The Perceptual Origin of Thematic Relations

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

The Perceptual Origin of Thematic Relations On the Acquisition of Lexical Entries: The Perceptual Origin of Thematic Relations James Pustejovsky Department of Computer Science Brandeis University Waltham, MA 02254 617-736-2709 jamesp~br andeis.csnet-relay Abstract that the conceptual abstraction of thematic information does not develop arbitrarily but along a given, predictable path; namely, a developmental path that starts with tan- This paper describes a computational model of concept gible perceptual predicates (e.g. spatial, causative) to acquisition for natural language. We develop a theory later form the more abstract mental and cognitive predi- of lexical semantics, the Eztended Aspect Calculus, which cates. In this view thematic relations are actually sets of together with a ~maxkedness theory" for thematic rela- thematic properties, related by a partial ordering. This tions, constrains what a possible word meaning can be. effectively establishes a maxkedness theory for thematic This is based on the supposition that predicates from the roles that a learning system must adhere to in the acqui- perceptual domain axe the primitives for more abstract sition of lexical entries for a larlguage. relations. We then describe an implementation of this We will discuss two computational methods for model, TULLY, which mirrors the stages of lexical acqui- concept development in natural language: sition for children. (1) F~ature Relaxation of particular features of the ar- guments to a verb. This is performed by a con- straint propagation method. I. Introduction (2) Thematic Decoupling of semantically incorporated In this paper we describe a computational model of con- information from the verb. cept acquisition for natural language making use of po- When these two learning techniques are combined with sitive-only data, modelled on a theory of lexical seman- the model of lexical semantics adopted here, the stages tics. This theory, the Eztende~t Aspect Calculus acts to- of development for verb acquisition are similar to those gether with a maxkedness theory for thematic roles to acknowledged for child language acquisition. constrain what a possible word type is, just as a gram- mar defines what a well-formed tree structure is in syntax. We argue that linguistic specific knowledge and learning principles are needed for concept acquisition from positive 2. Learnabillty Theory and Concept De- evidence alone: Furthermore, this model posits a close in- velopment teraction between the predicates of visual perception and the early semantic interpretation of thematic roles as used Work in machine learning has shown the useful- in linguistic expressions. In fact, we claim that these re- ness to an inductive concept-learning system of inducing lations act as constraints to the development of predicate "bias" in the learning process (cf. [Mitchell 1977, 1978], hierachies in language acquisition. Finally, we describe [Michalski 1983]). An even more promising development TULLY, an implementation of this model in ZETALXSP is the move to base the bias on domain-intensive models, and discuss its design in the context of machine learning as seen in [Mitchell et al. 1985], [Utgoff 1985], and [Win- research. ston et al. 1983 I. This is an important direction for those concerned with natural language acquisition, as it con- There has been little work on the acquisition of verges with a long-held belief of many psychologists and thematic relation and case roles, due to the absence of linguists that domain-specific information is necessary for any consensus on their formal properties. In this research learning (cf. [Slobin 1982], [Pinker 1984], {Bowerman we begin to address what a theory of thematic relations 1974], [Chomsky 1980]). Indeed, Berwick (1984) moves in might look like, using learnabUity theory as a metric for exactly this direction. Berwick describes a model for the evaluating the model. We claim that there is an impor- acquisition of syntactic knowledge based on a restricted tant relationship between visual or imagistic perception X-syntactic parser, a modification of the Marcus parser and the development of thematic relations in linguistic us- ([Marcus 1980]). The domain knowledge specified to the age for a child. This has been argued recently by Jackend- system in this case is a parametric parser and learning off (1983, 1985) and was an assumption in the pioneering system that adapts to a particular linguistic environment, work of Miller and Johnson-Laird (1976). Here we argue given only positive data. This is just the sort of biasing necessary to account for data on syntactic acquisition. 172 One area of language acquisition that has not been How does this principle relate to lexical seman- sufficientlyaddressed within computational models is the tics and the way thematic relations are mapped to syn- acquisition of conceptual structure. For language acquisi- tactic positions? We claim that the connection is very tion, the problem can be stated as follows: How does the direct. Concept learning begins with spatial, temporal, child identify a particular thematic role with a specific and causal predicates being the most salient. This follows grammatical function in the sentence? This is the prob- from our supposition that these are innate structures, or lem of mapping the semantic functions of a proposition are learned very early. Following Miller and Johnson- into specified syntactic positions in a sentence. Laird (1976), [Miller 1985], and most psychologists, we Pinker (1984) makes an interestingsuggestion (due assume the prelinguistic child is already able to discern originally to D. Lebeaux) in answer to this question. He spatial orientations, causation, and temporal dependen- proposes that one of the strategies available to the lan- cies. We take this as a point of departure for our theory guage learner involves a sort of ~template matching" of of markedness, which is developed in the next section. argument to syntactic position. There are canonicalcon- j~gurat{ortsthat are the default mappings and non-cano- 3.0 Theoretical Assumptions nicoJ mappings for the exceptions. For example, the tem- plate consists of two rows, one of thematic roles, and the 3.1 The Extended Aspect Calculus other of syntactic positions. A canonical mapping exists In this section we outline the semantic framework if no lines joining the two rows cross. Figure 1 shows a which defines our domain for lexical acquisition. In the canonical mapping representing the sentence in (1), while current linguistic literature on case roles or thematic re- Figure 2 illustratesa noncanonical mapping representing lations, there is littlediscussion on what logical connec- sentence (2). tion exists between one e-role and another. Besides being the workhorse for motivating several principles of syn- tax (cf. [Chomsky 1981], [Willi~ms 1980]) the most that 0-roles: ~~L is claimed is that Universal Grammar specifies a reper- toire of thematic relations (or case roles), Agent, Theme, Syntactic roles: SUBJ OBJ OBL Patient, Goal, Source, Instrument, and that every NP must carry one and only one role. It should be remem- Figure 1 bered, however, that thematic relations were originally conceived in terms of the argument positions of seman- tic predicates such as CAUSE and DO. * That is a verb e-roles: A Th G/S/L didn't simply have a list of labelled arguments 2 such as Agent and Patient,but had an interpretation in terms of Syntactic ro~O BL more primitive predicates where the notions Agent and Patient were defined. The causer of an event (following Jackendoff (1976)) is defined as an Agent, for example, Figure 2 c ,4u s E(=, ,) -. Ag,.~(=). Similarly, the first argument position of the pred- (1) Mary hit Bill. icate GO is interpreted as Theme, as in GO(=,y,z). The (2) Bill was hit by Mary. second argument here is the SOURCE and the third is called the GOAL. The model we have in mind acts to constrain the With this principle we can represent the productivity of space of possible word meanings. In this sense it is similar verb forms that are used but not heard by the child. We to Dowty's aspect calculus but goes beyond it in embed- will adopt a modified version of the canonical mapping ding his model within a markedness theory for thematic strategy for our system, and embed it within a theory of how perceptual primitives help derive linguisticconcepts. types. Our model is a first-orderlogic that employs sym- bols acting as special operators over the standard logical As mentioned, one of the motivations for adopt- vocabulary. These are taken from three distinct semantic ing the canonical mapping principle is the power it gives fields. They are: causal, spatial, and aspectual. a learning system in the face of positive-only data. In terms of learnability theory, Berwick (1985) (following The predicates associated with the causal field are [Angluin 1978]) notes that to ensure successful acquisi- Cau~e, (C,), C~se~ (C2), and l.stru,ne.t(I). The spatial field has only one predicate, which is predicated tion of the language after a finite number of positive ex- Locatiue, of an object we term the Th~me. Finally, the aspectual amples, something llke the Subset Principle is necessary. We can compare this principle to a Version Space model of inductive learning( [Mitchell 1977, 1978]), with no neg- i CfiJackendoff(1972, 1976) for a detailed elaboration of ative instances. Generalization proceeds in a conservative this theory. fashion, taking only the narrowest concept that covers the data. 2 This is now roughly the common assumption in GB, GPSG, and LFG. 173 field has three predicates, representing the three temporal culmination to the process of giving. This is captured by intervals t~, beginning, t2, middle, and t3, end. From the reference to the final subinterval, is. The linking between interaction of these predicates all thematic types can be = and the L associated with tt is interpreted as Source, derived.
Recommended publications
  • On Root Modality and Thematic Relations in Tagalog and English*
    Proceedings of SALT 26: 775–794, 2016 On root modality and thematic relations in Tagalog and English* Maayan Abenina-Adar Nikos Angelopoulos UCLA UCLA Abstract The literature on modality discusses how context and grammar interact to produce different flavors of necessity primarily in connection with functional modals e.g., English auxiliaries. In contrast, the grammatical properties of lexical modals (i.e., thematic verbs) are less understood. In this paper, we use the Tagalog necessity modal kailangan and English need as a case study in the syntax-semantics of lexical modals. Kailangan and need enter two structures, which we call ‘thematic’ and ‘impersonal’. We show that when they establish a thematic dependency with a subject, they express necessity in light of this subject’s priorities, and in the absence of an overt thematic subject, they express necessity in light of priorities endorsed by the speaker. To account for this, we propose a single lexical entry for kailangan / need that uniformly selects for a ‘needer’ argument. In thematic constructions, the needer is the overt subject, and in impersonal constructions, it is an implicit speaker-bound pronoun. Keywords: modality, thematic relations, Tagalog, syntax-semantics interface 1 Introduction In this paper, we observe that English need and its Tagalog counterpart, kailangan, express two different types of necessity depending on the syntactic structure they enter. We show that thematic constructions like (1) express necessities in light of priorities of the thematic subject, i.e., John, whereas impersonal constructions like (2) express necessities in light of priorities of the speaker. (1) John needs there to be food left over.
    [Show full text]
  • The Recovery of Thematic Role Structure During Noun-Noun Interpretation
    Psychonomic Bulletin & Review 2006, 13 (3), 423-428 The recovery of thematic role structure during noun–noun interpretation TODD R. FERRETTI Wilfrid Laurier University, Waterloo, Ontario, Canada and CHRISTINA L. GAGNÉ University of Alberta, Edmonton, Alberta, Canada We examined how people use their knowledge of events to recover thematic role structure dur- ing the interpretation of noun–noun phrases. All phrases included one noun that was a good-agent/ poor-patient ( prosecutor) in a particular event (accuse), and the other noun was a good-patient/poor-agent (defendant) for the same event. If people interpret the noun–noun phrases by inverting the nouns and ap- plying a thematic relation (see Downing, 1977; Levi, 1978), phrases should be interpreted more easily when the head nouns typically are good agents and the modifiers are good patients for specific events. Two experiments supported these predictions. Furthermore, the results indicated that in the less pre- ferred thematic order (agent–patient), people often generated interpretations in which the modifiers became the focus of the interpretations. This finding suggests that violating thematic role preferences is one constraint on when the inversion process occurs during noun–noun interpretation. Thematic roles represent the semantic roles played by event-specific knowledge is used during noun phrase in- nouns in relation to the events denoted by verbs in sen- terpretation comes from research examining phrases that tences (Fillmore, 1968). For example, for the event arrest, have participle modifiers (Ferretti, Gagné, & McRae, 2003; cop plays the agent role, and crook plays the patient role. Gagné & Murphy, 1996; Potter & Faulconer, 1979; Springer Earlier approaches posited that thematic role information & Murphy, 1992).
    [Show full text]
  • Full Page Photo
    International Journal of Applied Linguistics & English Literature ISSN 2200-3592 (Print), ISSN 2200-3452 (Online) Vol. 4 No. 4; July 2015 Flourishing Creativity & Literacy Australian International Academic Centre, Australia Establishing the Thematic Structure and Investigating the most Prominent Theta Roles Used in Sindhi Language Zahid Ali Veesar (Corresponding author) Faculty of Linguistics, University of Malaya, Malaysia E-mail: [email protected] Kais Amir Kadhim Faculty of Linguistics, University of Malaya, Malaysia E-mail: [email protected] Sridevi Sriniwass Faculty of Linguistics, University of Malaya, Malaysia E-mail: [email protected] Received: 07-12- 2014 Accepted: 21-02- 2015 Advance Access Published: February 2015 Published: 01-07- 2015 doi:10.7575/aiac.ijalel.v.4n.4p.216 URL: http://dx.doi.org/10.7575/aiac.ijalel.v.4n.4p.216 Abstract This study focuses on the thematic structure of the Sindhi verbs to find theta roles in the Sindhi language. The study tries to answer the research questions; “What are the thematic structures of Sindhi verbs?” and “What are the prominent theta roles in the Sindhi language?” It examines the argument/thematic structure of Sindhi verbs and also finds the theta roles assigned by the Sindhi verbs to their arguments along with the most prominent theta roles used in the Sindhi language. The data come from the two interviews taken from two young native Sindhi speakers, which consist of 2 hours conversation having 1,669 sentences in natural spoken version of the Sindhi language. Towards the end, it has been found that the Sindhi language has certain theta roles which are assigned by the verbs to their arguments in sentences.
    [Show full text]
  • Theta-Roles and Lexicon Theta-Criterion, Projection Principle, Extended Projection Principle
    Theta-Roles and Lexicon Theta-Criterion, Projection Principle, Extended Projection Principle Ling 322 Read Syntax, Ch. 8 (Lecture notes based on Andrew Carnie’s notes) 1 Overgeneration of X-bar Theory • X-bar Schema XP (YP) X X (ZP) • Overgeneration (1) a. The linguist loves wheat beer. b. The linguist laughed. (2) a. * The linguist loves. b. * The linguist laughed the philosopher. Sometimes an object is required, and sometimes it is not. What is responsible for this? 2 Using the Lexicon to Constrain X-bar Theory • Whether an object is required or not is a property of the particular verb. • Information about particular properties of verbs is contained in our mental dictionary – Lexicon. • Lexicon stores information about particular words. – pronunciation of word – morphological irregularities – meaning of word – requirements about other words they occur with 3 Argument Structure • (Fregean) Predicate:Defines the relation between the individuals being talked about and the real world, as well as each other. Argument: The central entities (including abstract ones) participating in the relation. The linguist loves wheat beer argument predicate argument • Argument Structure: specifies the number of arguments a predicate requires. (Adjuncts are never counted in the list of arguments.) intransitives, transitives, ditransitives • Subcategorization Restriction: Predicates control the category of arguments. (3) a. I asked a question. I asked if you know the professor. b. I hit the ball. *I hit that you knew the answer. • Selectional Restriction: Predicates limit the semantic properties of arguments. (4) a. # The bolt of lightening killed the rock. b. # My toothbrush loves raisins. 4 Thematic Relations Defines semantic role a participant plays in the situation described by the predicate.
    [Show full text]
  • Events and Maximalization: the Case of Telicity and Perfectivity1
    Events and Maximalization: The Case of Telicity and Perfectivity1 HANA FILIP University of Florida ABSTRACT. This paper advances the thesis that telicity in natural languages fundamentally relies on the maximalization operation in the domain of events. What counts as a maximal event in the denotation of a telic sentence in a given situation is derived from basic components of meaning that are directly related to the grammar of measurement and closely related scalar semantics. The maximalization operation on events is at the intersection of telicity in Germanic languages and the semantics of the grammatical category of perfectivity, as it is instantiated in Slavic languages, for example. Telicity viewed as maximalization on events provides us with a deeper understanding of the well-known differences in the way in which verbs interact with their nominal arguments and modifiers in the calculation of telicity of verb phrases and sentences in these two language families. 1. Introduction The goal of this paper is to address the following basic questions: What is the nature of telicity? How is it encoded? How is the semantic property of telicity related to perfectivity, a formal property of verbs? The answers will be couched within a semantically and pragmatically motivated framework. The main thesis is that telicity fundamentally relies on the maximalization operation in the domain of events (Section 2). Telic predicates denote events that are maximal with respect to an abstract representation of measurement, i.e., a scale. The maximalization operator on events MAXE is applied to a partially ordered set of events, from which it picks out the unique largest event at a given situation.
    [Show full text]
  • Telicity Corresponds to Degree of Change
    TopicsinSemantics 24.979 Telicity Corresponds to Degree of Change 1 Introduction Analyses of aspect often focus on the variable telicity of creation/destruction verbs (1), but such variability is also shown by directed motion verbs (2) (Levin and Rappaport Hovav 1995) and (so-called) “degree achievements” (3) (Dowty 1979). (1) a. Kim ate rice for an hour. atelic b. Kim ate a bowl of rice in an hour. telic (2) a. The balloon ascended for an hour. atelic b. The submarine ascended in an hour. telic (3) a. The dripping water lengthened the icicle for an hour. atelic b. The tailor lengthened my pants in an hour. telic Krifka (1989, 1992) argues that telicity is a function of the structure of the ‘incremental theme’ argument of the verb, and follows from the relation between the structure of the argument and the described event (cf. Dowty 1991; Filip 1999; Jackendoff 1996; Tenny 1987, 1994; Verkuyl 1993; Ramchand 1997). Focusing specifically on verbs of creation/destruction, Krifka argues that a defining charac- teristic of the incremental theme role is that it satisfies ‘Mapping to Objects’ and ‘Mapping to Events’: (4) a. Mapping to Objects ∀R[MAP-O(R) ↔ ∀e, e0, x[R(e, x) ∧ e0 ≥ e → ∃x0[x0 ≥ x ∧ R(e0, x0)]]] b. Mapping to Events ∀R[MAP-E(R) ↔ ∀e, x, x0[R(e, x) ∧ x0 ≥ x → ∃e0[e0 ≥ e ∧ R(e0, x0)]]] Given (4a-b), a telic interpretation of the predicate arises whenever the incremental theme argument is quantized: (5) a. A predicate P is quantized if and only if no entity that is P can be a subpart of another entity that is P (see Krifka 1998, p.
    [Show full text]
  • Implementing Home Blood Pressure Monitoring Into Clinical Practice
    Current Hypertension Reports (2019) 21: 14 https://doi.org/10.1007/s11906-019-0916-0 IMPLEMENTATION TO INCREASE BLOOD PRESSURE CONTROL: WHAT WORKS? (JEFFREY BRETTLER AND KRISTI REYNOLDS, SECTION EDITORS) Implementing Home Blood Pressure Monitoring into Clinical Practice Nadia Liyanage-Don1 & Deborah Fung2 & Erica Phillips2 & Ian M. Kronish1 Published online: 12 February 2019 # Springer Science+Business Media, LLC, part of Springer Nature 2019 Abstract Purpose of Review To review data supporting the use of home blood pressure monitoring (HBPM) and provide practical guidance to clinicians wishing to incorporate HBPM into their practice. Recent Findings HBPM more accurately reflects the risk of cardiovascular events than office blood pressure measurement. In addition, there is high-quality evidence that HBPM combined with clinical support improves blood pressure control. Therefore, HBPM is increasingly recommended by guidelines to confirm the diagnosis of hypertension and evaluate the efficacy of blood pressure-lowering medications. Nevertheless, HBPM use remains low due to barriers from the patient, clinician, and healthcare system level. Understanding these barriers is crucial for developing strategies to effectively implement HBPM into routine clinical practice. Summary HBPM is a valuable adjunct to office blood pressure measurement for diagnosing hypertension and guiding antihy- pertensive therapy. Following recommended best practices can facilitate the successful implementation of HBPM and impact how hypertension is managed in the primary care setting. Keywords Home blood pressure monitoring . Ambulatory blood pressure monitoring . Hypertension . Screening . Implementation . Barriers Introduction a central goal of numerous public health programs, including the Million Hearts Initiative [9] and the Improving Health Hypertension is one of the most prevalent medical conditions, Outcomes Initiative [10].
    [Show full text]
  • Chapter 3 Information Structure and the Partition of the Sentence
    Chapter 3 Information structure and the partition of the sentence The term information structure was introduced by Halliday (1967b, 200). It informally describes the organization of a spoken sentence, which is independent - and sometimes even orthogonal to - syntactic constituency: Any text in spoken English is organized into what may be called 'information units'. (...) this is not determined (...) by constituent structure. Rather could it be said that the distribution of information specifies a distinct structure on a different plan. This level is motivated as the functional correlate of the intonational phrases of an utterance, which are Halliday's "tone groups" (see section 2.3): The distribution into information units represents the speaker's blocking out of the message into quanta of information, or message blocks. Each information unit is realized as one tone group, in the sense that the information structure specifies the boundaries of the tone group to within certain limits (...). (Halliday 1967b, 202) This description of information structure as blocks or units of information is the most neutral one in the literature. So far, information structure is defined by (i) the general concept of information units and (ii) by correlation to intonational phrasing. Halliday himself adds further aspects to this concept, such as a thematic organiza- tion and the primacy of a division into two parts. The combination of these two additional aspects yields the common picture of information structure as a dichotomy of the sentence: The information structure of a sentence consists of two parts, one more informative and one less informative. The contrast is either marked by word order or by intonation.
    [Show full text]
  • On the Architecture of P¯An.Ini's Grammar
    On the Architecture of P¯an.ini’s Grammar∗ Paul Kiparsky Stanford University 1 Organization of the Grammar 1.1 Introduction P¯an. ini’s grammar is universally admired for its insightful analysis of Sanskrit. In addition, some of its features have a more specialized appeal. Sanskritists prize the completeness of its descriptive coverage of the spoken standard language (bh¯as.¯a) of P¯an. ini’s time, and the often unique information it provides on Vedic, regional and even sociolinguistic usage.1 Theoretical linguists of all persuasions are in addition impressed by its remarkable conciseness, and by the rigorous consistency with which it deploys its semi-formalized metalanguage, a grammatically and lexically regimented form of Sanskrit. Empiricists like Bloomfield also admired it for another, more specific reason, namely that it is based on nothing but very general principles such as simplicity, without prior commitments to any scheme of “universal grammar”, or so it seems, and proceeds from a strictly synchronic perspective. Generative linguists for their part have marveled especially at its ingenious technical devices, and at intricate system of conventions governing rule application and rule interaction that it presupposes, which seem to uncannily anticipate ideas of modern linguistic theory (if only because many of them were originally borrowed from P¯an. ini in the first place). This universal admiration of P¯an. ini poses a problem. Why do linguists who don’t approve of each other nevertheless agree in extolling P¯an. ini? Each school of linguistics seems to fashion its own portrait of P¯an. ini. In the following pages I propose to reconcile the Bloomfieldian portrait of P¯an.
    [Show full text]
  • THE FOURTH REPORT on the Diagnosis, Evaluation, and Treatment of High Blood Pressure in Children and Adolescents
    THE FOURTH REPORT ON THE Diagnosis, Evaluation, and Treatment of High Blood Pressure in Children and Adolescents U.S. DEPARTMENT OF HEALTH AND HUMAN SERVICES National Institutes of Health National Heart, Lung, and Blood Institute THE FOURTH REPORT ON THE Diagnosis, Evaluation, and Treatment of High Blood Pressure in Children and Adolescents U.S. DEPARTMENT OF HEALTH AND HUMAN SERVICES National Institutes of Health National Heart, Lung, and Blood Institute NIH Publication No. 05-5267 Originally printed September 1996 (96-3790) Revised May 2005 Acknowledgments THE FOURTH REPORT ON NATIONAL INSTITUTES OF THE DIAGNOSIS, EVALUATION, HEALTH STAFF AND TREATMENT OF HIGH Edward J. Roccella, Ph.D., M.P.H. BLOOD PRESSURE IN (National Heart, Lung, and Blood CHILDREN AND ADOLESCENTS Institute, Bethesda, MD); Tracey Hoke, M.D., M.Sc. (National Heart, Lung, and CHAIR Blood Institute, Bethesda, MD); Carl E. Bonita Falkner, M.D. (Thomas Jefferson Hunt, M.D. (National Center on Sleep University, Philadelphia, PA) Disorders Research, National Heart, Lung, and Blood Institute, Bethesda, MEMBERS MD); Gail Pearson, M.D., Sc.D. Stephen R. Daniels, M.D., Ph.D. (National Heart, Lung, and Blood (Cincinnati Children’s Hospital Medical Institute, Bethesda, MD) Center, Cincinnati, OH); Joseph T. Flynn, M.D., M.S. (Montefiore Medical Center, STAFF Bronx, NY); Samuel Gidding, M.D. Joanne Karimbakas, M.S., R.D., and (DuPont Hospital for Children, Ann Horton, M.S. (American Institutes Wilmington, DE); Lee A. Green, M.D., for Research Health Program, Silver M.P.H. (University of Michigan, Ann Spring, MD) Arbor, MI); Julie R. Ingelfinger, M.D. (MassGeneral Hospital for Children, FINANCIAL DISCLOSURES Boston, MA); Ronald M.
    [Show full text]
  • The Origins of Telicity Manfred Krifka
    The Origins of Telicity Manfred Krifka 1. Introduction The distinction between telic and atelic predicates has been described in terms of the algebraic prop- erties of their meaning since the early days of model-theoretic semantics. This perspective was in- spired by Aristotle’s discussion of types of actions that do or do not take time to be completed1 which was taken up and turned into a linguistic discussion of action-denoting predicates by Vendler (1957). The algebraic notion that seemed to be most conducive to express the Aristotelian distinc- tion appeared to be the mereological notion of a part, applied to the time at which these predicates hold: atelic predicates, like push a cart, have the subinterval property, that is, whenever they are true at a time interval, then they are true at any part of that interval; this does not hold for telic predicates, like eat an apple, cf. Bennett & Partee (1972), Taylor (1977), and Dowty (1979)2. Bach (1986) integrated these insights into a semantics based on events. Work by Garey (1957), Verkuyl (1972) and Platzack (1979) showed that the aspectual properties of a predicate result from two sources, the nature of the verbal head and the nature of a nominal argument. For example, whereas eat two apples is telic, eat apples is atelic. The early accounts of this phenomenon used syntactic features to describe this phenomenon; for example, Verkuyl ana- lyzed eat two apples by saying that eat has a feature [+ ADD TO] that allows for the feature [+ SPECIFIED QUANTITY] to percolate from the object NP an apple to the VP eat two apples.
    [Show full text]
  • On Root Modality and Thematic Relations in Tagalog and English Maayan Abenina­Adar & Nikos Angelopoulos UCLA
    On root modality and thematic relations in Tagalog and English Maayan Abenina­Adar & Nikos Angelopoulos UCLA The many varieties or “flavors” of modality have been argued to require a contextual account (Kratzer 1981, 1991, a.o.). More recently, however, Cinque 1999 and Hacquard 2010 have shown that broad categories of modal flavors correspond to different syntactic structures and have different grammatical properties. These works have focused on modal auxiliaries and other functional modal expressions; the grammatical properties of lexical modals, i.e. thematic verbs, are less understood. In this paper, we use Tagalog kailangan and English need as a case study in ​ ​ the syntax­semantics of lexical modals. Kailangan and need enter two structures, which we call ​ ​ “impersonal” and “thematic.” We show that syntax constrains the verbs’ modal potential, a puzzle for contextual accounts. The impersonal structure only expresses deontic necessity (necessity according to 3rd­party rules or laws), while the thematic structure only expresses subject­teleological necessity (necessity given a particular goal of the subject’s). We propose that kailangan and need are always thematic; deontic modality arises when their “needer” is an ​ ​ implicit free variable argument whose reference is constrained by binding principles, resulting in constraints on modal flavor. Our analysis leads to a tentative but more articulated typology of lexical necessity modals, dividing them according to whether they accept implicit arguments. On root modality and thematic relations in Tagalog and English Introduction: It's a robust generalization that a single modal verb can be associated with a range ​ of modal “flavors” (Kr81,91). Kratzer's original proposal was that conversational backgrounds derive distinctions in flavor, but recent work suggests that some distinctions are in the grammar e.g.
    [Show full text]