And How “Sense of Life” Can Help You to Claim It Tara Smith OCON

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

And How “Sense of Life” Can Help You to Claim It Tara Smith OCON To Imagine A Heaven – And How “Sense of Life” Can Help You to Claim It Tara Smith OCON July 2011 / Fort Lauderdale Passages from Ayn Rand & Others A. Passages from Ayn Rand’s non-fiction: pp. 2-8 B. Passages from Ayn Rand’s fiction: pp. 8-12 C. Passages from other authors: pp. 12-13 Abbreviations & Editions Used: Throughout, all emphases in originals PSL = "Philosophy & Sense of Life” (in The Romantic Manifesto) AMT = “Art & Moral Treason” (in RM) ASL = “Art & Sense of Life” (in RM) PSA = “The Psycho-Epistemology of Art" (in RM) A&C = “Art and Cognition” (in RM) Goal = “The Goal of My Writing” (in RM) DLG = “Don’t Let it Go” (in Philosophy: Who Needs It) MM = “The Metaphysical versus the Manmade” (in PWNI) CVD = “Causality vs. Duty” (in PWNI) TOE = "The Objectivist Ethics" (in The Virtue of Selfishness) Envy = “The Age of Envy” (in Return of the Primitive) Journals = Journals of Ayn Rand, ed. David Harriman, Plume/Penguin, 1997 Letters = Letters of Ayn Rand, ed. Michael S. Berliner, Plume/Penguin, 1995 OPAR = Leonard Peikoff, Objectivism: The Philosophy of Ayn Rand, Penguin, 1991 NB: “Vacuum, speech, Zavarella” refers to Kara Zavarella’s transcription of Ayn Rand’s speech, “Our Esthetic Vacuum,” which is lengthier and somewhat different from the written version that was published in The Romantic Manifesto under the title, “The Esthetic Vacuum of Our Age.” Ayn Rand Answers – The Best of Her Q&A, ed. Robert Mayhew, Penguin, 2005 Objectively Speaking, eds. Peter Schwartz & Marlene Podritske, Lexington Books, 2009 Return of the Primitive – The Anti-Industrial Revolution, expanded edition of The New Left, ed. Peter Schwartz, Meridian, 1999 Editions of Ayn Rand’s works: The Romantic Manifesto, 1975, second revised edition Philosophy: Who Needs It, Bobbs-Merrill, 1982 The Virtue of Selfishness, Penguin, 1964 Atlas Shrugged, 50th anniversary edition paperback, (originally published 1957) We the Living, New American Library/Penguin, 2009 (originally published 1936) “Ideal,” in The Early Ayn Rand, 1986. _____________ 2 A. Passages from Ayn Rand’s Non-Fiction 1. “A sense of life is a pre-conceptual equivalent of metaphysics, an emotional, subconsciously integrated appraisal of man and of existence. It sets the nature of a man’s emotional responses and the essence of his character. "PSL" p. 25 2. “Long before he is old enough to grasp such a concept as metaphysics, man makes choices, forms value-judgments, experiences emotions and acquires a certain implicit view of life. Every choice and value-judgment implies some estimate of himself and of the world around him—most particularly, of his capacity to deal with the world. He may draw conscious conclusions, which may be true or false; or he may remain mentally passive and merely react to events (i.e., merely feel). Whatever the case may be, his subconscious mechanism sums up his psychological activities, integrating his conclusions, reactions or evasions into an emotional sum that establishes a habitual pattern and becomes his automatic response to the world around him. What began as a series of single, discrete conclusions (or evasions) about his own particular problems, becomes a generalized feeling about existence, an implicit metaphysics with the compelling motivational power of a constant, basic emotion—an emotion which is part of all his other emotions and underlies all his experiences. This is a sense of life.” "PSL" pp. 25-26 3. “The integrated sum of a man’s basic values is his sense of life.” "PSL" p. 29 4. “A given person’s sense of life is hard to identify conceptually, because it is hard to isolate: it is involved in everything about that person, in his every thought, emotion, action, in his every response, in his every choice and value, in his every spontaneous gesture, in his manner of moving, talking, smiling, in the total of his personality. It is that which makes him a ‘personality.’” "PSL" p.31 5. “There are two aspects of man’s existence which are the special province and expression of his sense of life: love and art.” "PSL" p. 32 6. “The key concept, in the formation of a sense of life, is the term ‘important.’” "PSL" p. 28 7. “…A sense of life is not infallible. But a sense of life is the source of art, the psychological mechanism which enables man to create a realm such as art. "ASL" p. 35 8. “The emotion involved in art is not an emotion in the ordinary meaning of the term. It is experienced more as a “sense” or a “feel,” but it has two characteristics pertaining to emotions: it is automatically immediate and it has an intense, profoundly personal (yet undefined) value-meaning to the individual experiencing it. The value involved is life, and the words naming the emotion are: ‘This is what life means to me.’ "ASL" p. 35 9. “Regardless of the nature or content of an artist’s metaphysical views, what an art work expresses, fundamentally, under all of its lesser aspects is: ‘This is life as I see it.’ The essential meaning of a viewer’s or reader’s response, under all of its lesser elements, is: ‘This is (or is not) life as I see it.’ "ASL" p. 35 10. “And just as an individual who has never translated his sense of life into conscious convictions is in terrible danger—no matter how good his subconscious values—so is a nation.” "DLG" p. 252 3 11. “A sense of life is not a substitute for explicit knowledge. Values which one cannot identify, but merely senses implicitly, are not in one’s control. One cannot tell what they depend on or require, what course of action is needed to gain and/or keep them. One can lose or betray them without knowing it.” "DLG" pp. 256-257 12. “Emotional abstractions. An emotional abstraction consists of all those things which have the power to make one experience a certain emotion. For instance: a heroic man, the New York skyline, flying in a plane, a sunlit "stylized" landscape, ecstatic music, an achievement of which one is proud. (These same things will give an emotion of terror and guilt to a man with the wrong premises; all except the last, which is impossible to him.) An opposite example: a humble or depraved man, an old village or ruins, "walking on the moors," a desolate landscape, folk songs or atonal music, the failure of someone else's achievement or ambition. (The root and common denominator in all these things is self-esteem or lack of it; pro-man or anti- man; pro-life or anti-life.)” Journals, p. 714, April 28, 1965, on To Lorne Dieterling 13. lengthy passage: “The fundamental mistake in this question is its treatment of sense of life as if it were a conscious, rational conviction. I’ve always stressed that a sense of life is not a conviction, but an emotional sum arrived at subconsciously. This is why man cannot be guided by a sense of life alone; he is helpless without a conscious philosophy. “You define your sense of life by introspection; however, if you’re interested in identifying your sense of life, you don’t start by defining it. Begin by defining the causes of your emotions. First learn to identify the exact nature of what you feel (and why) in any instance. Learn to be at home with your emotions. Learn to identify in conscious words (not approximately) what you feel and why. Once you’ve become acquainted with yourself emotionally—when there are no longer any great mysteries—then you can try to identify your sense of life. … “You need not characterize your sense of life; what’s important is to ask yourself: “Are my subconscious ideas right or wrong? Do I consciously believe them, or have I made a mistake in my childhood?” and then translate your sense of life into conscious convictions. Once you’ve reached the point where you have identified the essentials of your sense of life, you’ll know you’re succeeding when there is no clash between your conscious convictions and your subconscious, sense of life emotions. “How much detail is necessary? Sense of life doesn’t deal with details, just as emotions don’t. It deals with philosophical fundamentals. Therefore, if you know in sense of life terms what you feel about the nature of reality, cognition, man’s nature, and his morality, that’s sufficient to know your sense of life. “In the light of what I’ve said, it is of course impossible to name the sense of life of fiction characters. You might name the sense of life of your closest friend—though I doubt it. You may, after some years, know approximately the sense of life of the person you love, but nobody beyond that. You cannot judge the sense of life of another person; that would be psychologizing. Judge their philosophical convictions, not whether their feelings match their ideas. That’s not for you to judge; it’s of no relevance to you. “In art, you can say I like this artist’s sense of life, even though his conscious convictions are different or opposite. But then you’re not concerned with his psychology, but with the ideas expressed in his work. It’s impossible to tell the sense of life of a character of fiction. What you need to determine are his convictions—his basic views on life. … 4 “A novelist need not—and cannot—know the sense of life of his characters. He needs their conscious convictions.” Ayn Rand Answers – The Best of Her Q&A, pp.
Recommended publications
  • Originalism, Vintage Or Nouveau: “He Said, She Said” Law
    Fordham Law Review Volume 82 Issue 2 Article 10 2013 Originalism, Vintage or Nouveau: “He Said, She Said” Law Tara Smith University of Texas at Austin Follow this and additional works at: https://ir.lawnet.fordham.edu/flr Part of the Law Commons Recommended Citation Tara Smith, Originalism, Vintage or Nouveau: “He Said, She Said” Law, 82 Fordham L. Rev. 619 (2013). Available at: https://ir.lawnet.fordham.edu/flr/vol82/iss2/10 This Symposium is brought to you for free and open access by FLASH: The Fordham Law Archive of Scholarship and History. It has been accepted for inclusion in Fordham Law Review by an authorized editor of FLASH: The Fordham Law Archive of Scholarship and History. For more information, please contact [email protected]. ORIGINALISM, VINTAGE OR NOUVEAU: “HE SAID, SHE SAID” LAW Tara Smith* INTRODUCTION: AN OVERVIEW OF ORIGINALISM’S BASIC FAILURE I begin with a brief overview of originalism’s central failings. I then consider three lines of defense that help to explain its resilient appeal and proceed to critique those three lines of reasoning. Through its various incarnations, I contend, originalism is guilty of a fatal contradiction. Law represents coercion. A legal system governs by force; that is the tool that gives teeth to its rules. I say this not as an indictment of law or of government; it is simply a fact—a fact that is significant to the proper conduct of judicial review. A legal system also works by words, which state the authority that it does and does not possess and how its coercive power will be used.
    [Show full text]
  • Reason Papers No
    Editor: Tibor R. Machan Managbig Editor: Mark Turiano Executive Editor: Gregory R. Johnson Associate Editors: Walter Block/ Economics Douglas J. Den Uyl/ Philosophy Kelly Dean Jolley/ Philosophy Leonard Liggio/ History Eric Mack/ Philosophy John D. McCallie/ Economics H. Joachim Maitre/ Interrzational Relations Ralph Raico/ History Lynn Scarlett/ Political Science Advisory Board: D. T. Armentanol University ofHartford Yale Brazen/ University of Chicago Nicholas Capaldi/ Urziversity of Tulsa R.L. Cunningham/ University of Sun Francisco John Hospers/ Univmity of Southern Cdlifornia Isreal M. Kirzner/ Nm York University Kenneth G. Luce y/ SUNY College. Fredonia Fred D. Miller, Jr./ Bowling Green State University Herbert Morris/ University of California, Los Angeles Clifton Perry/ Auburn University Paul Craig Roberts/ Georgetown University Morton L. Schagrin/ SUNY College, Fredonia Thomas S. Szasz/ SUNYMedical Center, Syracuse Articles On the Fit between Egoism and Rights ......................Eric Mack 3 Resolving the Tension in Aristotle's Ethic: The Balance Between Naturalism and Responsibility ........ David E. W. Fenner 22 The Irrationality of the Extended Order: The Fatal Conceit of F. A . Hayek ....... Larry ]. Sechrest 38 Special Forum: Rand & Philosophy A Philosopher for the New Millennium? ........ Fred D. Miller. Jr. On Rand as Philosopher ............................... Dough J. Den Uyl Rand and Philosophy (and Capitalism) ..... Douglas B. Rasmussen Ayn Rand's Contribution to Philosophy ....... Neera K. Badhwar What is Living in the Philosophy of AynRand ... Lester H . Hunt Rand and Objectivity ............................................... David Kelly Rand Revisited ...................................... .. ................]. Roger Lee Ayn Rand's Philosophical Significance .................... John Hospers Ayn Rand as Moral & Political Philosopher ..........la n Narveson Discussion Notes Kamhi and Torres on Meaning in Ayn Rand's Esthetics ..............................................
    [Show full text]
  • Machan Vs. Rand
    DERIVING RIGHTS FROM EGOISM: MACHAN vs. RANID Eyal Mozes In his book Individuals and Their Rights, Tibor Machan presents an argument deriving individual rights fro~m an ethics of rational egoism (or, to use his term, classical egoism). Machan cites Ayn Rand throughout his book, and regards his own arguments as a more detai- led and systematic presentation of the argument sketched by Rand. However, I submit that Machan's argument is significantly different from Rand's. Rand's arguments are often misinterpreted in a form similar to Machan's. To a large extent, this is the result of the lack of a systematic presentation of Rand's philosophy, and of the brief, sketchy form in which she presented her views. However, a close reading of ,her statements on this subject, and a look at other, less easily avail- able sources (such as taped lectures by Leonard1 Peikoff, who has had the advantage of long personal discussions with Rand), reveal a line of argument very different from - and, :[ submit, much sounder than - Machan's. There are two aspects in which Machan's argument differs from Rand's: (1) Machan justifies his interpersonal ethics through a "substitution principle", the idea that rationality requires you to grant to other human beings the same: rights that your Reason Papers 17 (Fall 1992): 87-93 Copyright "' 1992 87 REASON PAPERS NO. 17 own nature requires. Rand, on the other hand, justifies her interpersonal ethics by demonstrating the effect that acting on the proper principles will have directly on your own life. (2) Machan uses the concept of rights in interpersonal eth- ics, i.e., in morally guiding an individual's actions towards others.
    [Show full text]
  • Tara Smith's Ayn Rand's Normative Ethics
    Review Essay: Tara Smith’s Ayn Rand’s Normative Ethics: The Virtuous Egoist Carrie-Ann Biondi Marymount Manhattan College There has been in academic philosophy a resurgence of naturalistic virtue ethics that renders it a viable competitor with deontology and utilitarianism, making the timing opportune for the appearance of Tara Smith’s Ayn Rand’s Normative Ethics: The Virtuous Egoist.1 Indeed, Smith in part situates her book within this trend, but also contrasts her explication of how Rand’s rational ethical egoism intersects with virtue theories that have at best “danced around the edges of egoism” (p. 1). Thus far, Smith’s book has been generally well received in the few reviews it has gotten,2 especially by scholars and advocates of Rand’s Objectivism. However, some attention from mainstream philosophers, even by those who are sympathetic readers,3 reveals that contemporary moral philosophers struggle to understand the nuanced value theory underlying Objectivism and are slow to embrace full-fledged egoism. This is hardly surprising, given that many (if not most) ethics 1 Tara Smith, Ayn Rand’s Normative Ethics: The Virtuous Egoist (New York: Cambridge University Press, 2006). 2 See Stephen Hicks, “Review of Tara Smith’s Ayn Rand’s Normative Ethics: The Virtuous Egoist,” Philosophy in Review 27, no. 5 (October 2007), pp. 377-79; Helen Cullyer, “Review of Tara Smith’s Ayn Rand’s Normative Ethics: The Virtuous Egoist,” Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews (November 12, 2006), accessed online at: http://ndpr.nd.edu/review.cfm?id=8123; Robert Mayhew, “Review of Tara Smith’s Ayn Rand’s Normative Ethics: The Virtuous Egoist,” Philosophical Books 49, no.
    [Show full text]
  • Beyond Reductionism: Reconsidering the Right to Privacy
    BEYOND REDUCTIONISM: RECONSIDERING THE RIGHT TO PRIVACY Amy L. Peikoff∗ INTRODUCTION ........................................................................................2 I. A SKETCH OF RAND’S VALIDATION OF INDIVIDUAL RIGHTS...............................................................................................5 II. THE RIGHT TO PROPERTY AS FUNDAMENTAL................................14 III. SHOULD THERE BE A LEGAL RIGHT TO PRIVACY? ........................20 A. Any Law Protecting a Right to Privacy Would be Non-Objective, and Thus Unjust. ..........................................20 B. Laws Directed Specifically at Invasions of Privacy Tend, in Their Application and Proliferation, to Erode Fundamental Rights to Liberty and Property ....................................................................24 ∗ Assistant Professor of Philosophy, United States Air Force Academy, J.D., Univer- sity of California Los Angeles School of Law, Ph.D. in Philosophy, University of Southern California. Thank you to S.A. Lloyd, Tara Smith and participants in the Anthem Foundation Workshop at the University of Texas at Austin, Philosophy Department, Spring 2004, for comments on earlier drafts of this piece. 1 2 N.Y.U. Journal of Law & Liberty [Vol. 3:1 1. “Decisional” Privacy – Roe v. Wade and its progeny.......................................................................................... 26 2 “Informational” Privacy Cases: Eroding the Right to Property .......................................................................... 34 IV. RECOMMENDATION.......................................................................
    [Show full text]
  • A Philosophical Approach to Business Education
    The Canadian Journal of Higher Education, Vol. XXII-2, 1992 La revue canadienne d'enseignement supérieur, Vol. XXII-2, 1992 A Philosophical Approach to Business Education JAANA WOICESHYN * Abstract Business education has been blamed for deficiencies in the leadership, decision- making and ethical conduct of business managers. The quantitative and analyti- cal orientation in business school curricula and the consequent lack of humani- ties-based courses have been identified as reasons. The fundamental reason, however, lies in the philosophy of business research and education which shapes the curricula, teaching methods, and ultimately the graduates' ability to handle various managerial functions. The most commonly recognized philosophical basis of business research is empiricism. The argument presented here is that pragmatism, which shares ele- ments with empiricism, has also significantly shaped business education. This paper is an attempt to show why empiricism, together with pragmatism, are the root causes of the above deficiencies. Supplementing business school curricula with humanities courses, a strategy often recommended to correct for the defi- ciencies, is not sufficient. As an alternative solution, an objective philosophical approach is evaluated, along with its practical implications for business educa- tion. Résumé La formation en administration est souvent blâmée pour les lacunes rencon- trées chez les gentionnaires en regard des habiletés de chef de file et de prise de décision, et par-rapport à l'éthique professionelle. On attribue généralement ces lacunes à l'orientation strictement quantitative et analytique des pro- grammes d'études et à l'absence de contenus provenant des disciplines des let- tres et des sciences humaines. Cette communication, cependant, suggère que ces lacunes s'expliquent avant tout par la philosophie sous-jacente à la recherche en administration et en éducation sur laquelle reposent les pro- grammes d'etudes, les méthodes d'enseignement, et utimement, les habiletés des * University of Calgary.
    [Show full text]
  • 200306 IMPACT02.Qxd
    Volume 9, Number 6, June 2003 Local Activism: Introducing Ayn Rand’s In the Media: Dr. Brook on PBS In May 2002 Dr. Yaron Brook was a panelist on Books Into Texas Schools The McCuistion Program; the topic was “The Israel-Palestine Conflict: Solutions for Peace.” That program re-aired last month, at various The Houston Objectivism Society (HOS), an At one school she suggested that her times, on PBS and cable channels throughout independent community group that promotes the department obtain copies of Anthem and Ayn the country. study of Ayn Rand’s philosophy, has long Rand’s play Night of January 16th. As a result, supported ARI’s projects. For several years a fellow teacher is using them in class, “because . and on Fox News Channel HOS has amplified the effect of our high school she saw them on the shelves, and she remem- On April 27 Dr. Brook was interviewed on the essay contest on Anthem and The Fountainhead bered me telling her how much my students Fox News Channel show At Large With by sponsoring prizes for contest winners in the enjoyed the books,” said Ms. Wich. Geraldo. He discussed the dangers of an Houston area. Since 1995 the members of HOS Iranian-backed attempt to install an Islamic have given more than $18,000 in scholarship Books Quickly Win Fans Among Students theocracy in post-war Iraq. money to local winners. The overwhelming response to Though the efforts of HOS Anthem and The Fountainhead, . and on C-SPAN have helped to encourage teachers she continued, “was extremely In April Dr.
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophical Foundations of Capitalism
    Capitalism and Morality _________________________ Philosophical Foundations of Capitalism Edward W. Younkins Professor of Accountancy Wheeling Jesuit University The power of ideas is great. If we are to educate, persuade, and convert others to free-market thinking, we need to articulate, in structured form, the conceptual and moral foundations of free enterprise. We are obliged to expound a coherent and consistent body of principles that are in accord with reality and that properly reflect and explain capitalism. In other words, we must approach the idea of free enterprise from a philosophical point of view. The survival of free enterprise may be in jeopardy unless people understand its conceptual and moral foundations. Capitalism is a rational doctrine based on a clear understanding of man and society in which economics, politics, and morality (all parts of one inseparable truth) are found to be in harmony with one another. Capitalism as defined in this essay involves that set of economic arrangements that would exist in a society in which the state’s only function would be to prevent one person from using force or fraud against another person. The enclosed exhibit provides an example model or diagram of the conceptual foundations of capitalism that are consistent with the nature of man and the world. The development of a conceptual framework is a natural endeavor that is undertaken in most areas that have claims to be called scientific or based on real world conditions. Frameworks for thinking about reality have long been the basis for organized knowledge. Constructing a set of ideas about real world objects, events, and occurrences would serve as a framework for a realistic political and economic system.
    [Show full text]
  • Greenspan and the Cult of Ayn Rand: Don't Reappoint 'The Undertaker'
    Click here for Full Issue of EIR Volume 26, Number 43, October 29, 1999 Greenspan and the cult of Ayn Rand: Don’t reappoint ‘the undertaker’ by Kathy Wolfe The quiet and unassuming Federal Reserve Chairman enters Greenspan, by his testimony, the testimony of his friends and the hearing in one of his two-dozen identical, 1950s-cut, navy family, and by the results you can see out your window, has blue suits, and leans his head on his hand, index finger up. been slowly and methodically acting to rip down the heavy “Alan Greenspan is the greatest central banker in the history industrial economy of the United States. His spokesmanship of the United States and therefore, by definition, is the greatest for the “leaders of business and industry” has been a facade. central banker in the history of the world,” a Senator such as Banking Committee Chairman Phil Gramm (R-Tex.) will say When the lights of New York go out before Greenspan testifies, as Gramm did on July 28, adding: Since 1952, Greenspan has been the leading disciple of “Your utterances have become somewhat like the Bible.” the Russian-born Hollywood writer Ayn Rand, whose 1957 Unless Greenspan is reappointed when his term as Fed novel Atlas Shrugged presents a detailed blueprint for slowly chairman runs out in June 2000, Gramm, Rep. James Leach and silently tearing down the industrial plant and infrastruc- (R-Iowa), Rep. Paul Ryan (R-Wisc.), and others insist—in- ture of the United States, in favor of a “post-industrial” soci- deed, unless President Clinton reappoints him early—the cur- ety.
    [Show full text]
  • Leighton Smith
    LLEIGHTONEIGHTON SSMITHMITH: WWhathat mmakesakes hhimim ttick?ick? – IInterviewnterview IInsidenside SSUEUE BBRADFORDRADFORD: WWhyhy iiss sshehe ssmackingmacking pparents!arents! OR F F R S E SSOCIALISTOCIALIST SSWEDENWEDEN: WWhyhy ddoesoes iitt wwork?ork? E W D O O L GGODOD: Dawkins explodes the delusion! M B 7474 JJOHNOHN KKEYEY: Anything there? NZ $8.50 March - April 2007 After the release of the report on global warming prepared by the United Nations’ Intergovernmental Panel on Climate Change, the call for a new environmental body to slow global warming and protect the planet -- a body that potentially could have policing powers to punish violators -- was led by French President Jacques Chirac. The meaning of this “effort” is that Chirac is attempting to make an international crime out of attempts to increase production and raise living standards. I am not surprised by this attempt to criminalize productive activity. In fact, I predicted it. - George Reisman, p.16 The NNooseoEEnvironmentalnvoirosnmeen tal iiss TTighteningightening NOT EXTRA: “Global Warming: The panic is offi cially over” - Monckton TAXPAYER FUNDED Subscribe NOW To The Free Radical Dear Reader, Said former editor Lindsay Perigo: Said Samuel Adams, “It does not An army of principle will penetrate The Free Radical is fearless, “How do we get government as require a majority to prevail, but where an army of soldiers cannot; it will succeed where diplomatic freedom-loving and brim-full of it might be & ought to be? It will rather an irate, tireless minority management would fail; it is great writing and good reading take a revolution inside people’s keen to set brush fi res in people’s neither the Rhine, the Channel, nor the ocean that can arrest – writing that challenges all the heads.” The Free Radical is fully minds.” The Free Radical is where its progress; it will march on the sacred cows, and gets you committed to that revolution that irate, tireless minority speaks horizon of the world ..
    [Show full text]
  • Tara Smith's Ayn Rand's Normative Ethics: a Positive Contribution?
    Reason Papers Vol. 35, no. 1 Response to Eyal Mozes, “Tara Smith’s Ayn Rand’s Normative Ethics: A Positive Contribution?” Carrie-Ann Biondi Marymount Manhattan College Irfan Khawaja Felician College 1. Introduction In this discussion note, we respond to Eyal Mozes’s critique of Tara Smith’s Ayn Rand’s Normative Ethics via his criticism of Carrie-Ann Biondi’s review of that book in Reason Papers.1 We take issue with Mozes’s discussion of Ayn Rand’s non-conflicts-of-interest principle (NCIP) along with his discussion of the nature of moral virtue. We end by taking issue with his inappropriately moralized conception of philosophical discourse. Since we agree with many (though not all) of Mozes’s claims about emergencies and the scope of morality, we leave those topics undiscussed. 2. Conflicts of Interest Mozes offers two objections to Smith’s discussion of the NCIP: For any book that purports to be a presentation of Rand’s normative ethics, a crucial part of its task is to give an elaborate explanation and defense of Rand’s no-conflicts-of-interest-principle, filling in the details of Rand’s own cursory discussion. In evaluating such a book, I don’t think there’s any question more important than how well it succeeds in explaining and defending this principle. Ayn Rand’s Normative Ethics disgracefully fails in this task.2 We reject every element of this criticism. 1 Tara Smith, Ayn Rand’s Normative Ethics: The Virtuous Egoist (New York: Cambridge University Press, 2006), hereafter ARNE; Carrie-Ann Biondi, “Review Essay: Tara Smith’s Ayn Rand’s Normative Ethics: The Virtuous Egoist,” Reason Papers 30 (Fall 2008), pp.
    [Show full text]
  • John Dewey, Maria Montessori, and Objectivist Educational Philosophy During the Postwar Years
    73 Historical Studies in Education / Revue d’histoire de l’éducation ARTICLES / ARTICLES “The Ayn Rand School for Tots”: John Dewey, Maria Montessori, and Objectivist Educational Philosophy during the Postwar Years Jason Reid ABSTRACT Objectivism, the libertarian philosophy established by Ayn Rand during the postwar years, has attracted a great deal of attention from philosophers, political scientists, economists, and English professors alike in recent years, but has not received much notice from historians with an interest in education. This article will address that problem by discussing how Rand and her followers established a philosophy of education during the 1960s and 1970s that was based, in part, on vilifying the so-called collectivist ideas of John Dewey and lionizing the so-called individualist ideas of Maria Montessori. Unfortunately, the narrative that emerged during this time seriously misrepresented the ideas of both Dewey and Montessori, resulting in a some- what distorted view of both educators. RÉSUMÉ L’objectivisme, philosophie libertaire conçue par Ayn Rand dans la période de l’après-guerre, a suscitée beaucoup d’attention de la part des philosophes, politologues, économistes et profes- seurs de littérature anglaise, mais rien de tel chez les historiens de l’éducation. Cet article cor- rige cette lacune, en montrant comment durant les années 1960 et 1970 Rand et ses partisans ont établi une philosophie de l’éducation qui s’appuyait, en partie, sur la diffamation des idées prétendues collectivistes de John Dewey et l’idolâtrie de l’individualisme de Maria Montessori. Malheureusement, leurs travaux ont donné une fausse image des idées de Dewey et Montessori et conséquemment ont déformé les théories ces deux éducateurs.
    [Show full text]