FOR RELIGIOUS FREEDOM.......................................................... 488 II. THE ORIGINS OF RELIGIOUS FREEDOM IN EARLY CHRISTIAN THOUGHT ................................................................................... 495 A. Early Christian Views on Religious Toleration and Freedom.............................................................................. 495 1. Early Christian Teaching on Church and State............. 496 2. Persecution in the Early Roman Empire....................... 499 3. Tertullian’s Call for Religious Freedom ....................... 502 B. Christianity and Religious Freedom in the Constantinian Empire ................................................................................ 504 C. The Rise of Intolerance in Christendom ............................. 510 1. The Beginnings of Christian Intolerance ...................... 510 2. The Causes of Christian Intolerance ............................. 512 D. Opposition to State Persecution in Early Christendom...... 516 E. Augustine’s Theory of Persecution..................................... 518 F. Church-State Boundaries in Early Christendom................ 526 G. Emerging Principles of Religious Freedom........................ 528 III. THE PRESERVATION OF RELIGIOUS FREEDOM IN MEDIEVAL AND REFORMATION EUROPE...................................................... 530 A. Persecution and Opposition in the Medieval
    [Show full text]