John Dewey and Environmental Philosophy

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

John Dewey and Environmental Philosophy John Dewey and Environmental Philosophy Hugh P. McDonald JOHN DEWEY AND ENVIRONMENTAL PHILOSOPHY SUNY series in Environmental Philosophy and Ethics J. Baird Callicott and John van Buren, editors JOHN DEWEY AND ENVIRONMENTAL PHILOSOPHY Hugh P. McDonald STATE UNIVERSITY OF NEW YORK PRESS Published by State University of New York Press, Albany © 2004 State University of New York All rights reserved Printed in the United States of America No part of this book may be used or reproduced in any manner whatsoever without written permission. No part of this book may be stored in a retrieval system or transmitted in any form or by any means including electronic, electrostatic, magnetic tape, mechanical, photocopying, recording, or otherwise without the prior permission in writing of the publisher. For information, address State University of New York Press, 90 State Street, Suite 700, Albany, NY 12207 Production by Kelli Williams Marketing by Michael Campochiaro Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data McDonald, H. P. (Hugh P.) John Dewey and environmental philosophy / Hugh P. McDonald. p. cm. — (SUNY series in environmental philosophy and ethics) Includes bibliographical references and index. ISBN 0-7914-5873-3 (alk. paper) — ISBN 0-7914-5874-1 (pbk. alk. paper) 1. Dewey, John, 1859–1952. 2. Pragmatism. 3. Environmental sciences—Philosophy. 4. Environmental ethics. I. Title. II. Series. B945.D44M34 2003 179'.1'092—dc22 2003060825 10 9 8 7 6 5 4 3 2 1 This book is dedicated to the late Professor Reuben Abel, teacher, scholar, philosopher CONTENTS ACKNOWLEDGMENTS xi PREFACE xiii ONE Environmental Ethics and Intrinsic Value 1 PROLOGUE TO CHAPTER TWO 57 The Setting of the Problem of Pragmatism and the Environment: The Critique of Pragmatism as an Environmental Ethics in Taylor, Bowers, Katz, and Weston TWO Dewey’s Naturalism 67 THREE Dewey’s Instrumentalism 91 FOUR Dewey’s (Moral) Holism 109 FIVE Dewey’s Ethics as a Basis for Environmental Issues 123 EPILOGUE Pragmatism and Environmental Ethics 143 NOTES 159 BIBLIOGRAPHY 207 INDEX 215 |vii| Human nature exists and operates in an environment . as a plant is in the sunlight and soil. It is of them, continuous with their energies, dependent upon their support, capable of increase only as it utilizes them and as it gradually rebuilds from their crude indifference an environment genially civilized. —Dewey ACKNOWLEDGMENTS My thanks to Professor Richard Bernstein, who patiently read the initial drafts of this work and provided many helpful comments and criticisms. In particular, his suggestion that pragmatism might provide an alternative approach to environmental ethics, apart from intrinsic value, proved fruitful and changed the direction of the book. Chapter two, Dewey’s Naturalism, has appeared in Environmental Ethics in a slightly altered form. I also wish to acknowledge the influence of J. Baird Callicott on my thinking, despite many critical comments in chapter two. Reprinted from In Defense of the Land Ethic: Essays in Environmental Philosophy, by J. Baird Callicott, by permission of the State University of New York Press, © 1989, State University of New York. All rights reserved. Por- tions throughout. From excerpts in Environmental Ethics, Duties to and Values in the Natural World, by Holmes Rolston III. Reprinted by permission of Temple University Press. © 1988 by Temple University. All Rights Reserved. Portions throughout. From excerpts in Experience and Nature, by John Dewey. Grateful acknowledgment is made to Open Court Publishing Company, a division of Carus Publishing Company. © 1925, 1929 by Open Court Publishing Company. |xi| PREFACE Environmental ethics has recently developed as a separate field within philos- ophy and has a large and growing literature of its own. This field involves eth- ical studies of the rights of other species, of ecosystems, and of the environ- ment of all living things as a whole. Much of the internal debate within the field has concerned issues of value and moral considerability. It is argued that if species other than humans, ecosystems, and the biosphere—the entire plan- etary zone of life—have value on their own, then they are entitled to moral consideration from humans, either some form of rights, or a duty of humans to the environment. This may take the minimal form of letting the bearer of rights alone or a larger, more activist role in managing the environment with an eye to its benefit. The central issue in this debate, which has attracted perhaps the most attention in the journals, is the issue of the value of the environment, other species, and ecosystems. One of the interesting things about this ongoing dis- cussion has been the almost exclusive concentration on issues of value in the literature of environmental ethics. This has revived value studies, which had shown recent signs of fading,1 in a vigorous way. The debate has been framed in terms of “anthropocentric” as opposed to “non-anthropocentric” values.2 “Anthropocentric” values are values that are exclusive to humans in some respect, whether involving a uniquely human capacity such as some would claim reason to be; or the purported unique moral agency of humans, that humans alone are rights bearers, agents of duty, or the like. Non-anthro- pocentrists locate value in a larger set of members or a set with larger scope. This may include higher animals, all living things, ecosystems, species, and the biosphere. The value structure that has framed the debate has not so much challenged traditional divisions of values, namely, instrumental and intrinsic values, as the exclusivity of human value and human valuing. Non-anthro- pocentrists have argued that anthropocentric value theories, as their etymol- ogy would imply, are oriented exclusively toward humans. They are arbitrary |xiii| |xiv| Preface and “speciesist” in their view of value as based solely in human being and as excluding all other species and the environment itself from moral considera- tion. Other species and the environment are treated exclusively as instruments for human use, and not given consideration in their own right as worthy of preservation, survival, and autonomy. Because, it is charged, traditional West- ern ethics is almost universally anthropocentric, a new, environmental ethic is needed, which will challenge the primacy or even exclusivity of humans to ethical consideration.3 It is not enough for some of the radicals in this move- ment to merely rework traditional ethics with an eye to the environment. Environmental ethics is considered by some to be a revolution in ethics, which will completely change the human-centered orientation of morals to include all species, ecosystems, or the larger biosphere. The critique of Western philosophy as a whole has been extended by individual authors to criticisms of particular schools of philosophy in the West, for example, utilitarianism and other prominent ethical theories. Recently, there have been criticisms of pragmatism as a whole, as well as more specific criticisms of James and Dewey, two of its more accessible and promi- nent members.4 Pragmatism has been criticized as being inherently anthro- pocentric and thus implicitly anti-environmental in the strong sense that envi- ronmentalism cannot be anthropocentric. These criticisms of pragmatism have as a premise that all the various authors who have been identified as pragmatists have some common elements that make them pragmatists and that these are implicitly hostile or indifferent to environmentalism or envi- ronmental ethics. More specifically, the instrumental theory of values in Dewey is regarded as an implicit critique of the very possibility of assigning or locating intrinsic value in any of the candidates for such a larger set or locus of intrinsic value, for example, higher animals or ecosystems. Thus pragma- tism, it is alleged, would undermine the very possibility of an environmental ethic by arguing against its central and ultimate foundation, intrinsic value, if it were to be used as the basis for environmental ethics. My main argument will be that the pragmatism of Dewey can be defended against charges of anti-environmentalism and anthropocentricity.5 Dewey was picked to represent pragmatism not only because of his highly developed and intricate theory of values and his naturalistic approach but because his naturalism already is environmentally minded. In order to inves- tigate the critique of pragmatism by certain authors from the point of view of environmental ethics, I will also include an analysis of these criticisms as a prologue to chapter two. In chapter one, I will analyze several representative philosophies that argue for the intrinsic value of nature: those of J. Baird Callicott, Tom Regan, and Holmes Rolston III. These are three of the most prominent environmental philosophers, who have published the most thoroughgoing and articulate Preface |xv| theories of intrinsic value in environmental philosophy. This chapter will introduce and critically examine the concept of the intrinsic value of nonhu- man life and the ecology.6 I will also consider a prominent critic of non- anthropocentric intrinsic value theories from within the environmental liter- ature, Bryan Norton. The next four chapters will present a detailed analysis of the (practical) philosophy of John Dewey. However, I will also include a brief examination of some elements of his naturalism, especially in chapter two. The second chap- ter is in a sense central to the book as it directly refutes the notion that prag- matism could not serve as an environmental ethic. I argue that Dewey brings human nature back into nature as a whole, ending the isolation and detach- ment of the subject. Values are treated along with natural processes in a way that provides an alternative model for environmental ethics, one that is more closely in accord with the formal requirements of such an ethic. Dewey’s nat- uralism could be used, I will argue, for such an alternative model. Thus the criticism of pragmatism as a whole as undermining the central foundation of environmental ethics will be challenged.
Recommended publications
  • Contributions of John Dewey and Louise M
    THE EMERGING PARADIGM OF READER-TEXT TRANSACTION: CONTRIBUTIONS OF JOHN DEWEY AND LOUISE M. ROSENBLATT, WITH IMPLICATIONS FOR EDUCATORS by Elizabeth H. Roth Dissertation submitted to the Faculty of the Virginia Polytechnic Institute and State University in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in Curriculum and Instruction Jim Garrison, Chair Patricia P. Kelly Jan Nespor Warren P. Self Robert C. Small, Jr. December 4, 1998 Blacksburg, Virginia Key words: philosophy of education, teaching of literature, literary theory, John Dewey, Louise M. Rosenblatt The Emerging Paradigm of Reader-Text Transaction: Contributions of John Dewey and Louise M. Rosenblatt, With Implications for Educators Elizabeth H. Roth (ABSTRACT) This dissertation will trace the emerging paradigm of transaction as a model for the dynamics of the reading process. The paradigm of transaction, implicit in John Dewey's writings as early as 1896 in "The Reflex Arc Concept in Psychology," was originally described in terms of "interaction" between organism and environment. Only in 1949, in the twilight of his career, did Dewey definitively distinguish between "transaction" and "interaction," ascribing a mutually transformative character to the former process. In Knowing and the Known, Dewey and co-author Arthur F. Bentley (1949) proposed adoption of a wholly new "transactional vocabulary" as a precision tool for a new mode of scientific inquiry, whereby inquiry itself was recognized as a species of transaction between inquirer and observed phenomena. Even before the publication of Knowing and the Known, literary theorist Louise M. Rosenblatt had applied an implicitly transactional model of the relationship between organism and environment to the relationship between reader and text.
    [Show full text]
  • Social Epistemology and Online Knowledge Exchange
    Social Epistemology and Online Knowledge Exchange Paul Daniel Matthews A statement submitted in partial fulfilment of the requirements of the University of the West of England, Bristol for the degree of DPhil Faculty of Environment and Technology, University of the West of England, Bristol October 2015 Abstract This document summarises the submitted research, which has investigated online knowledge exchange and related it to the philosophical field of social epistemology. The broad aims have been: firstly to investigate what social epistemology theory can offer in the way of guidance and evaluative frameworks for the design of knowledge systems; and secondly, to determine what the empirical study of knowledge exchange platforms can tell us about knowledge as emerging from online practice. The submitted work consists of six papers that are a mixture of review/position papers and reports of empirical investigation. These have been published in information science journals and conference proceedings. However, following the established tradition of information science, the work is positioned as being cross-disciplinary in ambition. After introducing the submitted papers and the inspiration for the research, the main theoretical positions of the research are outlined and justified. These were a naturalised social epistemological position, inspired by Alvin Goldman, but widened to a situated and systems-oriented view. The naturalised view of epistemology allows for consideration of evidence from psychology, and here some key theories in social and cognitive psychology are outlined. Finally, as the subject is human- computer-human interaction, the sociotechnical setting is established. Further, the main platforms of study in the empirical work — social question answering systems — are introduced and described.
    [Show full text]
  • Methodological Transactionalism and the Sociology of Education Daniel A
    Methodological Transactionalism and the Sociology of Education Daniel A. McFarland, David Diehl and Craig Rawlings (Stanford University) Abstract: The development and spread of research methods in sociology can be understood as a story about the increasing sophistication of tools in order to better answer fundamental disciplinary questions. In this chapter we argue that recent developments, related to both increased computing power and data collection ability along with broader cultural shifts emphasizing interdependencies, have positioned Social Network Analysis (SNA) as a powerful tool for empirically studying the dynamic and processual view of schooling that is at the heart of educational theory. More specifically, we explore how SNA can help us both better understand as well as reconceptualize two central topics in the sociology of education: classroom interaction and status attainment. We conclude with a brief discussion about possible future directions network analysis may take in educational research, positing that it will become an increasingly valuable research approach because our ability to collect streaming behavioral and transactional data is growing rapidly. INTRODUCTION In recent years Social Network Analysis (SNA) has become increasingly common in numerous sociological sub-disciplines, the result being a host of innovative research that tackles old and new problems alike. Students of the sociology of knowledge, for example, use networks of journal co-citations as a novel method for tracking the diffusion of new ideas through the academy (e.g., Hargens 2000; Moody 2004). Political sociologists are drawing on SNA to understand the dynamics of collective action (Diani 1995; Tarrow 1994). Organizational sociologists use formal and informal work networks to study organizational learning (Hansen 1999; Rawlings et.al.
    [Show full text]
  • It's Only Wrong If It's Transactional: Moral Perceptions of Obfuscated
    It’s Only Wrong If It’s Transactional: Moral Perceptions of Obfuscated Exchange Forthcoming in American Sociological Review Acknowledgments: The authors gratefully acknowledge the comments and contributions provided by Aleksander Ellis, Alan Fiske, Sarah Harkness, Linda Molm, Martin Reimann, Reihan Salam, three anonymous reviewers, the ASR Editors, and participants of the Innovation and Creativity Workshop at UCLA Anderson School of Management, the 2016 Southern California Symposium on Network Economics and Game Theory at UCLA, the Organizational Behavior Seminar at Stanford GSB, the Duke University Department of Sociology Colloquium, and the 2017 American Sociological Association Regular Session on Economic Sociology. Oliver Schilke The University of Arizona, Eller College of Management Gabriel Rossman UCLA, Department of Sociology Funding: Preparation of this article was supported in part by a Research Small Grant from the Center for Leadership Ethics, Eller College of Management to the first author and a UCLA Senate Faculty Research Grant to the second author. Keywords: obfuscation, economic sociology, bribery, legitimacy, vignette experiments Corresponding Author: Gabriel Rossman, UCLA, Department of Sociology, 264 Haines Hall, Los Angeles, CA 90095-1551, USA Phone: 310-206-8904, Fax: 310-206-9838, E-mail: [email protected] ABSTRACT A wide class of economic exchanges, such as bribery and compensated adoption, are considered morally disreputable precisely because they are seen as economic exchanges. However, parties to these exchanges can structurally obfuscate them by arranging the transfers so as to obscure that a disreputable exchange is occurring at all. In this paper, we propose that four obfuscation structures—bundling, brokerage, gift exchange, and pawning—will decrease the moral opprobrium of external audiences by (1) masking intentionality, (2) reducing the explicitness of the reciprocal nature, and (3) making the exchange appear to be a type of common practice.
    [Show full text]
  • Journal of the Swedenborgian Church
    2020 Journal of the Swedenborgian Church No. 198 THE SWEDENBORGIAN CHURCH UNITED STATES AND CANADA INCORPORATED 1861 THE GENERAL CONVENTION OF THE NEW JERUSALEM IN THE UNITED STATES OF AMERICA ANNUAL SESSION “20/20 SPIRITUAL VISION: TRANSCENDING TIME AND SPACE” JUNE 26 - JUNE 28, 2020 VIRTUAL CONVENTION HOSTED ON FACEBOOK LIVE ANNUAL THEME THE YEAR OF THE LORD JULY 1, 2019-SEPTEMBER 1, 2020 RECORDING SECRETARY KAREN CONGER 314 APOLLO CIRCLE BISHOP, CA 93514-7051 P: (760) 872-3392 E: [email protected] CENTRAL OFFICE BRITTANY PRICE, OPERATIONS MANAGER 50 QUINCY STREET CAMBRIDGE, MA 02138-3013 P: (617) 969-4240 F: (833) 843-3611 E: [email protected] W: www.swedenborg.org LETTER FROM THE PRESIDENT Oh, what a year! The 2020 Journal is different due to the COVID-19 pandemic that affected the annual session of Convention, the requirement for our churches to move to virtual services, and our camps not able to gather in-person, due to health safety concerns. It is important to produce an annual Journal because it is our legal record of the business and gather- ings for the year between our annual sessions. The decision to cancel the planned 2020 Convention in Bridgewater, Massachusetts due to the worldwide pandemic was made by the Executive Committee of General Council, March 2020. By that time it was evident we would be unable to gather in physical presence due to mandated travel restrictions and worldwide health concerns for potential transmission of the COVID-19 virus. Our denomination came up with a “virtual” process to gather as a sa- cred community to worship, learn, share, and participate in many aspects of a regular convention over the same weekend previously planned, June 26-28, 2020.
    [Show full text]
  • Explicating Emotions
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by D-Scholarship@Pitt EXPLICATING EMOTIONS by Andrea Scarantino B.S., Economics, Bocconi University, 1994 M.S., Philosophy of the Social Sciences, London School of Economics and Political Science, 1997 Ph.D., Economics, Universita’ Cattolica, 2000 M.A., Philosophy, University of Pittsburgh, 2005 Submitted to the Graduate Faculty of University of Pittsburgh in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy University of Pittsburgh 2005 UNIVERSITY OF PITTSBURGH FACULTY OF ARTS AND SCIENCES This dissertation was presented by Andrea Scarantino It was defended on July 20, 2005 and approved by Paul Griffiths, ARC Federation Fellow and Professor of Philosophy, Department of Philosophy, University of Queensland (Co-Director) Peter Machamer, Professor of Philosophy, Department of History and Philosophy of Science, University of Pittsburgh (Co-Director) Bob Brandom, Distinguished Service Professor of Philosophy, Department of Philosophy, University of Pittsburgh Ruth Millikan, Emeritus Professor of Philosophy, Department of Philosophy, University of Connecticut (Outside Reader) ii Copyright © by Andrea Scarantino 2005 iii EXPLICATING EMOTIONS Andrea Scarantino, PhD University of Pittsburgh, 2005 In the course of their long intellectual history, emotions have been identified with items as diverse as perceptions of bodily changes (feeling tradition), judgments (cognitivist tradition), behavioral predispositions (behaviorist tradition), biologically based solutions to fundamental life tasks (evolutionary tradition), and culturally specific social artifacts (social constructionist tradition). The first objective of my work is to put some order in the mare magnum of theories of emotions. I taxonomize them into families and explore the historical origin and current credentials of the arguments and intuitions supporting them.
    [Show full text]
  • Contextual Adaptation. Human Functioning As Dynamic Interaction: a Social Work Perspective
    University of Pennsylvania ScholarlyCommons Doctorate in Social Work (DSW) Dissertations School of Social Policy and Practice Spring 5-13-2013 Contextual Adaptation. Human Functioning as Dynamic Interaction: A Social Work Perspective Naomi B F Pollock University of Pennsylvania, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://repository.upenn.edu/edissertations_sp2 Part of the Social Work Commons Recommended Citation Pollock, Naomi B F, "Contextual Adaptation. Human Functioning as Dynamic Interaction: A Social Work Perspective" (2013). Doctorate in Social Work (DSW) Dissertations. 35. https://repository.upenn.edu/edissertations_sp2/35 This paper is posted at ScholarlyCommons. https://repository.upenn.edu/edissertations_sp2/35 For more information, please contact [email protected]. Contextual Adaptation. Human Functioning as Dynamic Interaction: A Social Work Perspective Abstract Despite the recent development of theories in the social sciences that define human development and functioning in an integrated, nuanced and complex manner, the social work concept of “person-in- environment” remains outdated and limited. This is in part due to the “person” and “environment”--the biological, psychological, and social environments--being defined in distinction from one another. In order to remain current and effective in arguing on behalf of a clear professional voice in the field, social workers must not only engender but also promote a fundamental practice perspective that addresses complexity. A reformulation of “person-in-environment” can help social workers more fully realize the desire to unite under the common professional mandates requiring that both a “person-in-environment” perspective and a full biopsychosocial picture be taken into clinical accounts. To meet this aim I develop the concept of contextual adaptation, a new definition of person-in-envir“ onment” reliant on tenets of nonlinear dynamic systems theory, specifically chaos theory.
    [Show full text]
  • Theoretical Underpinnings of European Union
    IOSR Journal Of Humanities And Social Science (IOSR-JHSS) Volume 20, Issue 1, Ver. III (Jan. 2015), PP 29-33 e-ISSN: 2279-0837, p-ISSN: 2279-0845. www.iosrjournals.org Theoretical Underpinnings of European Union Maneesha Tripathi*1 1Ph.D. Scholar, Department of Political Science, JamiaMilliaIslamia, New Delhi Abstract: The aftermath of Second World War offered a prospect of utter misery and desolation. Europeans felt hopeless and exhausted. The objective of peace went hand in hand with desire to ensure that Europe was able to get back on its feet economically after 1945. The proponents of European integration advanced theories for integration that involved gradual surrendering of sovereignty to a supranational entity. The ECSC was the first step towards European Union. The post 1945, regionalism emerged out of gradual process of integration from a six member organization to today 27 members European Union; from an inter-governmental organization to a supranational entity.The paper looks at the theoretical framework of European integration. Keywords:European Union, Functionalism, Liberalism, Realism, Regional Integration. I. Introduction The institutional architecture and the multi-level governance make European Union a reference point or a yardstick for regional integration experiments. EU is the only example of regional integration which has endeavoured for political integration along with economic integration where approach has been supranational. It was set up with the aim of ending the frequent wars within Europe. Extreme form of nationalism had devastated the continent. European integration was seen as the remedy to create a no war zone within Europe. This process began with the formation of council of Europe in1949, the European steel and coal community in 1950.
    [Show full text]
  • Hilary Putnam (1926–2016): a Lifetime Quest to Understand the Relationship Between Mind, Language, and Reality
    c 2016 Imprint Academic Mind & Matter Vol. 14(1), pp. 87{95 Hilary Putnam (1926{2016): A Lifetime Quest to Understand the Relationship between Mind, Language, and Reality David Leech Anderson Department of Philosophy Illinois State University, Normal, USA Hilary Putnam was one of the most influential philosophers of the 20th century. His peers have called him \one of the finest minds I've ever encountered" (Noam Chomsky) and \one of the greatest philosophers this nation has ever produced" (Martha Nussbaum). Standard obituaries covering his \life and times" are available in the mass media.1 This essay 1See, e.g., the New York Times (www.nytimes.com/2016/03/18/arts/hilary- putnam-giant-of-modern-philosophy-dies-at-89.html), the Guardian (www. theguardian.com/books/2016/mar/14/hilary-putnam-obituary), or the Huffington 88 Anderson will focus exclusively on the legacy he has left from his published works and from the way he has modeled a philosopher's life. Hilary Putnam was a towering figure in philosophy of language, phi- losophy of mind, and in metaphysics, and special attention will be paid (below) to those contributions. His influence, however, extends well be- yond those boundaries. He has published works in dozens of different research areas, of which the following is only a small sample. Early in his career he contributed (with Martin Davis, Yuri Matiyasevich, and Julia Robinson) to the solution of Hilbert's 10th problem, a major result in mathematics which, together with other related accomplishments, would have warranted an appointment in a mathematics department. While his central focus was not ethics and political philosophy he advanced a sus- tained attack on the fact-value distinction { a central presupposition of logical positivism and a position that he thought continued to influence research in many areas to deleterious effect.
    [Show full text]
  • Annual Report
    FIFTY-FOURTH ANNUAL REPORT OP THE AMERICAN BOARD OF COMMISSIONERS ron FOREIGN MISSIONS, PRESENTED AT THE MEETING HELD AT WORCESTER, MASS. OCTOBER 4 - 7 , 1864. BOSTON: PRESS OF T. R. MARTIN & SON, 42 CONGRESS STREET. 1 864. A/PL A v. T 9 ANNUAL MEETING. T h e A m e r i c a n B o a r d o f C ommissioners f o r F o r e ig n M is ­ s io n s held its fifty-fifth Annual Meeting at Worcester, Massachu­ setts, in Mechanics’ Hall, commencing Tuesday, October 4, at 4 o’clock, P. M ., and closing Friday, October 7, at 11 o’clock, A. M. CORPORATE MEMBERS PRESENT. Maine. Hon. Samuel Williston. Enoch Pond, D. D. Rev. Selah B. Treat. William T. Dwight, D. I). Hon. William J. Hubbard. John W . Chiekering, D. D. Henry B. Hooker, D. D. George E. Adams, D. D. Hon. Linus Child. William W. Thomas, Esq. Samuel M. Worcester, D. D. Amos D. Lockwood, Esq. Andrew W. Porter, Esq. Hon. Samuel H. Walley. New Hampshire. Augustus C. Thompson, D. D. Zedekiah S. Barstow, D. D. Hon; William T. Eustis. John K. Young, D. D. Hon. John Aiken. Asa D. Smith, D. D. John Todd, D. D. Nathaniel Bouton, D. D. Seth Sweetser, D. D. Hon. William Haile. James M. Gordon, Esq. Rev. Alvan Tobey. Amos Blanchard, D. D. Edward Spalding, M. D. Hon. Alpheus Hardy. Vermont. Hon. Reuben A. Chapman. Silas Aiken, D. D. William S. South worth, Esq. ^ Rev. Joseph Steele. Abner Kingman, Esq. Si J, Lewis H.
    [Show full text]
  • {FREE} Does the Center Hold? an Introduction to Western Philosophy
    DOES THE CENTER HOLD? AN INTRODUCTION TO WESTERN PHILOSOPHY 6TH EDITION PDF, EPUB, EBOOK Donald Palmer | --- | --- | --- | 9780078038372 | --- | --- Does the Center Hold? An Introduction to Western Philosophy 6th edition PDF Book The Nicene definition established the meaning of faith which Christians were to hold and its defenders had recourse less to philosophical or theological speculation than to the Scripture as they understood it. No CD Included. Ideas do not have origin in experience…we approach the world with ideals: truth, beauty, the good; in addition to the value-concepts. In addition, intrigued by the manner in which Christian theology was drawing on nineteeth- and twentieth-century European philosophies, pockets of so-called Buddhist-Christian dialogue began to emerge and fully blossomed in the post-censorship era after This means, especially, that even while a crisis may exist its nature may not be what it is commonly held to be. Jacobi — The universe is a cosmos—a beautiful, well-ordered, perfect whole. Should that arrangement end, each of the pair returns to his or her originally discrete individuality and attendant rights. As for utilitarianism, they admired its consequentialist ethics that used an empirically derived cost-benefit analysis to determine what would bring maximum happiness or pleasure for society as a whole. Paper Cavalier Italia via United States. At the time, Descartes was working on The World , a study he thought would revolutionize the study of physics. Usually ships within 4 to 5 days. Book Deals via United States. My comment: yet it is clear to imagine ways in which synthetic judgments may be universal and necessary: our very formation may be so in attune with the universe that certain facets of our perceptual-cognitive systems may render synthetic contentful judgments that are always true universal and represent the very nature of the universe necessary.
    [Show full text]
  • Perception and Scientific Observation: a Challenge to the Assumption of Objectivity
    University of New Hampshire University of New Hampshire Scholars' Repository Doctoral Dissertations Student Scholarship Winter 1971 PERCEPTION AND SCIENTIFIC OBSERVATION: A CHALLENGE TO THE ASSUMPTION OF OBJECTIVITY RAYMOND E. RAINVILLE Follow this and additional works at: https://scholars.unh.edu/dissertation Recommended Citation RAINVILLE, RAYMOND E., "PERCEPTION AND SCIENTIFIC OBSERVATION: A CHALLENGE TO THE ASSUMPTION OF OBJECTIVITY" (1971). Doctoral Dissertations. 939. https://scholars.unh.edu/dissertation/939 This Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by the Student Scholarship at University of New Hampshire Scholars' Repository. It has been accepted for inclusion in Doctoral Dissertations by an authorized administrator of University of New Hampshire Scholars' Repository. For more information, please contact [email protected]. RAINVILLE, Raymond E., 1940- PERCEPTION AND SCIENTIFIC OBSERVATION: A CHALLENGE TO THE ASSUMPTION OF OBJECTIVITY. University of New Hampshire, Ph.D., 1971 Psychology, general University Microfilms, AXEROX Company, Ann Arbor, Michigan I ___________ _ r_______ ___________________ J THIS DISSERTATION HAS BEEN MICROFILMED EXACTLY AS RECEIVED PERCEPTION AND SCIENTIFIC OBSERVATION: A CHALLENGE TO THE ASSUMPTION OF OBJECTIVITY by RAYMOND E. RAINVILLE A THESIS Submitted to the University of New Hampshire In Partial Fulfillment of The Requirements for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy Graduate School Department of Psychology December, 1970 This thesis has been examined and approved. Thesis director, Frederick Jervis, Professor of Psychology RaymoA6 Erickson,Professor of Psychology Eugene Mills, Professor of Psychology Cecil Schneer, Professor of Geology ft oM/jcb Robert Watson, Professor of Psychology / J /ia m Duane Whittier, ‘Associate Professor of Philosophy TABLE OF CONTENTS LIST OF TABLES..................................... iv LIST OF FIGURES...................................
    [Show full text]