The Cambridge Companion to Augustine the Cambridge Companion to Augustine

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

The Cambridge Companion to Augustine the Cambridge Companion to Augustine THE CAMBRIDGE COMPANION TO AUGUSTINE THE CAMBRIDGE COMPANION TO AUGUSTINE EDITED BY ELEONORE STUMP St. Louis University AND NORMAN KRETZMANN published by the press syndicate of the university of cambridge The Pitt Building, Trumpington Street, Cambridge, United Kingdom cambridge university press The Edinburgh Building, Cambridge cb2 2ru, UK www.cup.cam.ac.uk 40 West 20th Street, New York, NY 10011–4211, USA www.cup.org 10 Stamford Road, Oakleigh, Melbourne 3166, Australia Ruiz de Alarcón 13, 28014 Madrid, Spain © Cambridge University Press 2001 This book is in copyright. Subject to statutory exception and to the provisions of relevant collective licensing agreements, no reproduction of any part may take place without the written permission of Cambridge University Press. First published 2001 Typeface Sabon MT 10/13pt System QuarkXPress™ [se] A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library isbn 0 521 65018 6 hardback isbn 0 521 65985 x paperback Transferred to digital printing 2003 CONTENTS List of contributors page ix Preface xiii List of abbreviations xiv Introduction 1 1 Augustine: his time and lives 8 james j. o’donnell 2 Faith and reason 26 john rist 3 Augustine on evil and original sin 40 william e. mann 4 Predestination, Pelagianism, and foreknowledge 49 james wetzel 5 Biblical interpretation 59 thomas williams 6 The divine nature 71 scott macdonald 7 De Trinitate 91 mary t. clark 8 Time and creation in Augustine 103 simo knuuttila 9 Augustine’s theory of soul 116 roland teske 10 Augustine on free will 124 eleonore stump vii contents 11 Augustine’s philosophy of memory 148 roland teske 12 The response to skepticism and the mechanisms of cognition 159 gerard o’daly 13 Knowledge and illumination 171 gareth b. matthews 14 Augustine’s philosophy of language 186 christopher kirwan 15 Augustine’s ethics 205 bonnie kent 16 Augustine’s political philosophy 234 paul weithman 17 Augustine and medieval philosophy 253 m. w. f. stone 18 Post-medieval Augustinianism 267 gareth b. matthews Bibliography 280 Index 297 viii CONTRIBUTORS mary t. clark, RSCJ is Professor Emeritus of Philosophy at Manhattanville College. Among her books on Augustine are Augustine, Philosopher of Freedom; Augustinian Personalism; Augustine, An Introduction to His Thought. She also wrote the Analytical Introduction to and translation of Marius Victorinus: Theological Treatises on the Trinity. Her articles on Augustine have been published in Augustinian Studies; Revue des etudes Augustiniennes; Augustinus; and Studia Patristica. bonnie kent is an Associate Professor of Philosophy at Syracuse University and the author of Virtues of the Will: The Transformation of Ethics in the Late Thirteenth Century. Her articles include “Moral Provincialism” and “Moral Growth and the Unity of the Virtues.” christopher kirwan is Emeritus Fellow in Philosophy at Exeter College, Oxford. He is author of Augustine in the Arguments of the Philosophers series, and his articles include “Augustine on Souls and Bodies” and “Avoiding Sin: Augustine against Consequentialism.” simo knuuttila is Research Professor in the Academy of Finland and Professor of Theological Ethics and the Philosophy of Religion at the University of Helsinki. He is the editor of The New Synthese Historical Library and the author of Modalities in Medieval Philosophy and many articles on the history of logic, semantics, the philosophy of mind, and philosophical theology. scott macdonald is Professor of Philosophy and Norma K. Regan Professor in Christian Studies at Cornell University. His many publications in medieval philosophy include “Primal Sin” and “Aquinas’s Incompatibilist Account of Free Choice,” and he has recently co-edited (with Eleonore Stump) Aquinas’s Moral Theory. He edits the journal Medieval Philosophy and Theology. ix list of contributors william e. mann is Professor of Philosophy at the University of Vermont. He has written extensively on topics in medieval philosophy and the philosophy of religion. His recent articles include “Inner-Life Ethics” (on Augustine) and “Duns Scotus on Natural and Supernatural Knowledge of God” in The Cambridge Companion to Duns Scotus. gareth b. matthews is Professor of Philosophy at the University of Massachusetts, Amherst. He is the author of Thought’s Ego in Augustine and Descartes and the editor of The Augustinian Tradition. gerard o’daly is Professor of Latin at University College London. He is the author of Plotinus’ Philosophy of the Self, Augustine’s Philosophy of Mind, The Poetry of Boethius, and Augustine’s ‘City of God’: A Reader’s Guide, and is on the editorial board of the Augustinus-Lexikon. james j. o’donnell is Professor of Classical Studies and Vice Provost for Information Systems and Computing at the University of Pennsylvania. He is author of a three-volume edition of and commentary on the Confessions and more recently of Avatars of the Word: From Papyrus to Cyberspace. john rist is Professor Emeritus of Classics and Philosophy at the University of Toronto. He is author of various books and articles mostly on ancient phi- losophy and patristics, including Eros and Psyche, Plotinus: The Road to Reality, and Augustine: Ancient Thought Baptized. m. w. f. stone is Lecturer in the Philosophy of Religion, King’s College London. He is the editor with Jill Kraye of Humanism and Early Modern Philosophy and author of the two-volume work, The Subtle Arts of Casuistry. He has published articles on late medieval philosophy and early modern scholasticism. eleonore stump is the Robert J. Henle, S.J., Professor of Philosophy at Saint Louis University. She has written extensively on various topics in medieval philosophy as well as in philosophy of religion and metaphysics. Her books include Boethius’s De topicis differentiis, Boethius’s In Ciceronis Topica, and Dialectic and Its Place in the Development of Medieval Logic. Her recent articles include “Ockham on Sensory Cognition,” in the Cambridge Companion to Ockham, “Aquinas on Justice,” and “Saadya Gaon and the Problem of Evil.” roland teske, S.J., is Professor of Philosophy at Marquette University in Milwaukee. He is author of Paradoxes of Time in St. Augustine and of many articles on Augustine and on William of Auvergne. He has also translated six volumes of the works of Augustine, including all the anti-Pelagian writings. x list of contributors paul weithman is Associate Professor of Philosophy at the University of Notre Dame. He has published articles in medieval political theory, contem- porary political philosophy, religious ethics, and medical ethics. He is the editor of Religion and Contemporary Liberalism and the co-editor, with Henry Richardson, of the five-volume The Philosophy of Rawls. james wetzel is Associate Professor of Philosophy and Religion at Colgate University. His publications include Augustine and the Limits of Virtue, “Snares of Truth: Augustine on Free Will and Predestination,” in Augustine and his Critics, ed. Robert Dodaro and George Lawless, and “Time After Augustine.” thomas williams is Assistant Professor of Philosophy at the University of Iowa. His work in medieval philosophy includes articles on John Duns Scotus and translations of Augustine’s On Free Choice of the Will and Anselm’s Proslogion and Monologion. xi PREFACE When this project was conceived, Norman Kretzmann had had multiple myeloma for a long time; but he and I were fairly confident that he would live long enough to hold the finished book in his hand. As it turned out, that did not happen. The disease took a sudden turn for the worse, and he died on 1 August, 1998. His death was a great loss for the field of medieval philosophy, as well as for philosophy of religion, where his influence was also widely felt. His death was an incalculable loss for me. He was my teacher, my mentor, and my friend; and everything I did, I did better because of him. Although I finished this project without him, it is entirely fitting that his name should appear on the book as co- editor. He and I shared in conceiving and launching the project, and his stamp and influence are apparent everywhere in it. No doubt the final product would have looked different if he had been able to participate in all its stages; but I think that, if he could have seen it, he would have been very pleased with this volume as it stands. More ordinary debts also need to be acknowledged here. Hilary Gaskin, the Cambridge University Press editor for this series, was helpful at every stage of the process of production, and the volume is much better for her input to it. My secretary Betty Andrews is responsible for whatever organization there was in the process that begins with commissioning chapters and finishes with the acknowl- edgment of the final drafts. Bryan Cross suffered with the task of producing harmony across chapters in the citations of Augustine’s works, and Chris Pliatska labored at the bibliography and the proofs. I am very grateful for all these contributions to the volume. The final stages of this volume were completed at the National Humanities Center, where I was a Lilly Foundation Fellow for the academic year 1999–2000. It is hard to imagine a more pleasant environment in which to work, or one more conducive to research, than the National Humanities Center, and I am grateful to the Center and to the Lilly Foundation for my year there. Eleonore Stump xiii LIST OF ABBREVIATIONS Series CCSL Corpus Christianorum, Series Latina CSEL Corpus Scriptorum Ecclesiasticorum Latinorum PL Patrologia Latina Titles of Augustine’s works Adnotat. in Job Adnotationes in Job Conf. Confessiones C. Acad. Contra Academicos C. ep. Pelag. Contra duas epistolas Pelagianorum C. ep. fund. Contra epistulam Manichaei quam vocant fundamenti C. Faust. Contra Faustum Manichaeum C. Gaud. Contra Gaudentium Donatistarum episcopum C. Max. Contra Maximinum Arianorum episcopum C. Mend. Contra Mendacium C.
Recommended publications
  • RELG 399 Fall2019
    McGill University School of Religious Studies RELG 399 TEXTS OF CHRISTIAN SPIRITUALITY (Late Antiquity) In the Fall Term of 2019 this seminar course will focus on Christian spirituality in Late Antiquity with close study and interpretation of Aurelius Augustine’s spiritual odyssey the Confessiones, his account of creation in De genesi ad litteram, and his handbook of hermeneutics De doctrina Christiana. We will also read Ancius Manlius Severinus Boethius’s treatment of theodicy in De consolatione philosophiae, his De Trinitate, and selections from De Musica. Professor: Torrance Kirby Office Hours: Birks 206, Tuesdays/Thursdays, 10:00–11:00 am Email: [email protected] Birks Building, Room 004A Tuesdays/Thursdays 4:05–5:25 pm COURSE SYLLABUS—FALL TERM 2019 Date Reading 3 September INTRODUCTION 5 September Aurelius Augustine, Confessiones Book I, Early Years 10 September Book II, Theft of Pears 12 September Book III, Adolescence and Student Life 17 September Book IV, Manichee and Astrologer 19 September Book V, Carthage, Rome, and Milan *Confirm Mid-Term Essay Topics (1500-2000 words) (NB Consult the Style Sheet, essay-writing guidelines and evaluation rubric in the appendix to the syllabus.) 24 September Book VI, Secular Ambitions and Conflicts 26 September Book VII, Neoplatonic Quest for the Good 1 October Book VIII, Tolle, lege; tolle, lege 3 October Book IX, Vision at Ostia 8 October Book X, 1-26 Memory *Mid-term Essays due at beginning of class. Essay Conferences to be scheduled for week of 21 October 10 October Book X, 27-43 “Late have I loved you” 15 October Book XI, Time and Eternity 17 October Book XII, Creation Essay Conferences begin this week, Birks 206.
    [Show full text]
  • 1 of 3 Ethics: Consequentialism-Utilitarianism Ethics Script: Consequentialism & Utilitarianism Slide 2 {Introduction To
    Ethics Script: Consequentialism & Utilitarianism slide 2 {Introduction to the Theory of Consequentialism} There are two basic principles within the theory of consequentialism: (1) an action’s ethicality depends only on the results of that action, and (2) the more “good” (and less harmful) results an action produces, the better (or more right) the act is. You already know the basic idea behind this concept as “the end justifies the means.” slide 3 {How it Works… and Doesn’t Work} While actions tend to be brief and immediate, the consequences of those actions can have long-term—even permanent—effects. A consequentialist would expect that you (and everyone else) consider the implications of your actions in terms of a “good” or “right” outcome. Consequentialism itself doesn’t define which consequences are “good.” It’s up to you to decide what is right and wrong on a personal basis. Two consequentialists can look at the same choice and completely disagree on the action that should be taken… like in the case of an assisted suicide or how to deal with a pandemic. But they are more likely to agree on what kind of action should be taken in order to help a lost child so some actions are easier to agree on than others. slide 4 {Utilitarianism a Model of Consequentialism and Introduction to Mr. Bentham} The most popular consequentialist model, Utilitarianism, accounts for ambiguities that consequentialism alone does not. Utilitarianism emerged in the early 19th century with British philosopher and “hedonist” Jeremy Bentham, who aimed to assess whether or not Parliament was passing fair and ethical laws at the time.
    [Show full text]
  • Why Retributivism Needs Consequentialism: the Rightful Place of Revenge in the Criminal Justice System
    Louisiana State University Law Center LSU Law Digital Commons Journal Articles Faculty Scholarship 2014 Why Retributivism Needs Consequentialism: The Rightful Place of Revenge in the Criminal Justice System Ken Levy Louisiana State University Law Center, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.law.lsu.edu/faculty_scholarship Part of the Law Commons Repository Citation Levy, Ken, "Why Retributivism Needs Consequentialism: The Rightful Place of Revenge in the Criminal Justice System" (2014). Journal Articles. 67. https://digitalcommons.law.lsu.edu/faculty_scholarship/67 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Faculty Scholarship at LSU Law Digital Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Journal Articles by an authorized administrator of LSU Law Digital Commons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Forthcoming in Rutgers L. Rev. (spring 2014) Why Retributivism Needs Consequentialism: The Rightful Place of Revenge in the Criminal Justice System KEN LEVY* TABLE OF CONTENTS I. Introduction ..................................................................................................... 2 II. The Main Goals of the Criminal Justice System ....................................... 10 A. The First Primary Goal of the Criminal Justice System: Crime Minimization ................................................................................................. 11 B. The Second Primary Goal of the Criminal Justice System: Retribution ....................................................................................................
    [Show full text]
  • Consequentialism and Moral Responsibility
    Consequentialism and Moral Responsibility Draft of September 2015 Elinor Mason For Christian Seidel (ed.) Consequentialism: new directions, new problems? OUP, forthcoming. There are two different ways of thinking about the relationship between consequentialism and moral responsibility. First, we might think that consequentialism can give us an account of responsibility. I discuss this possibility briefly, and then set it aside. The other way of thinking about the relationship is the focus of this paper. The question that concerns me, is, to what extent is a normative theory, consequentialism in particular, constrained by requirements that stem from concerns about responsibility? 1. Consequentialist Accounts of Moral Responsibility J.J.C. Smart suggests that we can extend consequentialist reasoning about morality to reasoning about responsibility. One of the attractions of consequentialism is that it provides such a straightforward and attractive account of justification for our moral practices. Why do we pay our taxes, treat each other with respect, look after each other and so on? Because doing so has good consequences. However, this sort of justification, though very appealing when considering moral practice, becomes extremely counterintuitive in other sorts of case. For example, it seems obvious that justification for beliefs cannot be consequentialist. Beliefs must be justified in some way that relates to their truth, though of course there is disagreement about exactly what makes a belief justified. Similarly, so a familiar line of thought goes, whether or not someone is responsible for an act, or for anything else, cannot be determined by looking at the consequences of holding them responsible. The claim that 1 responsibility can be understood in a consequentialist way seems like a category mistake.1 Smart’s view might be correct that, insofar as praising and blaming are actions, consequentialists should take the value of the consequences of performing those acts as the relevant factor in deciding whether or not to perform them.
    [Show full text]
  • “Grounding and Omniscience” (PDF)
    Grounding and Omniscience Abstract I’m going to argue that omniscience is impossible and therefore that there is no God.1 The argument turns on the notion of grounding. After illustrating and clarifying that notion, I’ll start the argument in earnest. The first step will be to lay out five claims, one of which is the claim that there is an omniscient being, and the other four of which are claims about grounding. I’ll prove that these five claims are inconsistent. Then I’ll argue for the truth of each of them except the claim that there is an omniscient being. From these arguments it follows that there are no omniscient beings and thus that there is no God. §1. Stage Setting The best way to get a grip on the notion of grounding – or more exactly, for our purposes, the notion of partial grounding - is by considering examples. (By “partial grounding” I mean “at-least-partial grounding”, just as mereologists mean “at-least-part of” by “part of”.) The first example hearkens back to Plato’s Euthyphro. Suppose that a theorist claims that as a matter of metaphysical necessity, a given act is morally right if and only if it is approved of by God. At first blush at least, it is plausible that this theorist owes us an answer to following question: when acts are right, are they right because God approves of them, or does he approve of them because they are right? We all understand this question right away, right when we first hear it.
    [Show full text]
  • Metaphysics Today and Tomorrow*
    1 Metaphysics Today and Tomorrow* Raphaël Millière École normale supérieure, Paris – October 2011 Translated by Mark Ohm with the assistance of Leah Orth, Jon Cogburn, and Emily Beck Cogburn “By metaphysics, I do not mean those abstract considerations of certain imaginary properties, the principal use of which is to furnish the wherewithal for endless dispute to those who want to dispute. By this science I mean the general truths which can serve as principles for the particular sciences.” Malebranche Dialogues on Metaphysics and Religion 1. The interminable agony of metaphysics Throughout the twentieth century, numerous philosophers sounded the death knell of metaphysics. Ludwig Wittgenstein, Rudolf Carnap, Martin Heidegger, Gilbert Ryle, J. L. Austin, Jacques Derrida, Jürgen Habermas, Richard Rorty, and, henceforth, Hilary Putnam: a great many tutelary figures have extolled the rejection, the exceeding, the elimination, or the deconstruction of first philosophy. All these necrological chronicles do not have the same radiance, the same seriousness, nor the same motivations, but they all agree to dismiss the discipline, which in the past was considered “the queen of the sciences”, with a violence at times comparable to the prestige it commanded at the time of its impunity. Even today, certain philosophers hastily spread the tragic news with contempt for philosophical inquiry, as if its grave solemnity bestowed upon it some obviousness. Thus, Franco Volpi writes: ‘Grand metaphysics is dead!’ is the slogan which applies to the majority of contemporary philosophers, whether continentals or of analytic profession. They all treat metaphysics as a dead dog.1 In this way, the “path of modern thought” would declare itself vociferously “anti- metaphysical and finally post-metaphysical”.
    [Show full text]
  • The Foundations of Economic Personalism: Daniel Rush Finn Promise and Peril Saint John’S University
    Journal of Markets & Morality Volume 6, Number 2 (Fall 2003): 599–615 Copyright © 2003 The Foundations of Economic Personalism: Daniel Rush Finn Promise and Peril Saint John’s University The Acton Institute’s three-volume series on the Foundations of Economic Personalism contributes much to the dialogue between theology and economics. This article, however, identifies a number of shortcomings. These include an overly individualistic bias and a reliance on the Austrian school of economics that are not consonant with Christian and especially Catholic social thought on economic life. There is a certain naiveté about the philosophy of science and an artificial bifurcation between “economic” life (where values are assumed to be subjective) and the rest of life (where objective values are endorsed). The dia- logue between theology and economics is badly needed, but it requires a strong dose of self-criticism from all its participants. Introduction It is all too rare for theologians and economists to work seriously together. In an effort to overcome this unfortunate tendency, the Center for Economic Personalism at the Acton Institute commissioned and published a three- volume work titled Foundations of Economic Personalism. The first volume is entitled Beyond Self Interest: A Personalist Approach to Human Action, by Gregory R. Beabout, Ricardo F. Crespo, Stephen J. Grabill, Kim Paffenroth, and Kyle Swan. The second volume is Human Nature and the Discipline of Economics: Personalist Anthropology and Economic Methodology, by Patricia Donohue-White, Stephen J. Grabill, Christopher Westley, and Gloria Zúñiga. The third volume is entitled The Free Person and the Free Economy: 599 The Foundations of Economic Daniel Rush Finn Personalism: Promise and Peril A Personalist View of Market Economics, by Anthony J.
    [Show full text]
  • The Church and the People of God: Fragments of a Constitution Al History*
    THE CHURCH AND THE PEOPLE OF GOD: FRAGMENTS OF A CONSTITUTION AL HISTORY* By J.T. Me PARTLIN I THE re-appraisal of the place of the laity in the Church is well-known to be a task which at once arouses the suspicion and hostility of a certain type of Catholic: it eamed Newman himself a formal delation to Rome for heresy, l and the attitude of Newman' s opponents has unfortunately not disappeated with the passage of time, but remains to complicate still further an already sufficiently complex discussion. For some, to recom­ mend a new vision of the laity is nothing less than a chal1enge to the authority of the Church, cal1ing in question the collective wisdom of Catho1icism which has ordained the present relationship of the two orders. On the other hand, ie is now becoming painfully evident that a great deal of our present situation is due more to historical accident than to the considered decision of the Church, and that some of the Church's collective wisdom is thereby obscured rather than expressed - for in the recent past the Church has 'appeated above everything else to be a reli­ gious organisation for practical aims, of an outspoken juridical character. The mystical element in her, everything that stood behind the palpable aims and arrangements, everything that expressed itself in the concept of the Kingdom of God, of the mystical Body of Christ, would not be perceived at once.'2 The restoration of these hitherto obscured elements, moreover, is no merely academic question, for the needs of the modem world are now widely recognised to require a thoroughly activt;! partici­ pation of the laity in the Church' s life.
    [Show full text]
  • © in This Web Service Cambridge University
    Cambridge University Press 978-0-521-89754-9 - An Introduction to Medieval Theology Rik Van Nieuwenhove Index More information Index Abelard, Peter, 82, 84, 99–111, 116, 120 beatific vision, 41, 62, 191 Alain of Lille, 71 beatitude, 172, 195–96 Albert the Great, 171, 264 Beatrijs van Nazareth, 170 Alexander of Hales, 147, 211, 227 beguine movement, 170 allegory, 15, 43, 45, 47, 177 Benedict XII, Pope, 265 Amaury of Bène, 71 Benedict, St., 28–29, 42 Ambrose, 7, 10, 149 Berengar of Tours, 60, 83, 129, 160, see also amor ipse notitia est 51, 117, see love and knowledge Eucharist anagogy, 47 Bernard of Clairvaux, 79, 82, 100, 104, 110, 112–15, analogy, see univocity 147, 251 analogy in Aquinas, 182–85, 234, 235 critique of Abelard, 110–11 Anselm of Canterbury, 16, 30, 71, 78, 81, 83–98, on loving God, 112–14 204, 236 Boccaccio, Giovanni, 251 Anselm of Laon, 72, 99 Boethius, 29–33, 125, 137 Anthony, St., 27 Bonaventure, 34, 47, 123, 141, 146, 148, 170, 173, apophaticism, 8, 34, 271 176, 179, 211–24, 227, 228, 230, 232, 242, 243, Aquinas, 182–83 245, 254 Aquinas, 22, 24, 34, 47, 51, 72, 87, 89, 90, 133, 146, Boniface, Pope, 249 148, 151, 154, 164, 169, 171–210, 214, 225, 227, 230, 235, 236, 237, 238, 240, 241, 244, 246, Calvin, 14 254, 255, 257, 266 Carabine, Deirdre, 65 Arianism, 20, 21 Carthusians, 79 Aristotle, 9, 20, 29, 78, 84, 179, 181, 192, 195, 212, Cassian, John, 27–29, 47 213, 216, 223, 225, 226, 227, 229, 237, 254, Cassidorius, 124 267, 268 cathedral schools, 82, 169 Arts, 124, 222 Catherine of Siena, 251 and pedagogy (Hugh), 124–28
    [Show full text]
  • Satisficing Consequentialism Author(S): Michael Slote and Philip Pettit Source: Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volumes, Vol
    Satisficing Consequentialism Author(s): Michael Slote and Philip Pettit Source: Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volumes, Vol. 58 (1984), pp. 139-163+165-176 Published by: Blackwell Publishing on behalf of The Aristotelian Society Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/4106846 Accessed: 15/10/2008 09:26 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use. Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=black. Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission. JSTOR is a not-for-profit organization founded in 1995 to build trusted digital archives for scholarship. We work with the scholarly community to preserve their work and the materials they rely upon, and to build a common research platform that promotes the discovery and use of these resources. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. The Aristotelian Society and Blackwell Publishing are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volumes.
    [Show full text]
  • Divine Utilitarianism
    Liberty University DIVINE UTILITARIANISM A Thesis Presented in Partial Fulfillment Of the Requirements for the Masters of Arts in Philosophical Studies By Jimmy R. Lewis January 16, 2017 TABLE OF CONTENTS Chapter One: Introduction ……………………………...……………..……....3 Statement of the Problem…………………………….………………………….3 Statement of the Purpose…………………………….………………………….5 Statement of the Importance of the Problem…………………….……………...6 Statement of Position on the Problem………………………...…………….......7 Limitations…………………………………………….………………………...8 Development of Thesis……………………………………………….…………9 Chapter Two: What is meant by “Divine Utilitarianism”..................................11 Introduction……………………………….…………………………………….11 A Definition of God.……………………………………………………………13 Anselm’s God …………………………………………………………..14 Thomas’ God …………………………………………………………...19 A Definition of Utility .…………………………………………………………22 Augustine and the Good .……………………………………………......23 Bentham and Mill on Utility ……………………………………………25 Divine Utilitarianism in the Past .……………………………………………….28 New Divine Utilitarianism .……………………………………………………..35 Chapter Three: The Ethics of God ……………………………………………45 Divine Command Theory: A Juxtaposition .……………………………………45 What Divine Command Theory Explains ………………….…………...47 What Divine Command Theory Fails to Explain ………………………47 What Divine Utilitarianism Explains …………………………………………...50 Assessing the Juxtaposition .…………………………………………………....58 Chapter Four: Summary and Conclusion……………………………………...60 Bibliography……………………………………………………………………..64 2 CHAPTER ONE: INTRODUCTION Statement of the
    [Show full text]
  • Alienation, Consequentialism, and the Demands of Morality,” Peter Railton Introduces an Approach to Consequentialism That Has Since Become Influential
    1 Sophisticated Consequentialism and Psychological Coherence In “Alienation, Consequentialism, and the Demands of Morality,” Peter Railton introduces an approach to consequentialism that has since become influential. 1 His approach, which he calls ‘sophisticated consequentialism’, claims that a consequentialist ought to be motivated by whichever set of motivations will in fact lead to maximizing value, instead of being motivated to directly maximize value. As a result, a consequentialist might maximize value by having dispositions to commit acts that may not themselves maximize value. I concern myself here with the psychological tension that might exist in a person with such apparently conflicting commitments: how may a person that is, on one hand, committed to believing that consequences determine how people ought to act, on the other hand, be motivated to generally act in ways that pay no direct attention to consequences? In particular, I will argue that, on Railton's picture, a consequentialist must pay attention to two distinct and inconsistent sets of reasons. First, it is difficult to see how a person can really make decisions in that way, and second, a person situated in the way Railton imagines is not actually in a position to maximize value. But before I get to a more rigorous statement of what I will call the criticism from psychological incoherence, I need to lay the scene. The criticism from psychological incoherence is related to another objection to which Railton was directly responding, the alienation objection. I first set out this objection before moving to a statement of sophisticated consequentialism that handles the alienation objection.
    [Show full text]