Thinking the Future. Death and Redemption. Heidegger and Rosenzweig

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Thinking the Future. Death and Redemption. Heidegger and Rosenzweig $AI´MWN. Revista Internacional de Filosofía, Suplemento 3, 2010, 249-256 ISSN: 1130-0507 Thinking the Future. Death and Redemption. Heidegger and Rosenzweig BENIAMINO FORTIS* Abstract: Embedded within the leading issue of Resumen: Enmarcado dentro del tema principal the thinking of the future, Heideggerian Death del pensamiento del futuro, la muerte heidegge- and Rosenzweigian Redemption represent two riana y la redención de Rosenzweig presentan dos different reference-points which can shed light on formas diferentes de apuntar a aspectos que pue- human existence. den arrojar luz sobre la existencia humana. More precisely, the way the future is conceived Más en concreto, el modo en que Heidegger y by Heidegger and Rosenzweig lies at the roots of Rosenzweig conciben el futuro se encuentra en such relevant issues as mortality, otherness and las raíces de cuestiones tales como la mortalidad, possibility. la otredad y la posibilidad. Key words: Heidegger, Rosenzweig, Death, Palabras claves: Heidegger, Rosenzweig, muerte, Redemption. redención This article compares and analyzes the parallels and disjunctures between the concep- tions of the future that emerge from Heidegger’s and Rosenzweig’s thinking about time. The reference works to this aim are Being and Time1 and The Star of Redemption2. The way the future is conceived develops through complex interactions among such themes as mortality, otherness and possibility which are all strictly affected by the way the temporal issue is thought. The sharp alternative between a vision of death as last possibility (letzte Möglichkeit), in Heidegger, and as first factuality (erste, elementare Tatsächlichkeit), in Rosenzweig, represents the first main attainment whose intrinsic meaning reflects the deep difference between the perspectives of the two philosophers (§ 1). The Heideggerian Dasein considers death an extreme possibility just because it is the cessation of every other possibility. Mortality, showing the fade out of every Potentiality-for- being, exercises a retroactive effect on existence which brings such aspects as finitude and transitoriness to the fore. But existence seen from Rosenzweig’s point of view can however acquire the same features by mean of contact with the sphere of otherness (§ 2). The profound affinity Heidegger recognizes between the dimensions of future and possibility confirms a subordination of the one of otherness. To connect directly the future to the otherness of redemption – like Rosenzweig does – implies instead the downsizing – but not the annulment – of the range of possibility. University of Florence. E-mail: ben.fortis@gmail. 1 M. Heidegger: Being and Time, New York, Harper & Row, 1962. 2 F. Rosenzweig: The Star of Redemption, Medison, The University of Wisconsin Press, 2005. 250 Beniamino Fortis These are two existential positions whose radical contrast can in no case come to an agreement through a conciliatory compromise. Only the opposition dynamics of an aut-aut based way of thinking can render an account of it (§ 3). 1. Last possibility or first factuality? Every form of temporal existence is deeply affected by an impending destiny of mortality. Both Heideggerian Dasein and Rosenzweigian Judesein regard the end of life as the main focus of existence, but the difference between them consists in the way they relate to death. They represent two opposite attitudes to face human being in time. a. In Being and Time the problem of death is tackled on the base of the difference Heidegger remarks between the existentiell-ontical dimension and the existentiale-ontological one. The main trait of existence consists, for Heidegger, in the fact that in each case Dasein is already ahead of itself, i.e. in the fact that «in Dasein there is always something still outstanding, which, as a potentiality-for-being for Dasein itself, has not yet become “actual”»3. But a conception of death as the mere end of existence, from which Dasein is kept away by a lack of being, would confer on the reaching of death the meaning of filling of a lack and this would imply the loss of Dasein’s innermost essential feature: Dasein’s «Being is annihilated when what is still outstanding in its Being has been liquidated»4. The reaching of death as fulfilment of existence would deprive it of its fundamental incompleteness. The completion of existence would also be its dissolution. The fundamental flaw in this conception of death consists in considering Dasein «something present-at-hand, ahead of which something that is not yet present-at-hand is costantly shoving itself»5, in other words, in assuming a merely ontical point of view. But a radical change in perspective can show that «death is not something not yet pesent-at-hand, […]. Death is something that stands before us – something impending»6. The extreme dimension of death does not represent a simple not yet present aiming at a definitive presence. From an existentiale-ontological point of view, what develops between Dasein and death is rather a combination of mutual relationships characterized by fluidity and possibility more than by rigidity and actuality. Dasein, as potentiality-for-being, is moulded on the ontological manner of being-ahead- of-itself, it is motivated by a tendency toward what it not yet is – on one hand. But – on the other hand – the focus of Dasein’s striving is also something that it already is in the particular way of having something to reach, of being leaning toward something – an existential inclination that originates in the ontological manner of being of a tensional should be. What Dasein encounters in its facing forward is death seen as the possibility of extinguishment of every other possibility, but it is exactly at this level that Heideggerian argument reverses and, from the field of mortality, turns back to the one of existence. 3 M. Heidegger: Being and Time, op. cit., p. 279. 4 Ibid., p. 280. 5 Ibid. 6 Ibid., p. 293-294. Daímon. Revista Internacional de Filosofía, Suplemento 3, 2010 Thinking the Future. Death and Redemption. Heidegger and Rosenzweig 251 Showing the end of every possibility, death exercises a retroactive influence on existence, by virtue of which possibility strengthens its existential-ontological meaning and turns out to be confirmed in the role of main characteristic feature of existing in time. The intrinsic leaning forward of potentiality-for-being turns to the extreme of death7. Death, as a limit, sheds new light on the dimension of possibility, bringing to the fore its importance for existence8. This reciprocity is the background on which death and possibility relate to each other and mutually define their ontological status. Heideggerian conception of death gains in this way a connotation in terms of last possibility, the extreme level of the openness of existence. It is now worth pointing out that such an idea of death rides out the ontical impasse considered before. The risk of an ontical degradation is avoided by mantaining the ontological tenor of mortality at a state of possibility and preventing it from changing into a condition of actuality: «Death, as possibility, gives Dasein nothing to be “actualized”, nothing which Dasein, as actual, could itself be»9. b. Also The Star of Redemption opens with the need to come to terms with the problem of death. Every form of philosophical knowledge is conceived by Rosenzweig as an attempt to escape from death and to elude the atavistic fear by which death is accompanied. But though philosophy rises up against the originary dread of death, every claim of rebellion against human condition is inexorably fated to fall. «From death, it is from the fear of death that all cognition of the All begins. Philosophy has the audacity to cast off the fear of the earthly, to remove from death its poisonous sting, from Hades his pestilential breath»10. Philosophy claims to be able to face up to death, but in fact it is not. Death, as a triggering motive to make philosophical thought react against human destiny, keeps implicitly affecting existence, thus frustrating every effort to assuage the fear of the poisonous sting and of the pestilential breath. In the course of its history, philosophy has adopted many different strategies to pursue the goal of a definitive abolition of death (Abschaffung des Todes). But every attempt, only apparently succeeding in achieving its purpose, turns in fact out to be a failure and thus, a further argument in support of a need for taking seriously into account the presupposition (Voraussetzung) of mortality. This is a fondamental issue that cannot be got around by philosphical abstractions and that rather emerges as the most pressing, concrete and inescapable one for human existence. 7 «Thus death reveals itself as that possibility which is one’s ownmost, which is non-relational, and which is not to be outstripped. As such, death is something distinctively impending. Its existential possibility is based on the fact that Dasein is essentially disclosed to itself, and disclosed, indeed, as ahead-of-itself» (Ibid., p. 294). 8 «With death, Dasein stands before itself in its ownmost potentiality-for-Being. This is a possibility in which the issue is nothing less that Dasein’s Being-in-the-world. Its death is the possibility of no-longer-being-able-to-be- there. If Dasein stands before itself as this possibility, it has been fully assigned to its ownmost potentiality-for- Being» (Ibid.). 9 Ibid., p. 307. 10 F. Rosenzweig: The Star of Redemption, op. cit., p. 9. Daímon. Revista Internacional de Filosofía, Suplemento 3, 2010 252 Beniamino Fortis On the one hand, metaphysical-transcendent philosophies cope with the fear of death by way of division: Body and soul, the empirical and the intelligible, are the two dimensions into which the world is divided, according to such a way of thinking. Death concerns only the first one, while the second one is immortal and eternal.
Recommended publications
  • 1 Thomas Meyer Leo Strauss's Religious Rhetoric
    Thomas Meyer Leo Strauss’s Religious Rhetoric (1924-1938) Although he had been regarded as shy and restrained since his period of study in Marburg, Strauss was a master of religious rhetoric in his letters and [published] texts. This rhetoric was, for him, neither a [form of] compensation [for insufficient argument], nor a superficial adornment. On the contrary, he deployed religious rhetoric in same way that he analysed [its function] in Plato and Aristotle, through Maimonides and Abravanel, into Spinoza and Hobbes, and up to Hermann Cohen and Julius Guttmann: as an expression of the complex contest between philosophy and religion. After his engagement with Hermann Cohen’s critique of Spinoza in 1924, religious rhetoric was, for Strauss, no longer a feature of Zionist debates alone. Instead, it was a constitutive element of a problematic that Strauss strikingly and provocatively dubbed the “querelle des anciens et des modernes.” In order to understand this change in the function of religious rhetoric [in Strauss’ work], I shall consider three stations of Strauss’ intellectual development. First of all, I shall present several articles that I found in the “Jewish Weekly for Cassel, Hessen, and Waldeck”, which have remained unknown to scholarship until now. Strauss published these articles between February 1925 and January 1928. If we connect these texts with Strauss’s conclusions regarding Spinoza, we can develop a stable account of his religious rhetoric up to about 1934. But [Strauss’s use of religious rhetoric in these texts] can be understood only if we consider it in light of Strauss’ translation of a different religious rhetoric [into the terms of his own thought]: namely, the way Strauss enriched his religious rhetoric through an understanding of, and in dialogue with, the most radical position in Protestant [thought]—that of the dialectical theologian Friedrich Gogarten.
    [Show full text]
  • KIERKEGAARD and EXISTENTIALISM. Edited by Jon Stewart
    KIERKEGAARD AND EXISTENTIALISM. Edited by Jon Stewart. Kierkegaard Research: Sources, Reception and Resources 9. Burlington, VT: Ashgate, 2011. Pp. xvii+427. ISBN: 978-1-4094-2641-7. The series, Kierkegaard Research: Sources, Reception and Resources, collects articles that treat the sources of Kierkegaard’s own thought, the reception of his thought in philosophy, theology, drama, aesthetics, literature, and political life, and reference works in order to guide scholars in their engagement with Kierkegaard’s writings. This ninth volume in the series, Kierkegaard and Existentialism, comprises part of this series’ goal by exploring the reception of Søren Kierkegaard’s thought in the movement that, on some accounts, begins with the Dane himself. In the preface, Jon Stewart maintains that though Kierkegaard’s thought has been influential for the development of existentialism and has been cast, particularly by Sartre in L’existentialisme est un humanisme, as a forerunner to existentialism, “recent scholarship has been attentive to the ideological use of Kierkegaard in this context.” Thus, this volume, continues Stewart, aims to “reexamine the complex relation between Kierkegaard and the existentialist thinkers” in order to determine whether or not Kierkegaard is misrepresented and distorted in this reception (x). The contributors to this volume accomplish this task with great aplomb by addressing the reception of Kierkegaard’s thought in the phi- losophies of Friedrich Nietzsche, Miguel de Unamuno, Lev Shestov, Nicholas Berdyaev, Martin Buber, Jacques Maritain, Karl Jaspers, Franz Rosenzweig, Jean Wahl, Martin Heidegger, Gabriel Marcel, Jean-Paul Sartre, Simone de Beauvoir, Maurice Merleau-Ponty, Albert Camus, and Michel Henry. One essay is devoted for each of these figure’s reception of Kierkegaard’s thought.
    [Show full text]
  • Ethics After Auschwitz: Hans Jonas's Notion Of
    INTRODUCTION ETHICS AFTER AUSCHWITZ: HANS JONAS’S NOTION OF RESPONSIBILITY IN A TECHNOLOGICAL AGE Richard Wolin It is worth pausing for a moment at the outset to refl ect on what a remarkable life Hans Jonas led. Born in Mönchengladbach, Germany, in 1903, by the age of thirty Jonas had experienced, in extremis, the full array of early twentieth-century European cultural and political turmoil: World War I (albeit as a civilian), the rising tide of Central European anti-Semitism, Germany’s collapse on the home front accompanied by civil war, the proclamation of the Weimar Republic (Germany’s fi rst), anti-democratic coup attempts from both left and right, devastating hyperinfl ation, and the Crash of 1929, followed by renewed civil strife and the ominous rise of National Socialism. Hitler’s 1933 seizure of power would plunge Germany—and Europe—into a twelve-year night- mare of dictatorship, persecutions, concentration camps, and world war. In 1934, in light of escalating levels of anti-Semitic persecution, Jonas wisely decided to emigrate to Palestine. At the time, he pledged that he would only return to Germany as part of a conquering army. As it turned out, his vow proved prophetic. In 1939, he joined the British army’s Jewish Brigade, reentering his former homeland along with the victorious allies in 1945. Three years later, in 1948, Jonas would don military garb again to fi ght in Israel’s war of independence. Weary of war, Jonas and his wife, Lore, moved to Montreal in 1949, where he began a distinguished career as a university professor.
    [Show full text]
  • Lebovic on Gordon, 'Rosenzweig and Heidegger: Between Judaism and German Philosophy'
    H-German Lebovic on Gordon, 'Rosenzweig and Heidegger: Between Judaism and German Philosophy' Review published on Thursday, June 1, 2006 Peter Eli Gordon. Rosenzweig and Heidegger: Between Judaism and German Philosophy. Weimar and Now: University of California Press, 2003. 357 pp. $65.00 (cloth), ISBN 978-0-520-23611-0; $25.95 (paper), ISBN 978-0-520-24636-2. Reviewed by Nitzan Lebovic (Department of History, University of California-Los Angeles and University of Tel Aviv) Published on H-German (June, 2006) The Radical Horizon of German-Jewish Thought In his recent book, Peter Gordon makes an excellent case for the relevance of German-Jewish thought, pointing out the seminal role it played in the development of modern critical theory and intellectual history. The new role of German-Jewish studies, according to Gordon, is to blaze a new critical path: at the end of protracted efforts to erect a decisive barrier between supporters and critics of humanism, we now need to reconsider the radical and shared legacy of such names as Franz Rosenzweig and Martin Heidegger. For Gordon, the current interest in Rosenzweig's "negative theology" is largely political, a classic case of enlightened society questioning norms and conventions. Heidegger sets the stage and allows Gordon to emphasize the "positive possibility" of radical thinking. However, while examining the suppressed topics of the past, Gordon ignores the might- have-beens and the inevitable theoretical horizon of his own investigation. The reader is left to wonder: at what point would Rosenzweig have recognized the terrifying connections between Heidegger's philosophy and his politics? When Franz Rosenzweig and Martin Heidegger was published three years ago, it was received enthusiastically and immediately added to syllabi in Jewish history and Jewish studies.
    [Show full text]
  • The 1916-1924 Dialogue of Franz Rosenzweig and Eugen Rosenstockhuessy
    Politics, Theology, Race, and Religion: The 1916-1924 Dialogue of Franz Rosenzweig and Eugen RosenstockHuessy By Gregory Kaplan, Rice University [October 18, 2008 draft] In a 1924 paper revised from a 1916 letter sent initially to his friend the Jewish educator and theorist Franz Rosenzweig, the historian of jurisprudence and Christian revolution, Eugen Rosenstock-Huessy, wrote the following of November 9, 1918. “That day caused everyone, from Hindenburg to Liebknecht, to die, to break through to a new time, to change. So we indeed have a life in common despite it all.” He understood that the communicative force of revolution in time from before to after, the transformation from old to new, also brings the participants together into communal space, a commons and a cosmos. Hindenburg and Liebknecht are opposites bound together in the coincidence of government, polity, time and territory. Rosentock-Huessy made this remark after 1923’s gradual stabilization calmed years of turmoil. Arguing that the practical study of the soul needs more than humanistic and scientific inquiry into mind and body, the paper speculates on immortality, life which proceeds from death in the course of translation, “a venture and an advance into unseen territory.” Translation renders practice transcendent; but to “cross over to another shore: that is the risk of politics.”1 Politics according to Rosenstock-Huessy not only risks life for death, but wagers its life after death. Even before 1924 politics and theology were linked controversially, as the Rosenzweig-Rosenstock debate demonstrates. 1 Eugen Rosenstock-Huessy, Practical Knowledge of the Soul [PKS] (Argo Books: 1988), 51, 66.
    [Show full text]
  • THE CATHOLIC UNIVERSITY of AMERICA Speaking and Thinking
    THE CATHOLIC UNIVERSITY OF AMERICA Speaking and Thinking about God in Rosenzweig and Heidegger A DISSERTATION Submitted to the Faculty of the School of Philosophy Of The Catholic University of America In Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements For the Degree Doctor of Philosophy By Paul Murphy Higgins Washington, D.C. 2013 Speaking and Thinking about God in Rosenzweig and Heidegger Paul Murphy Higgins, Ph.D. Director: Holger Zaborowski, D.Phil. In the early twentieth century, many philosophers began to reject Kantian and Hegelian approaches to the question of God and the philosophy of religion. The challenge was then to formulate a new way of talking about God within philosophy without necessarily having to revert to pre-modern accounts. These thinkers saw the importance of retaining the insights of modernity while also taking into account the Romantic and post-Romantic critiques of modernism as a one- sided or overly rationalistic enterprise. This dissertation seeks to provide a comprehensive picture of the approaches of Franz Rosenzweig and Martin Heidegger to rethinking the question of how philosophy is to proceed, especially in light of religious phenomena. Placing Rosenzweig and Heidegger in dialogue helps to further our understanding of both figures, particularly insofar as Rosenzweig’s thought might be used as a corrective to possible shortcomings in the later Heidegger. Many scholars have argued that there is something problematic about Heidegger’s religious thought, but Rosenzweig has been almost completely overlooked as an important corrective resource. Both Rosenzweig’s comprehensive account of the basic phenomena of human existence and his grammatical method for formulating this account share many of Heidegger’s insights, yet surpass them insofar as Rosenzweig is able to address the topic in a more philosophically cogent manner.
    [Show full text]
  • Totality and Community: Rosenzweig Versus Hegel
    UDK: 172.4 Rozencvajg F. (048) https://doi.org/10.2298/FID2004467P Original Scientific Article PHILOSOPHY AND SOCIETY Received: 24.09.2020. Accepted: 02.11.2020. VOL. 31, NO. 4, 449–660 Giacomo Petrarca TOTALITY AND COMMUNITY: ROSENZWEIG VERSUS HEGEL ABSTRACT KEYWORDS In his masterpiece The Star of Redemption, Franz Rosenzweig (1886-1929) Rosenzweig, Hegel, shows as the notion of totality is a constant and central reference in the totality, community, history of philosophy from Ionia to Jena. This paper aims to explain a Jewish thought different meaning of the concept of totality, reconsidering some aspects of the question starting from the philosophical reflection of Franz Rosenzweig and his opposition to the Hegelian thought. In particular, according to Rosenzweig, the concept of totality is the essential background in which one could rethink the concept of community. For this reason, the second part of this paper is focused on the implications of a different concept of totality embodied by Judaism. Introduction The aim of this paper is the explanation of a different meaning of the concept of totality, reconsidering some aspects of the question starting from the phil- osophical reflection of Franz Rosenzweig and his opposition to the Hegelian thought. In particular, the concept of totality is the essential background in which Rosenzweig rethinks his understanding of community. In order to try to outline at least the problem in a satisfactory manner, we will attempt to move on two fronts: on the one hand, we will try to outline a ge- nealogy of the Hegelian totality, assuming – along with Rosenzweig – that the totality is the deepest essence of Western thought (at least as stated by Hegel); on the other hand, we will primarily survey the connection between Judaism and philosophy, indicating, in conclusion, a possible reformulation capable of putting aside the classic opposition between Athens and Jerusalem.
    [Show full text]
  • Franz Rosenzweig's
    Franz Rosenzweig’s Star of Redemption As a System of Philosophy By: Erik Dreff For: Jewish Studies Workshop, University of Chicago 10/15/’12 DRAFT. NOT FOR QUOTATION, DUPLICATION, FURTHER DISSEMINATION, PUBLICATION, OR ANY OTHER “…ATION” Flush with undefined and unreferenced recondite terms, phrases and quotations, some apparently drawn from conversations with his interlocutors, yet often tweaked from their original meaning if just a little, Franz Rosenzweig’s Star of Redemption notoriously occludes ready understanding even by the initiated. Be it an unmarked quotation from Goethe or an allusion to a Kantian notion, Rosenzweig’s Star requires a North Star of its own for successful navigation.1 As a result, and in large part due to simple humility in the face of such a daunting and difficult task, we leave the exposition and clarification of those details for someone better suited to it. Our task here, rather, is to delve into a more abstract question regarding Rosenzweig’s Star of Redemption when one considers his claim that the work constitutes a system of philosophy. Our task here then is to investigate the grounding of Rosenzweig’s Star as a system of philosophy. I. Introduction I.A. Defining the Universe of Discourse The question regarding the grounding of the Star as a system of philosophy involves, on the face of it, two questions: A) Is the Star in fact what it claims to be – a system of philosophy?2 And B) is the Star qua system of philosophy, which, due to the complexity and difficulty of the text, we are assuming as having met the criteria for a system of philosophy and thus meeting the requirements for (A),3 well-grounded and thus convincing? By (B) well-grounded and thus convincing, however, I intend the following distinction from (A): Taking (A) to entail any questions concerning the system’s internal or logical coherence and 1 I’d like to take this opportunity to say thank you to my own personal North Star for all things Rosenzweig, Prof.
    [Show full text]
  • Gottlieb on Pollock, 'Franz Rosenzweig's Conversions: World Denial and World Redemption'
    H-Judaic Gottlieb on Pollock, 'Franz Rosenzweig's Conversions: World Denial and World Redemption' Review published on Tuesday, December 1, 2015 Benjamin Pollock. Franz Rosenzweig's Conversions: World Denial and World Redemption. Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 2014. 282 pp. $60.00 (cloth), ISBN 978-0-253-01312-5. Reviewed by Michah Gottlieb (New York University)Published on H-Judaic (December, 2015) Commissioned by Matthew A. Kraus Coherence or Contradiction? In 1953, Nahum Glatzer published his influential book, Franz Rosenzweig: His Life and Thought. For decades, Glatzer’s book was one of the only sources of original texts by Rosenzweig and served as the introduction to Rosenzweig for American readers. Stressing the unity between Rosenzweig’s life and thought, Glatzer devoted much attention to Rosenzweig’s biography. The most dramatic element was his moving account of Rosenzweig’s near conversion to Christianity and subsequent return to Judaism. Glatzer recounted Rosenzweig’s early training in European philosophy, especially his encounter with German Idealism. But Glatzer noted that Rosenzweig “moved away” from German philosophy “toward the ‘existential’ philosophy that took its starting point in the situation of the concrete individual,” and was particularly drawn to religion. The problem, according to Glatzer, was that Rosenzweig felt barred from accepting religion because of his training in “the sciences, in logical criticism, and in the methods of modern historical research.”[1] More specifically, Rosenzweig accepted historicism, which led him to adopt a relativistic view of truth. Glatzer claimed that conversations Rosenzweig had with his cousin Rudolf Ehrenberg and his friend Eugen Rosenstock, both baptized Jews, finally freed him from the shackles of relativism.
    [Show full text]
  • Reading Rosenzweig's Little Book
    Reading Rosenzweig’s Little Book Hilary Putnam Harvard University Abstract In this article the author addresses the issues that Franz Rosenzweig raises in his Büch- lein as they affect the former’s own very personal manifestation of Judaism. The arti- cle therefore covers not only the contents of the “little book”, but aims more generally to say something about aspects of Rosenzweig’s thought that the author finds prob- lematic. The article begins by looking at three notions that are often used in connec- tion with the sorts of issues Rosenzweig raises (atheism, religion, and spirituality), goes on to stress the importance of Rosenzweig’s “religious existentialism”, and ends by keeping its distance from some of Rosenzweig’s central claims, with an eye to both reconciling the author’s religiosity with a plausible naturalism and salvaging a suitable space for philosophical speculation about God. Keywords: atheism, religion, spirituality, religious existentialism, Rosenzweig In this article I will discuss Rosenzweig’s Büchlein,1 but I do not want to simply in- terpret the “little book”—that I did in chapter one of my Jewish Philosophy as a Guide to Life.2 I want to address the issues that Rosenzweig raises as they affect my own very personal manifestation of Judaism. So my article will range more widely than just the contents of the “little book”, and also say more about aspects of Rosenzweig’s thought that I find problematic. To do that, I will begin by looking at three notions that are often used in connection with the sorts of issues Rosenzweig raises: atheism, religion, and spirituality.
    [Show full text]
  • Strauss, Soloveitchik and the Genesis Narrative: Conceptions of the Ideal Jew As Derived from Philosophical and Theological Readings of the Bible
    Thejournal of jewish Thought and Philosophy, Vol. 5, pp. 99-143 © 1995 Reprints available directly from the publisher. Photocopying permitted by license only Strauss, Soloveitchik and the Genesis Narrative: Conceptions of the Ideal Jew as Derived from Philosophical and Theological Readings of the Bible Jonathan Cohen School rf Education, The Hebrew University rf Jerusalem Recent publications bespeak an abiding interest in the Judaic thought of Leo Strauss and Joseph B. Soloveitchik.1 As Martin Jaffe reminds us, Strauss sub- mitted twentieth century Jewish thought, as embodied in the writings of Hermann Cohen, Martin Buber and Franz Rosenzweig, to a relentless cri- tique from the dual standpoints of philosophical consistency and traditional Jewish authenticity. His call for unflinching recognition of the traditional Jew- ish posture concerning the primacy of the externally imposed law, and his insistence on the stark ,irreconcilability of the Bible's orientation to obedi- ence and the philosophical attitude of "checking" and "investigation," advise the modern Jew of the grave difficulties attendant upon even the most sin- cere attempt at a return to tradition.2 The re-issue of Soloveitchik's major works and the continuing compilation of his oral discourses could be inter- preted as evidence of his ongoing status as orientational figure for signifi- 1 The past decade has seen the appearance of a number of anthologies of Strauss's writings, con- taining, alongside studies in the classics of the western political tradition, essays or lectures, some- times previously unpublished, on more or less explicitly Jewish thinkers and themes. See in particular: Pangle, Thomas, ed. Studies in Platonic Political Philosophy (Chicago, University of Chicago Press, 1983); Pangle, Thomas, ed.
    [Show full text]
  • Reason and Revelation in the Work of Leo Strauss and Eric Voegelin
    Reason and Revelation in the Work of Leo Strauss and Eric Voegelin Copyright 2008 Barry Cooper The title of this paper indicates a subject-matter far too extensive to discuss properly in a short paper, or even a long one. This was not always true. In 1993, when Peter Emberley and I drew together 53 letters by Strauss and Voegelin, the task was relatively manageable.1 [1] The eight commentaries in Part III of that book provide the evidence. Fifteen years ago it was possible to argue that Voegelin's hermeneutic of experience and symbolization was sharply distinct from Strauss's "total commitment to Greek philosophy,� as Tom Altizer put it (p. 267). A few pages later, Tom Pangle contrasted "Voegelin's faith-inspired historical philosophizing or philosophy of history� with Strauss's "intransigent stand for philosophy as rigorous science� (p. 341). Several commentaries drew attention to a remark by Strauss from his 1954 paper, "The Mutual Influence of Theology and Philosophy,� also included with the correspondence, that: "no one can be both a philosopher and a theologian or, for that matter, a third which is beyond the conflict between philosophy and theology, or a synthesis of both� (p. 217). Or, as Strauss wrote to Voegelin (25/02/1951) "every synthesis is actually an option either for Jerusalem or for Athens� (p. 78). Voegelin replied that "the problem of revelation,� along with the form of the 1 [1] Faith and Political Philosophy: The Correspondence between Leo Strauss and Eric Voegelin, 1934-1964, tr. and ed., Peter Emberley and Barry Cooper (University Park: The Pennsylvania State University Press, 1993).
    [Show full text]