<<

GENERAL THEMES UsingAlainBadiou’sEthicofto Supportan‘Eventful’Social TeacherEducationProgram KENTDENHEYER University of Alberta DIANECONRAD University of Alberta Personal-Professional Context of This Essay OTHRECENTLYPROMOTEDtotheranksofAssociateProfessorinaCanadianuniver sitywithalargeundergraduateteachereducationprogram,wearenonethelessambivalent aboutourtaskofeducatingteachers.Wewerecaught,ontheonehand,byourexperiencesof teaching (let alone teaching teachers) as an impossible profession (Freud, 1937/1968); on the ,byourpersistentfaiththateducationstillhassomethingtocontributetoimproveshared socialandmateriallives(howevervariouslydefined).Ourlivedexperiencesasteachereducators fell,however,decidedlyshortofourexpectationsforwhatteachereducationcouldbe.Beyond ourownambivalence,moreover,wefeltthereweresignificantflawswiththeprograminwhich wetaught.Wewerenotaloneinourdiscontent. Withanexistingprogramstructuremorethantwodecadesold,ourFacultyresolvedtoen gageinacomprehensiveprogramreview.Throughfacultyconsultationandresearch,acommit tee devised a set of five foundational principles for our teacher education program. These principles became a framework to guide program revision. To promotea degree of coherence across departments, however, we felt these principles also needed an explicit purpose. For example, one of the principles concerning scholarship states that current research should be consistentlyrepresentedinundergraduatecourses.Butwhatcurrentresearchgiventhevolumeof workyearlyproduced?Eagertocontributetothepossibilityofpositivechangepresentedbythe opportunityofaprogramreview,weproposedthat“socialjustice”couldprovideaworthwhile purpose for the program and guide its principles while also giving integrity to our roles as teachereducators.Topromotethisidea,wecreatedapresentationforourFacultycolleagues.

Journal of Curriculum Theorizing ♦Volume27,Number1,2011 7 denHeyer&Conrad ♦UsingAlainBadiou’sEthicofTruths

Webeganbyexploringwhatasocialjusticeorientationtoteachereducationmightentail. Wedevelopedarationaleforsocialjusticeas a focusforteacher educationandexplicatedits possible definitions and models by drawing on relevant research related explicitly to social justice in addition to work in curriculum theory and philosophy. From this scholarship, we developedathesis.Asweaddressinthisessay,socialjusticeeducationusesthematterof particularcoursesasameanstoexaminethewaysinwhichournexusofprivilegeandignorance bothcontributestoandemergesfrombroaderstrugglesoverpurposesandidentificationsaround which cultural practices (such as education) coalesce. As explored, this privilegeignorance nexus constitutes an educational site for the possibility of an “” and subsequent “ processes”(Badiou,2001)thatisinitselfaneducationinitsmosthonorificsense. Ourthesiswasmetwithseveralobjectionsfromcolleagues.Theterm“socialjustice”itself wascontestedasanemptysignifierdevoidofdisciplinarycontent.Themultipletypesorexpres sionsofjustice(seeforexample,Fraser,1997;Gerwitz,2006)andtheparticularitiesofvarious contextsandconditionswereseenasobstacles.Somecolleaguesviewedsocialjusticeasfitting only with a “leftist” political agenda. There were also concerns for students’ discomfort with such a focus as it requires grappling with “difficult knowledge” (Britzman, 1998). Another objectionemergedfromtheperceptionthatsocialjusticeadvocatescritiqueexistingconditions withoutofferinganypositivealternatives.ThoughneverseriouslyconsideredbyourFaculty,we further develop our proposal here with our colleagues’objectionsinmindandreturntothose objectionsinthefinalsectionofthisessay. Asinourpresentation,wetakeupsocialjusticeinthisessayasacurriculumissueincontrast to,forexample,advocatingforaspecificsocialjusticecourseorasaquestionrelatedtoparticu lar topics (as relates to a range of topics such as urban education, masculinities, or disability studies;seeforexample,essayscollectedinAyers,Quinn&Stovall,2009).Whilewerecognize theimportanceofcontextandspecifics,wealsoseeanequalneedforatheorizationofsocial justiceasamoregeneralcurricularquestionofknowledge,knowing,andthosestudentsubjec tivities we as educators presume to teach. Such theorizations must both traverse particular contexts and provide categories that allow people in differing contexts to see themselves as implicated. Thereareseveraldangerstotryandavoidinthinkingthroughsocialjusticeeducation.One liesinthedangerthatsocialjusticeitselfbecomesanothermastersignifierthatiseitherideologi callyclosedtodiverseparticularitiesofcontextor,alternatively,asanemptysignifier,simplya rhetoricalappealtosomething‘good’(Bracher,1993).Wemustalsotakecaretoavoidthesetup ofschoolsandthoseinthemasresponsibleforcreatingbettersocialfutures.Theillogicofthis formulation has been well argued elsewhere (see for example, Britzman, 1991; Pinar, 2004). Finally, there is an obvious danger in insufficiently disagreeable to reigning doxa. As relatestocurriculumtheorization,weinterpret,,orappealstoanOtherasthe categoriesofandjusticedominatingcurriculumtheorizingasunderstoodinpostmodern, hermeneutic,andDeweyianpragmaticorientationsalongwithadvocaciesforcurriculuminclu sionsbasedoncommunitarianfiliations(e.g.,multiculturaleducation).Weturnnowtoatheori zationofsocialjusticethatwehopeavoidsthesedangers. The Privilege-Ignorance Nexus Wedefinesocialjusticeasthepublicactofchallengingpersonalandstructuralprivilegeasit manifestsinourclassrooms,personallives,andtheformalpoliticalsitesofourvariouscollec

Journal of Curriculum Theorizing ♦Volume27,Number1,2011 8 denHeyer&Conrad ♦UsingAlainBadiou’sEthicofTruths tiveconstituencies. Privilegeinourdiscussionbelowrefersveryspecificallytobothissuesand peopleaboutwhichoneisignorantoraboutwhichonebelievesthereisnoneedtobeconcerned (seealsoCarr&Lund,2007;McIntosh,2008;Tisdell,1993;Wildman&Davis,2000).Social justiceworksagainsttheprivilegethatisourignorance. Aswithidentifications,thenexusofprivilegeignoranceismultifaceted—situated,historical, andcontingent—withdifferentaspectsofourprivilegeanddisadvantageinvokeddependingon context.Therefore,teachercandidates,likeeachoftheirinstructors,havetheirowninstantiations ofprivilegeignorancetoinvestigateandchallenge. Aswithotherscholarsineducation(Bracher,1993;Britzman,1991,1998;Felman,1987; Taubman,2006),weuseignoranceinthepsychoanalyticsenseoftheword.Inthiswork,igno rance differs from, for example, being rude or unaware of something. Psychoanalytic theory positsthatweactivelychoose—indeed,haveapassionfor—ourignorance.Fromthisperspec tive, people avoid that which challenges cherished visions or ideals and or implicates us as agentsdirectlyinvolvedinandbenefitingfrom,albeitinunequalways,themanyhorrorsofthe present that privilege saves us from experiencing daily. Ignorance then is the shadow side of knowledgeaseachconstituteafamiliarsubjectivityandidentificationwhosesecurityrequires thatwecontinuouslystrivetostrikeabalanceofproximityanddistancetodifficultissues.A passionforignoranceemergesfromandservestoreinforcethesefamiliarities. Ignorance is neither innocent or accidental, nor does it reside solely in individuals. It is shaped rather through the institutionalization of our sensibilities and intelligibilities (Simon, 2005). Institutions (e.g., schools, textbooks, corporate media, museums) not only provide contentforourknowing,butshapeouremotionalresistancetounknowingaswell.Aswiththe ‘official’ knowledge found in programs of study resulting from and contributing to struggles overculturalpractices,ignoranceandresistanceservesomegroups’interestsattheexpenseof others’(Apple,2000).Being educated doesnotmean,therefore,simplyhavingachievedknowl edgeortheabilitytodosomething.Tobeeducatedisalsotohavesimultaneouslyacquireda somewhatpredictableignorancealongwithanemotionaltendencytoavoidissuesthatdonot conformtothe“instantaneousuptake”(Aoki,2000,p.354)ofourimmediateunderstandings; thatis,issues,people,andorbehavioursthatdefyoureffortstoimmediatelyapprehendthem (andaboutwhichwetherebyoftenbecomeapprehensive). InAlberta,forexample,manyteachersandteachercandidatesareexperiencingstressabouta newK12socialstudiesprogramthatrequiresteachingthestoryofCanadaandAlbertafrom AboriginalandFrancophoneperspectives.Theseperspectivesaretobeaddedtothedominant AngloCanadianhistoricalandnationalistnarrativeunnamedintheprogrambutfromandabout whichcontentfortheprovincialstandardizedtestisdrawn.Settingasidethefactthatthereisno singularperspectiveforeithergroupnowaddedintheprogram,thestressisunderstandable.As successfulstudents,thevastmajorityofteachercandidates (andtheirinstructors) areignorant about any perspective these communities themselves offer. This is the case despite the easy availabilityofimmenseresourcesintermsofbooks,people,courses,exhibitions,andsoonfrom whichonecouldlearn. Thechallengehereisnotoneofsimplyinformation.Issuesrelated,forexample,toAbori ginalAlbertaelicitdifficultemotionsthatreflectacoloniallegacy,ongoinglanddisputes(in cludinglandfromwhichgreatoilandgaswealthiscurrentlybeingextracted),andmaterialand symbolic divisions at the heart of the Canadian nationalist project. As Daniel Francis (1992, 1997) points out, most nonAboriginal Canadians—including those who arrive in our teacher education classrooms—posses inherited information about an “imaginary Indian” (Francis,

Journal of Curriculum Theorizing ♦Volume27,Number1,2011 9 denHeyer&Conrad ♦UsingAlainBadiou’sEthicofTruths

1992).Thisimaginaryisreflectedandreinforcedinmainstreammediawhenthechallengesthat many Aboriginal communities face are reduced to discussions about their “specialprivileges” (e.g.,statusmembersofFirstNationsdonotpayfederaltaxes)orclaimsthat their culturesof poverty create cycles of failure. 1 Usually unaddressed in such discussions are the ways their povertyprovidesthefoundationof our wealth.Alsocommonlyignoredaretheeducatingforces that produce the predictable nonAboriginal transCanadian imaginary of the Indian (Francis, 1992;seealsoTupper&Cappello,2008).Thisdivisionandstressexemplifythewaysinwhich privilegeignorance is, on the one hand, personal and emotive, while on the other, socially institutionally shaped. Unsurprisingly, therefore, we encounter a strong resistance from many teachercandidatestoquestionsaboutwhatnonAboriginalCanadiansmightpossiblylearnfrom investigating either that which their privilege allows them to ignore (i.e., from where their “imaginaryIndian”comesandwhoseinterestsitserves)orwhatwecanlearnfromAboriginal epistemologiesandexperiencesontermsthatdifferfromwhatourprivilegeallowsustoset. Takingupandlearningfromdifferentformsofresistanceinthespaceofteachereducation requiresaconcertedandsharedefforttoengageourownshadowsasteachereducators: Lackingininsightintotheego’sdefencemechanismsofdenial,rationalization,projec tionandsoforth,teachereducationispoorlyequippedtohelpstudentteacherslearnfrom theinevitableresistancestodifficultknowledge.(Carson,2007,p.3) Thekeypointinthisdiscussiontoemphasizeisthenecessitytolearnfromknowledgeal readypossessedandtolearnfromresistancetoquestions,issues,oralternativeperspectivesthat potentiallyputatriskwhat(andonwhatbasis)wecanclaimtoknow.Toengagethesespacesat theheartofourprivilegeignorancenexusisnotonlyaquestionofsocialjustice.Suchencoun terswithwhatwehavetheprivilegetoignore(andtheattendantstressinvolved)maybeapre conditionforlearningitself(Britzman,1991).Thisisespeciallysoifwethinkofbothjusticeand learningasanethicaljourneyratherthanachievementoracquisitionofapredeterminedthing (beitinformationorskill).WenowturntoengageBadiou’s(2000,2001,2003)articulationof an ethic of truths asanethicalbasisuponwhichwemightengagelearningandsocialjusticeas justsuchanuncertainjourney. Badiou and an Ethical Subjectivity of Truths Badiou(2000)interpretseducationin generalasnever having meant more than this: “or ganiz[ing]knowledgetotheextentthatacertaintruthcanbreakthrough”(p.17).Fromwhere doesatruthbreakthrough?AccordingtoBadiou’sformulation,atruthemergesfromthe“void” attheheartofall“situations”or“states”ofbeing,fromaripinthetissueof“opinions”(received knowledge) under which we take shelter from the void’s foreboding infinity (Badiou, 2001). Relatedinourdiscussionabove,onesitewhereteachersandstudentspotentiallyencounterthis voidistheirprivilegeignorancenexus. Badiou’s(2001)firstphilosophicalassertionisthattruthoughttobetheprimarycategoryof philosophyandthatethics,incontrasttoitsconcernwith“abstractcategories,(ManorHuman, RightorLaw,theOther…),shouldbereferredbacktoparticular situations ”(p.3).Bysituations Badiou names those concentrically overlapping social territories through which we gain an identityandorientationtowardstheworld.TheseinfluentialsitesrangefromfamilytoStateto

Journal of Curriculum Theorizing ♦Volume27,Number1,2011 10 denHeyer&Conrad ♦UsingAlainBadiou’sEthicofTruths economicrelationswherewelearntoact,desire,anddreamappropriatelyoridentifyourselves asbelongingtoonebutnotanothergrouping. Badiouarguesthatwhenthecontemporarysituationofphilosophy(postmodernandherme neuticorientationsbeinghisfavoritetarget)abandonedtruthandelevatedastheobject ofitsinquiry,itcouldnolongernameorsupportanagentintheworldtomilitateforjustice.Ina complementaryrole,thedecontextualized“bestpractices”thatexemplifytheAngloAmerican modernisteducationprojectassumeanoverlyindividualizedandcognitiveapproachtothethose subjectivitieswepresumetoteach(seeforexample,thefocuson“disciplinaryhabitsofmind”in Gardner,1999;MansillaandGardner,2008).ExtendingBadiou’spoint,wearguethatneither thedisciplinarybestpracticesorientationnorpostmoderninspirededucationadequatelyaccounts forpeople’sadventuroussubjectivityortheircapacitytoaffirmativelyinventnewsocialsitua tions.Thefirstchoosestoignorethecreativeenergiesofasubject’semotionalandimaginative fluiditywhileforthelatterthesubjectisprimarily the shadowy effect of discourses ruled by interlockingregimesofpreexistingpower.Eachisthemirrorimageoftheother.Theirargu ments rest on a mutually supporting logic of studenthuman deficit on the one hand and the philosophical abandonment of human inventive creativity on the other. To reclaim a more affirmativeethics,Badiou(2003)articulatesanethicoftruthspremisedon“thestrong,simple ideathateveryexistencecanonedaybesizedbywhathappenstoitandsubsequentlydevote itselftothatwhichisvalidforall…”(p.66). ForBadiou,truths—or,rather,generic“truthprocesses”—lackprespecifiedcontent(asar ticulatedbyanynumberofreligiousorders)ordestinationaswith,forexample,a‘scientific’ Marxistinterpretationofhistory.Thisinterpretationoftruthsisalsounrelatedtoanycommuni tarian identification. Rather, truths consist of the material traces that a “becoming subject” producesinfidelitytoauniqueandsingulartruthprocessinstigatedbyan“event.”Suchmate rialtracesconsistofspeechacts,art,socialmovements,orindeedanyconfigurationandaffirma tionofthoughtthatthinksthesituationfromtheperspectiveoftheevent.Itisforthesetruth processes instigated by an event that Badiou arguesethics andphilosophy—and,weassert,a justiceorientedteachereducation—mustlendsupport. Thestatusofan“event”is,ofcourse,amatterofmuchphilosophicaldebate.AsMariam Fraser(2006)writes, asaphilosophicalconcept,[anevent]existsinrelationtoaspecificsetofproblems,in cludingtheproblemofhowtoconceiveofmodesofindividuationthatpertainnottobe ing,ortoessencesandrepresentation,buttobecomingandeffectivity.(p.129) For Badiou, events and subsequent truthprocess potentially occur in four fields of human endeavor—politics,science,art,andlove(Badiou,2001,2003).Tothisweadd‘education’asa fifthfieldwhereaneventcanoccurif,and,wheneducatorsarrangetheircoursestoengagethe privilegeignorance nexus. Love, however, provides perhaps the most poignant and familiar exampleofBadiou’snotionofan“event”and“truthprocess.” Allloversaresimultaneouslysubjecttoboththeparticularandtheuniversal.Alllovers— however particular the people and the circumstances—are “becoming subject” to an event— falling in love—that is also universal in that loveas“event” respects no preset rules, pre existing identities or differences, and as we must assume, is potentially available to all. In additiontootherimplications,encounteringaneventsuchaslovesubtractsfrom(or“pierces”a holein)whatonethoughttobethecaseofone'ssituation. This subtraction also creates the

Journal of Curriculum Theorizing ♦Volume27,Number1,2011 11 denHeyer&Conrad ♦UsingAlainBadiou’sEthicofTruths possibilityofasupplementoradditionweenactinbecomingmorethanthe‘one’wethought (were‘opinionated’)wewere.Itisinthissensethata“becomingsubject”isacollectivesubjec tivity—between lovers, between artist and observer, between the works of scientists, teachers andstudents—whosecontinuanceisentirelydependentonafidelitytotheevent.Badiou’sis alsonotanargumentforenlightened“freewill”orforanthatisfullyinchargeof itself. As with love, the unpredictable occurrence and implications of an “event” mock such assertions. Thetaskoffidelityrequiresadiscipline,fortowhatthesubjectistoremainfaithfulnolong erexists.Inotherwords,thewholeofthe“event”(the‘falling’thatisaneventinthefieldof love,a‘voiding’oftheknownbythenotknowninthefieldforeducation)consistsofitsdisap pearing: “But this disappearing […] is also the occasion of a ‘radical power of affirmation’ insofar as it ‘bequeaths the imperative to weave a truth’ from its ” (Badiou as cited in Hallward, 2005,p.18). Inshort,aneventoccasions a possibility for a becoming subject to weaveatruthprocesswhosecontentorfinalformcanneverbepredeterminedorcontrolled. Shakespeare provides a classic example of an “event”ful subtraction from—and possible supplementationof—theidentitybasedformulationsofloyaltythatconstitutedthesituationin Romeo & Juliet .Thetragedyconveyedinthisstoryresultsnotfromthelovers’fidelitytotheir trutheventoflove,buttheadultrefusalorinabilitytoseebeyondtheirownlimitedinterests defined by “Montagues” and “Capulets.” Under the flags of their proper nouns, the situation dominatedbypatriarchalopiniondestroyedthatwhichmadetheyoungmosthuman,humane, andbecoming.Aswiththisclassiccase,allloversconstitutea“becomingsubject”byembody ingadisinterestedinterestininheritedopinions: I cannot,withinthe fidelitytofidelitythatdefines ethical consistency [of, and, to, an eventandsubsequenttruthprocess]takeaninterestinmyself,andthuspursuemyown interests. All my capacity for interest, which is my own perseverance in being, has pouredoutintothefutureconsequencesofthesolutiontothisscientificproblem,intothe examinationoftheworldinthelightoflove'sbeingtwo,intowhatIwillmakeofmy encounter, one night, with the eternal Hamlet, or into the next stage of the political process,oncethegatheringinfrontofthefactoryhasdispersed(Badiou,2001,p.50). More directly related to education, we might add ‘what I thought was my commitment to or understanding about (e.g., education policy, history, mathematics, art, critical thinking) is not onlynotmineatallbutpossiblycontributestotheproblemIseektoalleviate.’Or,moresimply, “I had/have no idea.” We can describe these moments in many ways, such as a moment of “biographicalcrises”(Britzman,1991,p.8)orasapiercingofthe“fictionalassemblages”by whichweorganize“aselfrepresentation”(Badiou,2001,p.55). 2Howeverdescribed,encounter ingthiseventweareconfrontedwiththequestion and task of “fidelity” which is where, for Badiou,theethicoftruthsbegins:“Acrisisoffidelityisalwayswhatputstothetest,following thecollapseofanimage,thesolemaximofconsistency(andthusethics):Keepgoing!”(Badiou, 2001,p.36).Badiou(2001)believes: Thereisalwaysonlyonequestionintheethicoftruths:howwillI,assomeone,continue toexceedmyownbeing?HowwillIlinkthethingsIknow,inaconsistentfashion,via theeffectsofbeingseizedbythenotknown?(p.50)

Journal of Curriculum Theorizing ♦Volume27,Number1,2011 12 denHeyer&Conrad ♦UsingAlainBadiou’sEthicofTruths

Theproperverbtense,therefore,withBadiou’seventandtruthprocessisneitherthepresentnor the past, but rather the future anterior. In essence, by maintaining fidelity to articulating the implicationsoftheeventinaconsistentfashion,a“becomingsubject”declares“thiswillhave beentrue”pursuingexactly“whatitwillbeabsurd not tohavebelieved”[italicsadded](Gibson, 2006,p.88). Encouraginghisethicalmaximof“keepgoing!”Badiouwarnsagainstthe“Evil”(translated fromhisterminFrench,“leMal”)madesimultaneouslypossibleonlybecauseofhumanpoten tialtoengageinthe“Good”oftruthprocesses(Badiou,2001).ForBadiou,leMal/Evilcomesin three forms: (of an event and truthprocess) /terror , or embracing a teleological fantasyofanexistingsituation’spromisedfulfillmentratherthanourrelationshiptothevoidat theheartofallsituations; betrayal ,whichistoeithergiveuponatruthprocessortomistake one’struthprocessforTruth;and disaster ,when,mistakingthecontentproducedbyasingular truthprocess for the Truth, Truth justifies the destruction of the material conditions people requiretopotentiallyenacttheirtruthprocessesor terrorizes themintosilence.Obviously,both presentandpastarefullofexamplesoftruthinventionsdistortedintosituationsof“disaster”and “terror.”ForBadiou,theethicalresponseisnottodenyorabandontheaffirmativehumanGood thatisatruthprocess,butthenecessityforvigilanceagainstthedistortionofthisGoodthatis Evil. Fromthisformulationofethicsitfollowsthenthatthepropersubjectofteachers’workisnot primarilyhistory,languagearts,mathematics,orabestpracticesapproachtoteachereducation; itis,rather,a“becomingsubject”whosediscipline is called forth by an event that renders as insufficienttheinheritedopinionsthatshapeourprivilegeignorancenexus.Asrelatestoteacher educationassocialjusticework,thisnexusexistsincoursesthatrangefromeducationalpolicy tosubjectmethodtoooftenrestingonunexaminedopinionsthatsustaintheenterpriseas‘just thewayitis’:thatpubliceducationis,forexample, a meritocracy or that individual courses shouldbeconcernedsimplywiththetransferenceofopinionratherthanturnattentiontothevoid attheheartofanysubject’sorganizationofignorance. FollowingBadiou’sethic,thecontentofthesecourseswouldbeorganizedsoastoencounter thatvoidwhichisaspacewithoutnameattheheartofapredictableignorancethatsustainswhat it is we claim to know, “organiz[ing] knowledge to the extent that a certain truth can break through.”Wecanreworkthisexhortationmoremildlyintheformofaquestion:Whatcanwe learnaboutteachingfromrereadingbothwhatandhowwehavebeentaughtabouteducation, policy,disciplines,Aboriginalperspectives,ourselvesandsoon(denHeyer,2009a)?Inorganiz ingcoursesaroundsuchrereadingsofthatwhichourprivilegeallowsustoignore,wemight encounteranevent. 3 Itisaspossible,ofcourse,toplananeventasitistoschedulewhenonefallsinlove—afact attheheartofeducationasamostimpossibleprofession.However,likelove,organizingcurricu lumforatruthtobreakthroughhonoursa“truthofhumanaspirationanddreaming”(Smith, 2000,p.18)asbecomingsubjectsstruggletolink theknowntotheunknowninaconsistent fashionwhilemaintainingvigilanceagainstthedistortionofthisgoodthatis“leMal.” Badiou’s formulationtherebytraversestwodangersinthinking aboutsocialjustice—avoidingaclosed readingofasituationinwhichaparticularinspirationofjustice(e.g.,Marxistderivedcritical theory) forecloses alternative articulations, and, avoiding a vision of justice as an unsituated ethicalidealismthatconstitutesnothingmoresubstantial than a empty signifier of something ‘good’forotherwiseunjustifiablesituations. 4Wenowturntobeingmoreexplicitlydisagreeable toreigningdoxa.

Journal of Curriculum Theorizing ♦Volume27,Number1,2011 13 denHeyer&Conrad ♦UsingAlainBadiou’sEthicofTruths

Badiou’sethicoftruthsstandsquitedistinctfromcallsforjusticepremisedonadefenseof difference, alterity, or for a phantasmal Other. In contrast, Badiou’s suturing of ethics to the subjectivityofa“becomingsubject”ispremisedonanofthe‘‘withoutone’’atthe heartofallsituations:‘‘Themultiple‘withoutone’—every multiple being in its turn nothing otherthanamultipleofmultiples—isthelawofbeing.Theonlystoppingpointisthevoid’’ (Badiou,2001,p.25).ExtrapolatingfromthisformulationleadsBadioutoconcludethat‘‘there are as many differences, say, between a Chinese peasant and a Norwegian professional as betweenmyselfandanybodyatall,includingmyself’’(p.26).Assuch,whereall,ontologically speaking, is difference then difference is of no significance at all to an ethics or education concernedwithjustice:‘‘Sincedifferencesarewhatthereis,andsinceeverytruthisthecoming tobeofthatwhichisnotyet,sodifferencesthen are precisely what truths depose, or render insignificant’’(p.27).Theproperobjectofethical and justiceoriented analysis then is not a defenseofdifferencebutasituationthatdeniesdifferenceasanontologicalrealityandignores truthprocessesasabecominghumanendeavor. Despitetheinsignificanceofdifferenceasanobjectofethicsorjustice,clearlybothcontem porarypoliticsandcurriculumareorganizedaroundtheforcefulexclusionofdifference(seefor example,Apple,2000;Donald,2009;Stanley,1998).Weargue,however,thatthissituationof exclusionsuffersnothreatfrommulticulturalcallsforjusticepremisedonthevery“opinions” quacategories(e.g., racethinking)thatthestatusquoitselfusestojustifyitsexistence.Like wise,wearguethatpostmodernorientationstojusticeoffernothingmorethanthe(ontologically) obviouswhencontenttoaffirm—whiledulyabandoning any collective cause—the fluidity of language’s trickster nature, power’s disciplining of language/body/gesture, or the arbitrary collationofelementsorcharacteristicsbywhichastatecountsasanensembleof‘one’ofthose whobelongandanotheras‘one’whodoesnot.Rather,adistinctionisrequiredbetweencallsfor justicethatseekgreaterinclusioninsituationspremisedonhierarchyandexclusionandcallsthat bothgeneralizetheclaimagainsthierarchyandexclusionandparticularizetheireverylimitation of“event”ualpossibilities.Thisisacrucialclaimtorecognize. Toreturntoarelevantexample,AboriginalandFrancophoneperspectivesarenowincluded intheprogramofsocialstudiesinAlberta.Wenowhaveamore‘inclusivecurriculum.’Yet,to whattheyaretobeaddedasadditionalperspectivesremainsunnamed.Thisunnamedperspec tiveisthenormand,likeallexamplesofthetype,manifestsitsprivilegeinitsinvisibility;a perspectivethatrequiresnonamebuttowhichthelegitimacyofothers(beyondacadreoffellow travelers) must make an appeal to be heard or considered.Withoutattendingtotheprivilege ignorancenexus—thatis,toexamineandnameboththecontentandsourcesofwhatonealready knowsorknowsbutdoesnotrecognizeasimplicatedinsocialstrugglesoverwhoweareand will become—keeps Aboriginal or any other perspective as an addon, a surface engagement withoutreflection.Toengageourprivilegeignorancenexus,incontrast,is tohelpCanadiansrealizethattheirformaleducationandsocializationhas,bothsubtly andovertly,presentedthemwithatheoryofIndigenousnessthathasshapedandcondi tionedtheirabilitytorespondtoAboriginalpresence and participation encountered in theirdailylives.(Donald,2009,p.38) Thisnexusthenisthesourcefromwhichtwocrucialandrelatedjusticegoalsemerge.First, aconsiderationofwhatourprivilegeallowsustoignorepotentiallysupplementsthetermsin whichanyalternativeperspectiveswillbecast,viewedasreasonableorashavingsomethingto

Journal of Curriculum Theorizing ♦Volume27,Number1,2011 14 denHeyer&Conrad ♦UsingAlainBadiou’sEthicofTruths learn from ratherthan about (Felman,1987,p.74).Second,thisnexusisasiteofpotentialevents andsubsequenttruthprocessesforteachersandstudentstoconsider‘whatis’aswepursue‘what mightbecome’“validforall”asrelatestoboththeparticularanduniversalofourpersonaland socialsituation. Inthisformulationoftheenterprise,educationispremisedonanofequality,equality ofhumancapacitiesforbecoming,truths,andfidelity.Thispositionstandsstarklyincontrastto the deficitreasoning underwriting contemporary enactments of education premised on the transferof“thething”(beitinformation,opinion,skillsordisposition)fromonepresumedto possesstoonepresumedtobelacking(Aoki,2002,p.30;Freire,1970).Inadditiontobeingill founded,thisratherarbitraryandselfservingpresumption(afterall,whendoesanyoneknow enoughofanything)servesonlytorecreatetheunjustconditionsofschoolingmanyeducators appoint themselves to solve with more schooling, better curricula, more research, and so on (Apple,2008). Forexample,readersofthisjournalarewellawareoftheharmofarbitrarilyassigneddiffer ences by which access to material and social resources is regulated. Why, then, continue to providesustenanceinourteachingandresearchtotheverysamecategoriesthatservetofurther objectifyintoabstractedsociologicalcategoriesthosealreadyobjectifiedanddiscountedbythe situation?Wecouldstartatthevoidattheheartoftheformaleducationprojectandourprivi legedinvestmentsinit.Onlyaneducationandresearchprogramthatbeginswiththepremiseof anactuallyalreadyexistingequalityofall—ofcapacityforlove,learning,becoming,andtruth— canwe“void”theselfservingandentwinedlogicsofdeficitreasoningandtheabandonmentof creativehumancapacitiesattheheartofcontemporaryformsofmainstreamformaleducation. A Summation of the Argument and Response to Objections In articulating the arguments above, we have attempted to negotiate several insights that emergedinourreviewofthesocialjusticeliterature:(a)Avoidreplacingonemastersignifier with another, including the term social justice itself (Bracher, 1993, 2002); (b)Attend to the particular contexts created through the interactions between people and affecting conditions (Gerwitz,2006);(c)Recognizethattherearemultipletypesorformsofjustice(Fraser,1997); and(d)Considerinstructionalconversationsasmomentsofpraxisopentoaneventthatcallsfor fidelitytoatruthprocess.Thus,althoughitisalwaysparticulartoinstructorsandstudents,who, amongstotherconditions,togethercreateacontext,wearguethattheprivilegeignorancenexus shouldbeacentralsubjectofstudythatweusethedifferingcontentofcoursestoaddress.This requireswebeginwiththequestionofwhetherourcurriculalimitorpromotethepossibilitiesof aneventful“becomingsubject.”Wenowreturntosomeoftheobjectionsraisedtothiscall. Oneobjectionisthatsocialjusticeisacoverstoryfora‘leftist’politicalagenda.Although socialjusticecommitmentsmostdefinitelyhavepoliticalimplications,webelievethatitdoesnot belongexclusivelytoanysinglepoliticalpartyorpoliticalleaning.Despite(Canadian)associa tionswiththepoliticalleft,everypoliticalpartyinvokessocialjusticerationalesastheyhavefor centuries. Today, for example, Canada’s ruling federal Conservative party justifies military intervention in as a social justice mission wherein the death, disfiguration, and destruction(“collateraldamage”)toparticularpeopleinparticularplacesmustbeoverlookedas an unfortunate but somewhat unavoidable cost of doing such justice work. Likewise, past Canadian and religious orders have couched the need for Indian Residential

Journal of Curriculum Theorizing ♦Volume27,Number1,2011 15 denHeyer&Conrad ♦UsingAlainBadiou’sEthicofTruths

Schoolsinresonateterms.Thus,manydifferentpoliticalcampsinvokesocialjusticeasapur posetoframetheirpoliciesandactions.Astheseexamplesillustrate,werequireadefinitionof socialjusticethatisfirstandforemostsituatedwhilealsoabletotraversediversecontexts.The definitionofsocialjusticethatweofferis:“Thepublicactofchallengingpersonalandstructural privilege as it manifests in our classrooms, personal lives, and formal political sites of our variouscollectiveconstituencies.”FollowingourreviewofBadiou’sethicalsubjectivity,tothis definitionwenowadd“soastoremoveparticularlimitationstoallpeople’scapacityfortruth processes.” Anotherobjectiontosocialjusticeasananimatingpurposeforteachereducationconcerns students’reactions.Ofcourse,weshouldexpectdiscomfortandresistancefromallwhograpple withthe“difficultknowledge”(Britzman,1998)involvedinanencounterwiththeirprivilege ignorancenexus.Thereis,andthisshouldbemadeexplicitacrossourprograms,nosalveforthe difficultgrapplinginvolvedinlearning.AsBracher(2002)notes,thisengagement“isfraught withmultipleobstacles,mostnotablythepresence,inallpartiesconcerned,ofidentitycompo nentsanddesirescontrarytothosemotivatinganddirectingtheeducationalenterprise”(p.93). Brachersuggeststhatsuchresistanceissymptomaticofpeople’sdesire/needtoprotecttheir always vulnerable identities and commitments. Badiou’s articulationof theneed forethicsto supportfidelitiestotruthprocessesencouragesalltofaceuptotheresistancesthatareinvitation to move beyond one’s “perseverance in being” within the categories of inherited opinions to “becomingsubject”toourlearninglives. Afinalchallengetoaddressliesintheperceptionthatsocialjusticecritiquesexistingcondi tionswithoutofferinganypositivealternatives.Onthecontrary,thesocialjusticeorientationfor whichweadvocateseekstoaffirmeveryone’spotentialtofallinloveortobecaughtupalong withanotherinanintractableproblemasaresultofencounteringthevoidattheheartofour privilegeignorance nexus. Through these relationships we enact our inventive capacities for “truthprocesses” by which every collective present is supplemented with the potential for somethingnew.The goalisclear:topromotethecapacity of all to affirmatively invent new situations so as to potentially live a better, more humane, and socially just future (variously defined).Wespeakhereofthefuturenotasaprediction,hope,orplaceofprojectedfantasy. Rather,itisacontingentandalwaysalreadytimespacewhoserealityrequiresofusanethicof thefutureanterior:thatis,thatwemaintainfidelityenoughtoliveitspreferablemanifestationas ifitalreadyexists.Indeed,thisisthestancewehavemaintainedinourowncoursesandwith colleaguesaswecontinuetomakethecaseforsocialjusticeinthefaceofobjections,resistance, andinertia. About the Authors KentdenHeyerisanAssociateProfessorofsocialstudieseducationandcurriculumtheory intheDepartmentofSecondaryEducationattheUniversityofAlbert.Hisrecentpublishedwork examinestheintersectionsinhistoricalconsciousnessofEmpirelogicsandtruthprocessesas articulatedintheworkofAlainBadiou,appearinginEducationalTheory,CurriculumInquiry and,aseditor,ThinkingEducationThroughAlainBadiou,WileyBlackwell. Diane Conrad is Associate Professor in Secondary Education at the University of Alberta. Sheteachesandresearchesintheareasofdrama/theatreeducation,appliedtheatre,atriskyouth, curriculumstudies,participatoryandartsbasedresearch.RecentpublicationsincludeInSearch

Journal of Curriculum Theorizing ♦Volume27,Number1,2011 16 denHeyer&Conrad ♦UsingAlainBadiou’sEthicofTruths of the Radical in Performance in Youth & Theatre of the Oppressed ; and Making Space for Youthin Education, Participatory Action Research & Social Change . NOTES 1. See,forexample,“TheLeft’sAboriginalBlindSpot”(Kay,2008) 2. This notion of “fictional assemblages” by which we organize a selfrepresentation provides a wonderfully nuancedsynonymforanyprogramofstudiesorteachereducationsyllabus. 3. Likewise,thereisnopresetmethodorcurriculumoftruths.Rather,andaswesuggest,therearecontextspecifics inourcurriculumandlearningspacesthatweeachcanidentifyassupportingorlimitingthepossibleoccurrencesof aneventandsubsequenttruthprocess.Thatsaid,attemptshavebeenmadetoenvisionanexampleofacurriculum insupportofeventsandtruthprocesses,seedenHeyer,2009b. 4. For an exemplary argument contesting insufficiently open ideological readings of the situation, see Elizabeth Ellsworth (1989), ‘‘Why Doesn’t This Feel Empowering? Working Through the Repressive Myths of Critical Pedagogy.’’

REFERENCES

Aoki, D. S. (2000). The thing never speaks for itself: Lacan and the pedagogical politic of clarity.Harvard Educational Review , 70 (3),347–369. Aoki, D. S (2002). The price of teaching: Love, evasion, and subordination of knowledge. Journal of Curriculum Theorizing . 18 (1),21–39. Apple,M.W.(2000). Official knowledge: Democratic education in a conservative age (2 nd ed.). NewYork:Routledge. Apple,M.W(2008).CurriculumPlanning:Content,Form,andthePoliticsofAccountability.In M.Connelly,M.F.He,&J.I.Phillion(Eds.), The SAGE Handbook of Curriculum and In- struction (pp.25–44).ThousandOaks,California:SagePublications. Ayers,W.,Quinn,T.,&Stovall,D.(Eds.).(2009). Handbook of social justice in education .New York:Routledge. Badiou,A.(2000).Artandphilosophy. , 17 ,48–67. Badiou,A.(2001). Ethics: An essay on the understanding of evil.(P.Hallward,Trans.).London: Verso.(Originalworkpublishedin1998) Badiou,A.(2003). Saint Paul: The foundation of universalism .(R.Brassier,Trans.).Stanford, CA:StanfordUniversityPress.(Originalworkpublishedin1997) Bracher,M. (1993). Lacan, discourse, and social change: A psychoanalytic cultural criticism . Ithaca,NY:CornellUniversityPress. Bracher,M.(2002).Identityanddesireintheclassroom. Inj.jagodzinski(Ed.), Pedagogical desire: Authority, seduction, transference, and the question of ethics (pp.93–121).Westport, CT:Bergin&Garvey. Britzman, D. (1998). Lost subjects, contested objects: Toward a psychoanalytic inquiry of learning. Albany,NY:StateUniversityofNewYorkPress. Britzman,D.(1991). Practice makes practice: A critical study of learning to teach .Albany,NY: StateUniversityofNewYorkPress. Carr,P.,&Lund,D.(Eds.).(2007). The great white north? Exploring whiteness, privilege, and identity in education. Rotterdam,TheNetherlands:Sense.

Journal of Curriculum Theorizing ♦Volume27,Number1,2011 17 denHeyer&Conrad ♦UsingAlainBadiou’sEthicofTruths

Carson, T. R. (2007, November). The time of learning: A dilemma for teacher education’s response to diversity .PaperpresentedtotheCATEInvitationalConferenceonResearchin TeacherEducation,Winnipeg,MN. denHeyer,K.(2009a).Stickypoints:Teachereducatorsreexaminetheirpracticeinlightofa newAlbertasocialstudiesprogramanditsinclusion of Aboriginal perspectives . Teaching Education , 20 (4),343356. denHeyer,K.(2009b).Educationasanaffirmativeinvention. Educational Theory , 59 (4),441– 463. Donald, D.T. (2009). The curricular problem of Indigenous: Colonial frontier logics, teacher resistances,andtheacknowledgementofethicalspace.InJ.Nahachewsky&I.Johnston, Be- yond ‘presentism’: Reimagining the historical, personal, and social places of curriculum (pp. 22–39 ).Rotterdam:SensePublishing. Ellsworth,E.(1989).Whydoesn’tthisfeelempowering?Workingthroughtherepressivemyths ofcriticalpedagogy. Harvard Educational Review, 59 (3),297–324. Felman,S.(1987). and the adventure of insight: in contemporary culture .Cambridge,Mass:HarvardUniversityPress. Francis,D.(1992). The imaginary Indian:Tthe image of the Indian in Canadian culture .Van couver,BC:ArsenalPulpPress. Francis,D.(1997). National dreams: Myth, memory and Canadian history.Vancouver:Arsenal PulpPress. Fraser,M.(2006).Event. Theory Culture & 23 ,129132. Fraser,N.(1997). Justice interruptus: Critical reflections on the “postsocialist” condition. New York:Routledge. Freire,P.(1970). Pedagogy of the oppressed (M.B.Ramos,Trans.).NewYork:Continuum. Freud, S. (1937/1968). Analysis Terminable and Interminable. The standard edition of the complete psychological works of Sigmund Freud Volume 23 (pp. 209–253). [J. Strachey, Trans].London:HogarthPress. Gardner, H. (1999). The disciplined mind: What all students should understand . New York: SimonandSchuster. Gerwitz,S.(2006).Towardsacontextualizedanalysisofsocialjusticeineducation. Educational Philosophy and Theory, 28 (1),69–81. Gibson,A.(2006). Beckett and Badiou: The pathos of intermittency .Oxford:NewYork; OxfordUniversityPress. Hallward,P.(2005).Dependingoninconsistency:Badiou’sanswertothe‘guidingquestionof allcontemporaryphilosophy.’ Polygraph,7–21. Kay,J.(2008,February3).TheLeft’sAboriginalblindspot. National Post. Kincheloe,J.(2008). Critical pedagogy (2 nd ed.).NY:PeterLang. Mansilla,V.B.,&Gardner,H.(2008).Discipliningthemind. Educational Leadership, 65 (5), 14–19. Pinar, W. F. (2004). What is curriculum theory? Mahwah, New Jersey: Laurence Earlbaum Associates,Publishers. Simon, R. I. (2005). The touch of the past: Remembrance, learning, and ethics . New York: PalgraveMacmillan. Smith,D.G.(2000).Thespecificchallengesofglobalizationforteachingandviceversa. Alberta Journal of Educational Research , 46 (1),7–25.

Journal of Curriculum Theorizing ♦Volume27,Number1,2011 18 denHeyer&Conrad ♦UsingAlainBadiou’sEthicofTruths

Stanley, T. (1998). The struggle for history: Historical narratives and a nti racist pedagogy. Discourse: Studies in the Cultural Politics of Education, 19 (1),41–49. Taubman,P.(2006).Whatistobedoneintheageofaccountability.InS.Leafgren,B. Schultz, M.O’Malley,L.Johnson,J.Brady,&A.Dentith(Eds.), The articu lation of curriculum and pedagogy for a just society: Advocacy, artistry, and activism (pp.1–13).Troy,NY:Educ a torsInternationalPress. Tisdell,E.J.(1993).Interlockingsystemsofpower,privilege,andoppressioninadulthigher educationclasses. Adult Education Quarterly, 43 ,203–226. Tupper , J., & Cappello, M. (2008). Teaching treaties as (un)usual narratives: Disrupting the curricularcommonsense. Curriculum Inquiry, 38 (5),559–578. Wildman,S.,&Davis,A.(2000). Languageandsilence:Makingsystemsofprivilegevisible .In M.Adams,W.Blumfeld,R.Caseñeda,H.Hackman,M.Peters,&X. Zúñiga(Eds.), Read- ings for diversity and social justice: An anthology on racism, , sexism, heter o- sexism, ableism, an d classism (pp.50–61).NewYork:Routledge.

Journal of Curriculum Theorizing ♦ Volume27 ,Number1,2011 19