Which Bridges for Bridging Definite Descriptions?

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Which Bridges for Bridging Definite Descriptions? Which bridges for bridging definite descriptions? Claire Gardent, Hélène Manuélian and Eric Kow LORIA BP239 Campus Scientifique F-54506 Vandoeuvre-les-Nancy [email protected] Abstract Note that the implicit relation must be supported by shared knowledge. This is illustrated by example This paper presents a corpus study of (1b) where no relation between “duck” and the en- bridging definite descriptions in the french tities previously mentioned can be inferred. As a corpus PAROLE. It proposes a typology result, no anchor can be provided for the definite of bridging relations; describes a system description (“the duck” is not interpreted as “the for annotating NPs which allows for a duck that is part of the room”) and the overall dis- user friendly collection of all relevant in- course is distinctly odd. formation on the bridging definite des- For natural language processing systems, so-ca- criptions occurring in the corpus and dis- lled “bridging” (or “associative”) definite descrip- cusses the results of the corpus study 1. tions raise the interesting issue of how to integrate knowledge based reasoning so as to correctly in- 1 Introduction terpret or generate them. In the analysis direction, the problem is to recover the missing relation bet- It has long been known (cf. e.g., (Clark, 1977)) ween antecedent and anaphor so as to provide a that the referent of a definite description can be full interpretation of the input text (assuming the implicitely related (through world or lexical know- antecedent has somehow been identified). In the ledge) to some previously mentioned entity. In (1a) generation process, the difficulty is to determine for instance, the referent of “the ceiling” is linked whether the relation that holds between the referent to the referent of its anchor “the room” through the of the definite description and the referent of its “part-of” relation: because we know that rooms antecedent is one that can be ommitted i.e., one have ceilings, we interpret “the ceiling” in the se- that is supported by human knowledge. cond sentence, not just as denoting any ceiling, but In both cases, knowing the spectrum of relations rather as denoting the ceiling that is part of the that are possible between a definite description and room mentioned in the previous sentence. its antecedent is essential. Without a finite set of relations to start with, a tractable treatment of the (1) a. I looked into the room. The ceiling was inferences involved is unlikely. very high. For the development of computational systems, b. I looked into the room. The duck was very it is also necessary to know where the implicit brid- yellow. ging relation “comes from”: is it a lexical relation 1. Héléne Manuelian gratefully acknowledges the finan- (e.g., meronymy, hyponymy, synonymy) whose en- cial support provided for part of this research by both IN- coding is part of tools such as WordNet? Is it given RIA and the Lorraine Region (CPER Ingenierie logicielle, Pole “Ingéniérie des langues, du document et de l’informa- by world knowledge? etc. tion scientifique, technique et culturelle”). In this paper, we focus on identifying the set of l. Village/Taxi drivers Location/Object relations that can hold between a bridging definite m. Today/The news Time/Object description and its antecedent. Starting from the li- terature, we propose a typology for these relations When either the anchor or the target is a set, the which we then validate on a medium size corpus related object can stand in a subset- or an element- (9500 definite descriptions of which roughly 400 of relation. are bridging definite descriptions). Further, we in- When one of the related individuals is an event, vestigate WordNet (Miller, 1995) and FrameNet the other individual can describe an argument of (Baker et al., 1998) and quantify the number of that event (Clark distinguishes here between obli- cases where these resources actually contain the gatory and optional arguments). relation used between the ontological types of the When both anchors and targets are objects, one antecedent/anaphor pair. We conclude with some of the related object can either fulfill a certain func- indications of which types of lexical resources are tion in the other or specify one of its attributes. needed in order to interpret and/or generate brid- The related objects can also stands in one of the se- ging definite descriptions as well as pointers for veral meronymic relations described by (Winston further research. et al., 1987). A part is a structurally or functio- nally motivated component of a structured whole. 2 A typology of bridging relations Clark further distinguishes between necessary (room- /ceiling), probable (room/window) and inducible In this section, we start by summarising the brid- (room/chandelier) parts. Pieces differ from parts ging relations identified in the literature. We then in that pieces are homoreneous (all pieces are si- explains why it cannot be used directly as a basis milar to each other and to their whole). A collec- for annotation and go on to propose a taxonomy of tion differs from a set in that the group is based on bridging relations which we believe, can reliably a spatial or social connection rather than on physi- be used for large scale annotation. We use the fol- cal similarity. The stuff is the matter of which an lowing terminology. The TARGET is the referent of individual is made and an area is a spatial subpart a bridging definite description which is related by of a whole which cannot be separated from it. some implicit BRIDGING relation to the referent of Finally, an associative link can specify the spa- some previously mentioned entity, the ANCHOR. tial or temporal location of the related object. 2.1 Bridging relations in the literature 2.2 Two requirements for a typology of As e.g., (Clark, 1977; Strand, 1997; Kleiber, 1997) bridging relations have shown the semantic nature of this bridging While the set of relations identified in the lite- relation can vary. The following examples summa- rature is a useful starting point for defining a typo- rise the various bridging possibilities identified in logy of bridging relations, it is insufficient to sup- the literature. port the development of computational models of (2) a. Investment/Two thirds Set/Subset bridging definite descriptions for at least two rea- b. Class/Student Set/Element sons. c. Murder/Murderer Event/Argument First, the proposed typology must provide an ac- curate semantics for bridging relations. As it stands, d. Club/President Individual/Function and as a first annotation pass quickly showed, the e. Bicyle/Price Individual/Attribute set of relations identified in the previous section f. Room/Ceiling Whole/Part does not fulfill this criteria. Consider for instance, g. Cake/Slice Whole/Piece the following anchor/target pairs found in our cor- h. Suitcase/Leather Individual/Stuff pus: i. Forest/Tree Collection/Member (3) a. Operation/Convalescence Following j. France/French waters Place/Area b. Athletism/National federation For k. Opera/Duet Whole/Temp.Subpart c. Question/Answer to ¡ denoting locations and time intervals respecti- d. Investigation/Witness reports Based on vely). This classification is summarised in table 1. We now discuss each class in more detail showing In these examples, the relation holding between in particular, how a specific relation is identified anchor and target is determined by the lexical se- and how its semantics is established. mantics of either target (examples 3a-c) or anchor (examples 3d). Thus, a convalescence follows an Set membership. This class covers cases such operation, a federation groups together associations as (4) where the target is either a member or a sub- acting for a common activity, an answer is a reac- set of a set (a group of similar individuals). tion to a question (or a request) and an investiga- (4) a. Seminars/The last seminar tion is based on witness reports. b. The CGT and the FO/The FO This is in contrast with the standard view of bridging relations which tends to assume a closed c. The army/The third set involving in essence three main types of rela- The semantics of this bridging relation is set tions: inclusion (whole-part, set membership, time membership and inclusion. The anchor (or the tar- and space anchor and locative anaphora), posses- get) must be a set of individuals and the target (or sion (subcategorisation, possessor-thing and func- the anchor) must be an individual. tional associative anaphora) and thematic (event- argument). As we shall see, the typology we pro- Thematic. As illustrated by (2c), the target can pose take these facts into account and encompasses be related to the anchor via a thematic relation (a both the “standard” bridging relations and the more murderer is the agent of a murder). More gene- unconventional “lexical” ones. rally, a thematic bridge links an event to an indivi- A second requirement that must be satisfied in dual via a thematic relation defined by the thema- order to develop a computational model of brid- tic grid of the event. As a result, the property de- ging definite descriptions, is that the possible sour- noted by the noun caracterising the individual ( ¨ © ) ces of bridging relations be identified. Where does must be subsumed by the conjunction of the pro- a bridging relation “come from”? Is it a lexical re- perty denoted by the verb or noun caracterising the lation (meronymy)? Or is it given by a lexical defi- event ( ¨ ) and the thematic relation holding bet- nition, a thematic grid (Event/Argument cases) or ween this event and the individual( ). That © ¨ ¦ by more extensive script- or world-knowledge? If is, ¨ . (and as we shall see, this is indeed the case) all of Definitional.
Recommended publications
  • On Root Modality and Thematic Relations in Tagalog and English*
    Proceedings of SALT 26: 775–794, 2016 On root modality and thematic relations in Tagalog and English* Maayan Abenina-Adar Nikos Angelopoulos UCLA UCLA Abstract The literature on modality discusses how context and grammar interact to produce different flavors of necessity primarily in connection with functional modals e.g., English auxiliaries. In contrast, the grammatical properties of lexical modals (i.e., thematic verbs) are less understood. In this paper, we use the Tagalog necessity modal kailangan and English need as a case study in the syntax-semantics of lexical modals. Kailangan and need enter two structures, which we call ‘thematic’ and ‘impersonal’. We show that when they establish a thematic dependency with a subject, they express necessity in light of this subject’s priorities, and in the absence of an overt thematic subject, they express necessity in light of priorities endorsed by the speaker. To account for this, we propose a single lexical entry for kailangan / need that uniformly selects for a ‘needer’ argument. In thematic constructions, the needer is the overt subject, and in impersonal constructions, it is an implicit speaker-bound pronoun. Keywords: modality, thematic relations, Tagalog, syntax-semantics interface 1 Introduction In this paper, we observe that English need and its Tagalog counterpart, kailangan, express two different types of necessity depending on the syntactic structure they enter. We show that thematic constructions like (1) express necessities in light of priorities of the thematic subject, i.e., John, whereas impersonal constructions like (2) express necessities in light of priorities of the speaker. (1) John needs there to be food left over.
    [Show full text]
  • The Perceptual Origin of Thematic Relations
    On the Acquisition of Lexical Entries: The Perceptual Origin of Thematic Relations James Pustejovsky Department of Computer Science Brandeis University Waltham, MA 02254 617-736-2709 jamesp~br andeis.csnet-relay Abstract that the conceptual abstraction of thematic information does not develop arbitrarily but along a given, predictable path; namely, a developmental path that starts with tan- This paper describes a computational model of concept gible perceptual predicates (e.g. spatial, causative) to acquisition for natural language. We develop a theory later form the more abstract mental and cognitive predi- of lexical semantics, the Eztended Aspect Calculus, which cates. In this view thematic relations are actually sets of together with a ~maxkedness theory" for thematic rela- thematic properties, related by a partial ordering. This tions, constrains what a possible word meaning can be. effectively establishes a maxkedness theory for thematic This is based on the supposition that predicates from the roles that a learning system must adhere to in the acqui- perceptual domain axe the primitives for more abstract sition of lexical entries for a larlguage. relations. We then describe an implementation of this We will discuss two computational methods for model, TULLY, which mirrors the stages of lexical acqui- concept development in natural language: sition for children. (1) F~ature Relaxation of particular features of the ar- guments to a verb. This is performed by a con- straint propagation method. I. Introduction (2) Thematic Decoupling of semantically incorporated In this paper we describe a computational model of con- information from the verb. cept acquisition for natural language making use of po- When these two learning techniques are combined with sitive-only data, modelled on a theory of lexical seman- the model of lexical semantics adopted here, the stages tics.
    [Show full text]
  • The Recovery of Thematic Role Structure During Noun-Noun Interpretation
    Psychonomic Bulletin & Review 2006, 13 (3), 423-428 The recovery of thematic role structure during noun–noun interpretation TODD R. FERRETTI Wilfrid Laurier University, Waterloo, Ontario, Canada and CHRISTINA L. GAGNÉ University of Alberta, Edmonton, Alberta, Canada We examined how people use their knowledge of events to recover thematic role structure dur- ing the interpretation of noun–noun phrases. All phrases included one noun that was a good-agent/ poor-patient ( prosecutor) in a particular event (accuse), and the other noun was a good-patient/poor-agent (defendant) for the same event. If people interpret the noun–noun phrases by inverting the nouns and ap- plying a thematic relation (see Downing, 1977; Levi, 1978), phrases should be interpreted more easily when the head nouns typically are good agents and the modifiers are good patients for specific events. Two experiments supported these predictions. Furthermore, the results indicated that in the less pre- ferred thematic order (agent–patient), people often generated interpretations in which the modifiers became the focus of the interpretations. This finding suggests that violating thematic role preferences is one constraint on when the inversion process occurs during noun–noun interpretation. Thematic roles represent the semantic roles played by event-specific knowledge is used during noun phrase in- nouns in relation to the events denoted by verbs in sen- terpretation comes from research examining phrases that tences (Fillmore, 1968). For example, for the event arrest, have participle modifiers (Ferretti, Gagné, & McRae, 2003; cop plays the agent role, and crook plays the patient role. Gagné & Murphy, 1996; Potter & Faulconer, 1979; Springer Earlier approaches posited that thematic role information & Murphy, 1992).
    [Show full text]
  • Full Page Photo
    International Journal of Applied Linguistics & English Literature ISSN 2200-3592 (Print), ISSN 2200-3452 (Online) Vol. 4 No. 4; July 2015 Flourishing Creativity & Literacy Australian International Academic Centre, Australia Establishing the Thematic Structure and Investigating the most Prominent Theta Roles Used in Sindhi Language Zahid Ali Veesar (Corresponding author) Faculty of Linguistics, University of Malaya, Malaysia E-mail: [email protected] Kais Amir Kadhim Faculty of Linguistics, University of Malaya, Malaysia E-mail: [email protected] Sridevi Sriniwass Faculty of Linguistics, University of Malaya, Malaysia E-mail: [email protected] Received: 07-12- 2014 Accepted: 21-02- 2015 Advance Access Published: February 2015 Published: 01-07- 2015 doi:10.7575/aiac.ijalel.v.4n.4p.216 URL: http://dx.doi.org/10.7575/aiac.ijalel.v.4n.4p.216 Abstract This study focuses on the thematic structure of the Sindhi verbs to find theta roles in the Sindhi language. The study tries to answer the research questions; “What are the thematic structures of Sindhi verbs?” and “What are the prominent theta roles in the Sindhi language?” It examines the argument/thematic structure of Sindhi verbs and also finds the theta roles assigned by the Sindhi verbs to their arguments along with the most prominent theta roles used in the Sindhi language. The data come from the two interviews taken from two young native Sindhi speakers, which consist of 2 hours conversation having 1,669 sentences in natural spoken version of the Sindhi language. Towards the end, it has been found that the Sindhi language has certain theta roles which are assigned by the verbs to their arguments in sentences.
    [Show full text]
  • Theta-Roles and Lexicon Theta-Criterion, Projection Principle, Extended Projection Principle
    Theta-Roles and Lexicon Theta-Criterion, Projection Principle, Extended Projection Principle Ling 322 Read Syntax, Ch. 8 (Lecture notes based on Andrew Carnie’s notes) 1 Overgeneration of X-bar Theory • X-bar Schema XP (YP) X X (ZP) • Overgeneration (1) a. The linguist loves wheat beer. b. The linguist laughed. (2) a. * The linguist loves. b. * The linguist laughed the philosopher. Sometimes an object is required, and sometimes it is not. What is responsible for this? 2 Using the Lexicon to Constrain X-bar Theory • Whether an object is required or not is a property of the particular verb. • Information about particular properties of verbs is contained in our mental dictionary – Lexicon. • Lexicon stores information about particular words. – pronunciation of word – morphological irregularities – meaning of word – requirements about other words they occur with 3 Argument Structure • (Fregean) Predicate:Defines the relation between the individuals being talked about and the real world, as well as each other. Argument: The central entities (including abstract ones) participating in the relation. The linguist loves wheat beer argument predicate argument • Argument Structure: specifies the number of arguments a predicate requires. (Adjuncts are never counted in the list of arguments.) intransitives, transitives, ditransitives • Subcategorization Restriction: Predicates control the category of arguments. (3) a. I asked a question. I asked if you know the professor. b. I hit the ball. *I hit that you knew the answer. • Selectional Restriction: Predicates limit the semantic properties of arguments. (4) a. # The bolt of lightening killed the rock. b. # My toothbrush loves raisins. 4 Thematic Relations Defines semantic role a participant plays in the situation described by the predicate.
    [Show full text]
  • Events and Maximalization: the Case of Telicity and Perfectivity1
    Events and Maximalization: The Case of Telicity and Perfectivity1 HANA FILIP University of Florida ABSTRACT. This paper advances the thesis that telicity in natural languages fundamentally relies on the maximalization operation in the domain of events. What counts as a maximal event in the denotation of a telic sentence in a given situation is derived from basic components of meaning that are directly related to the grammar of measurement and closely related scalar semantics. The maximalization operation on events is at the intersection of telicity in Germanic languages and the semantics of the grammatical category of perfectivity, as it is instantiated in Slavic languages, for example. Telicity viewed as maximalization on events provides us with a deeper understanding of the well-known differences in the way in which verbs interact with their nominal arguments and modifiers in the calculation of telicity of verb phrases and sentences in these two language families. 1. Introduction The goal of this paper is to address the following basic questions: What is the nature of telicity? How is it encoded? How is the semantic property of telicity related to perfectivity, a formal property of verbs? The answers will be couched within a semantically and pragmatically motivated framework. The main thesis is that telicity fundamentally relies on the maximalization operation in the domain of events (Section 2). Telic predicates denote events that are maximal with respect to an abstract representation of measurement, i.e., a scale. The maximalization operator on events MAXE is applied to a partially ordered set of events, from which it picks out the unique largest event at a given situation.
    [Show full text]
  • Telicity Corresponds to Degree of Change
    TopicsinSemantics 24.979 Telicity Corresponds to Degree of Change 1 Introduction Analyses of aspect often focus on the variable telicity of creation/destruction verbs (1), but such variability is also shown by directed motion verbs (2) (Levin and Rappaport Hovav 1995) and (so-called) “degree achievements” (3) (Dowty 1979). (1) a. Kim ate rice for an hour. atelic b. Kim ate a bowl of rice in an hour. telic (2) a. The balloon ascended for an hour. atelic b. The submarine ascended in an hour. telic (3) a. The dripping water lengthened the icicle for an hour. atelic b. The tailor lengthened my pants in an hour. telic Krifka (1989, 1992) argues that telicity is a function of the structure of the ‘incremental theme’ argument of the verb, and follows from the relation between the structure of the argument and the described event (cf. Dowty 1991; Filip 1999; Jackendoff 1996; Tenny 1987, 1994; Verkuyl 1993; Ramchand 1997). Focusing specifically on verbs of creation/destruction, Krifka argues that a defining charac- teristic of the incremental theme role is that it satisfies ‘Mapping to Objects’ and ‘Mapping to Events’: (4) a. Mapping to Objects ∀R[MAP-O(R) ↔ ∀e, e0, x[R(e, x) ∧ e0 ≥ e → ∃x0[x0 ≥ x ∧ R(e0, x0)]]] b. Mapping to Events ∀R[MAP-E(R) ↔ ∀e, x, x0[R(e, x) ∧ x0 ≥ x → ∃e0[e0 ≥ e ∧ R(e0, x0)]]] Given (4a-b), a telic interpretation of the predicate arises whenever the incremental theme argument is quantized: (5) a. A predicate P is quantized if and only if no entity that is P can be a subpart of another entity that is P (see Krifka 1998, p.
    [Show full text]
  • Implementing Home Blood Pressure Monitoring Into Clinical Practice
    Current Hypertension Reports (2019) 21: 14 https://doi.org/10.1007/s11906-019-0916-0 IMPLEMENTATION TO INCREASE BLOOD PRESSURE CONTROL: WHAT WORKS? (JEFFREY BRETTLER AND KRISTI REYNOLDS, SECTION EDITORS) Implementing Home Blood Pressure Monitoring into Clinical Practice Nadia Liyanage-Don1 & Deborah Fung2 & Erica Phillips2 & Ian M. Kronish1 Published online: 12 February 2019 # Springer Science+Business Media, LLC, part of Springer Nature 2019 Abstract Purpose of Review To review data supporting the use of home blood pressure monitoring (HBPM) and provide practical guidance to clinicians wishing to incorporate HBPM into their practice. Recent Findings HBPM more accurately reflects the risk of cardiovascular events than office blood pressure measurement. In addition, there is high-quality evidence that HBPM combined with clinical support improves blood pressure control. Therefore, HBPM is increasingly recommended by guidelines to confirm the diagnosis of hypertension and evaluate the efficacy of blood pressure-lowering medications. Nevertheless, HBPM use remains low due to barriers from the patient, clinician, and healthcare system level. Understanding these barriers is crucial for developing strategies to effectively implement HBPM into routine clinical practice. Summary HBPM is a valuable adjunct to office blood pressure measurement for diagnosing hypertension and guiding antihy- pertensive therapy. Following recommended best practices can facilitate the successful implementation of HBPM and impact how hypertension is managed in the primary care setting. Keywords Home blood pressure monitoring . Ambulatory blood pressure monitoring . Hypertension . Screening . Implementation . Barriers Introduction a central goal of numerous public health programs, including the Million Hearts Initiative [9] and the Improving Health Hypertension is one of the most prevalent medical conditions, Outcomes Initiative [10].
    [Show full text]
  • Chapter 3 Information Structure and the Partition of the Sentence
    Chapter 3 Information structure and the partition of the sentence The term information structure was introduced by Halliday (1967b, 200). It informally describes the organization of a spoken sentence, which is independent - and sometimes even orthogonal to - syntactic constituency: Any text in spoken English is organized into what may be called 'information units'. (...) this is not determined (...) by constituent structure. Rather could it be said that the distribution of information specifies a distinct structure on a different plan. This level is motivated as the functional correlate of the intonational phrases of an utterance, which are Halliday's "tone groups" (see section 2.3): The distribution into information units represents the speaker's blocking out of the message into quanta of information, or message blocks. Each information unit is realized as one tone group, in the sense that the information structure specifies the boundaries of the tone group to within certain limits (...). (Halliday 1967b, 202) This description of information structure as blocks or units of information is the most neutral one in the literature. So far, information structure is defined by (i) the general concept of information units and (ii) by correlation to intonational phrasing. Halliday himself adds further aspects to this concept, such as a thematic organiza- tion and the primacy of a division into two parts. The combination of these two additional aspects yields the common picture of information structure as a dichotomy of the sentence: The information structure of a sentence consists of two parts, one more informative and one less informative. The contrast is either marked by word order or by intonation.
    [Show full text]
  • On the Architecture of P¯An.Ini's Grammar
    On the Architecture of P¯an.ini’s Grammar∗ Paul Kiparsky Stanford University 1 Organization of the Grammar 1.1 Introduction P¯an. ini’s grammar is universally admired for its insightful analysis of Sanskrit. In addition, some of its features have a more specialized appeal. Sanskritists prize the completeness of its descriptive coverage of the spoken standard language (bh¯as.¯a) of P¯an. ini’s time, and the often unique information it provides on Vedic, regional and even sociolinguistic usage.1 Theoretical linguists of all persuasions are in addition impressed by its remarkable conciseness, and by the rigorous consistency with which it deploys its semi-formalized metalanguage, a grammatically and lexically regimented form of Sanskrit. Empiricists like Bloomfield also admired it for another, more specific reason, namely that it is based on nothing but very general principles such as simplicity, without prior commitments to any scheme of “universal grammar”, or so it seems, and proceeds from a strictly synchronic perspective. Generative linguists for their part have marveled especially at its ingenious technical devices, and at intricate system of conventions governing rule application and rule interaction that it presupposes, which seem to uncannily anticipate ideas of modern linguistic theory (if only because many of them were originally borrowed from P¯an. ini in the first place). This universal admiration of P¯an. ini poses a problem. Why do linguists who don’t approve of each other nevertheless agree in extolling P¯an. ini? Each school of linguistics seems to fashion its own portrait of P¯an. ini. In the following pages I propose to reconcile the Bloomfieldian portrait of P¯an.
    [Show full text]
  • THE FOURTH REPORT on the Diagnosis, Evaluation, and Treatment of High Blood Pressure in Children and Adolescents
    THE FOURTH REPORT ON THE Diagnosis, Evaluation, and Treatment of High Blood Pressure in Children and Adolescents U.S. DEPARTMENT OF HEALTH AND HUMAN SERVICES National Institutes of Health National Heart, Lung, and Blood Institute THE FOURTH REPORT ON THE Diagnosis, Evaluation, and Treatment of High Blood Pressure in Children and Adolescents U.S. DEPARTMENT OF HEALTH AND HUMAN SERVICES National Institutes of Health National Heart, Lung, and Blood Institute NIH Publication No. 05-5267 Originally printed September 1996 (96-3790) Revised May 2005 Acknowledgments THE FOURTH REPORT ON NATIONAL INSTITUTES OF THE DIAGNOSIS, EVALUATION, HEALTH STAFF AND TREATMENT OF HIGH Edward J. Roccella, Ph.D., M.P.H. BLOOD PRESSURE IN (National Heart, Lung, and Blood CHILDREN AND ADOLESCENTS Institute, Bethesda, MD); Tracey Hoke, M.D., M.Sc. (National Heart, Lung, and CHAIR Blood Institute, Bethesda, MD); Carl E. Bonita Falkner, M.D. (Thomas Jefferson Hunt, M.D. (National Center on Sleep University, Philadelphia, PA) Disorders Research, National Heart, Lung, and Blood Institute, Bethesda, MEMBERS MD); Gail Pearson, M.D., Sc.D. Stephen R. Daniels, M.D., Ph.D. (National Heart, Lung, and Blood (Cincinnati Children’s Hospital Medical Institute, Bethesda, MD) Center, Cincinnati, OH); Joseph T. Flynn, M.D., M.S. (Montefiore Medical Center, STAFF Bronx, NY); Samuel Gidding, M.D. Joanne Karimbakas, M.S., R.D., and (DuPont Hospital for Children, Ann Horton, M.S. (American Institutes Wilmington, DE); Lee A. Green, M.D., for Research Health Program, Silver M.P.H. (University of Michigan, Ann Spring, MD) Arbor, MI); Julie R. Ingelfinger, M.D. (MassGeneral Hospital for Children, FINANCIAL DISCLOSURES Boston, MA); Ronald M.
    [Show full text]
  • The Origins of Telicity Manfred Krifka
    The Origins of Telicity Manfred Krifka 1. Introduction The distinction between telic and atelic predicates has been described in terms of the algebraic prop- erties of their meaning since the early days of model-theoretic semantics. This perspective was in- spired by Aristotle’s discussion of types of actions that do or do not take time to be completed1 which was taken up and turned into a linguistic discussion of action-denoting predicates by Vendler (1957). The algebraic notion that seemed to be most conducive to express the Aristotelian distinc- tion appeared to be the mereological notion of a part, applied to the time at which these predicates hold: atelic predicates, like push a cart, have the subinterval property, that is, whenever they are true at a time interval, then they are true at any part of that interval; this does not hold for telic predicates, like eat an apple, cf. Bennett & Partee (1972), Taylor (1977), and Dowty (1979)2. Bach (1986) integrated these insights into a semantics based on events. Work by Garey (1957), Verkuyl (1972) and Platzack (1979) showed that the aspectual properties of a predicate result from two sources, the nature of the verbal head and the nature of a nominal argument. For example, whereas eat two apples is telic, eat apples is atelic. The early accounts of this phenomenon used syntactic features to describe this phenomenon; for example, Verkuyl ana- lyzed eat two apples by saying that eat has a feature [+ ADD TO] that allows for the feature [+ SPECIFIED QUANTITY] to percolate from the object NP an apple to the VP eat two apples.
    [Show full text]