Notes on Euthydemus

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Notes on Euthydemus 2011 Carrie Elizabeth Swanson ALL RIGHTS RESERVED SOCRATIC DIALECTIC AND THE RESOLUTION OF FALLACY IN PLATO‟S EUTHYDEMUS by CARRIE ELIZABETH SWANSON A Dissertation submitted to the Graduate School-New Brunswick Rutgers, The State University of New Jersey in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy Graduate Program in Philosophy written under the direction of Alan Code and Robert Bolton and approved by ________________________ ________________________ ________________________ ________________________ ________________________ New Brunswick, New Jersey May, 2011 ABSTRACT OF THE DISSERTATION SOCRATIC DIALECTIC AND THE RESOLUTION OF FALLACY IN PLATO‟S EUTHYDEMUS By CARRIE ELIZABETH SWANSON Dissertation Co-Directors: Alan Code and Robert Bolton My dissertation is devoted to an examination of the resolution of fallacy in Plato's Euthydemus. I argue that the Socratic response to fallacious reasoning is conducted at two different levels of philosophical sophistication. Socrates relies upon the resources of Socratic dialectic in responding to sophisms due to ignorance of refutation. Insofar as Socratic dialectic is grounded in a grasp of the nature of genuine refutation, the objections it raises to false refutation are fully explanatory. On the other hand, Socrates employs various self-refutation arguments against theses which depend on false assumptions regarding the nature of predication. While this method of examination cannot explain why the sophists‟ theses are false, these limitations on Socratic expertise are overcome in other passages in the dialogue which are replete with clues to the reader that point to a genuine explanation and resolution of the sophists‟ arguments for their various theses. Here Plato implicitly relies on the results of what I call higher dialectic. I conclude that the Euthydemus is concerned to identify Socratic dialectic as only a part of philosophy---thus anticipating the Sophist’s conception of Socrates as the practitioner of a „noble sophistry‟, (gennai&a sofistikh&, 231b3-8) and the elenchus as a propaedeutic to philosophy, which purges the soul of false beliefs. ii Table of Contents Introduction 1 Chapter One 15 1.1 Between Philosophy and Politics 15 1.2 Good Arts and Bad Arts 27 1.3 Between Good Arts and Bad 37 1.4 Winners and Losers 45 Chapter Two 54 2.1 The First Protreptic Episode 54 2.2 The Second Protreptic Episode: Producers and Users 61 2.3 Into the Labyrinth 64 2.4 The Aporia Resolved 75 Chapter Three 82 3.1 Socratic Dialectic 82 3.2 The First Eristic Episode: Learning about „Correctness in Names‟ 94 3.3 The Second Eristic Episode: the Impossibility of False Speaking 112 3.4 An Antisthenian Interlude 132 3.5 The Impossibility of Contradiction 144 3.6 The Socratic response: Self-Refutation Arguments 149 3.7 The Socratic Art of Refutation: an Initial Characterization 174 Chapter Four 4.1 The Final Eristic Episode: Plato on Secundum Quid and Ignoratio Elenchi 180 4.2 The Omniscience Argument 183 4.3 Plato and Aristotle on the Solution of Secundum Quid 193 4.4 The Always Omniscient Argument 203 4.5 Plato and Aristotle on the Fallacy of Ignoratio Elenchi 211 4.6 Socratic Dialectic and the Production of Paradox 235 4.7 Secundum Quid in the Sophist 239 4.8 Taking Stock 247 iii Chapter Five 254 5.1 Plato on the Distinctness of Secundum Quid, Homonymy, and Accident 254 5.2 The Other Than F → Not-F Argument 256 5.3 The Dog Fallacy 265 5.4 Plato‟s Examination of the Dog Fallacy 283 5.5 Medicine and Monsters 285 5.6 The Gold Fallacy 291 5.7 Aristotle Against the Double Signification of the Genitive Case 297 5.8 The God Fallacy 301 5.9 Amphiboly and Many Questions in the Euthydemus 314 5.10 Socrates‟ Iolaus and the Taxonomy of Fallacy 322 Chapter Six 325 6.1 Socratic Dialectic and the Causal Explanation of Fallacy 325 6.2 Dionysodorus‟ Ox: Other Than F → Not-F Redux 333 6.3 The Final Self-Refutation Argument 365 Conclusion 373 Bibliography 375 Curriculum Vitae 381 iv 1 Introduction The Euthydemus is certainly the funniest dialogue in the Platonic corpus. It is also one of the strangest. What exactly is the joke and what is the nature of this comedy? If it is a parody, what does it satirize? If its sole purpose is to amuse, why would Plato implicate that unfunniest of gods in such a farce? As Socrates explains to Crito, the whole riot began when the god ordered Socrates to engage the sophists Euthydemus and Dionysodorus in conversation: As good luck would have it, I was sitting by myself in the undressing-room just where you [Crito] saw me and I was already thinking of leaving. But when I got up, my customary divine sign (to\ ei0wqo\j shmei=on to^ daimo&nion) put in an appearance. So I sat down again, and in a moment the two of them, Euthydemus and Dionysodorus, came in… (272e1-273a2)1 Apollo‟s divine intervention, combined with the brothers‟ subsequent claims to wisdom (at 273d8-9, 274a5, and 274a10-b1), rouses our expectation that despite all the horseplay, the dialogue‟s underlying purpose is as serious as any elenctic encounter dramatized in the earlier Socratic dialogues: surely the soldier of Apollo will disabuse the pretenders to virtue of their conceit? This seriousness of purpose is underscored by Socrates himself in his initial challenge to the sophists: Put off the rest of your display to another time and give a demonstration of this one thing: persuade this young man here [i.e., Cleinias] that he ought to love wisdom and have a care for virtue (pei&saton w9j xrh\ filosofei=n kai\ a0reth=j e0pimelei=sqai), and you will oblige both me and all the present company. The boy‟s situation is this: both I and all these people want him to become as good as possible…He is young, and we are anxious about him, as one naturally is about a boy of his age, for fear that somebody might get in ahead of us and turn his mind to some other interest and ruin him (e0p a@llo ti e0pith&deuma tre&yaj au0tou= th&n dia&noian kai& diafqei&rh|). If you have no objection, make trial of the boy (pei=ran tou= meiraki&ou) and converse with him in our presence. (275a4-275b6) 1 Unless otherwise indicated, translation of the Euthydemus is from Sprague (1993) with modifications. 2 There is scarcely any task more serious than the protreptic task of exhorting the young to the care of the soul. It is noteworthy then that Plato makes Socrates insist from the start that the silliness (and the sadism) of the sophists is therefore not funny under the circumstances: These things are the frivolous part of study (which is why I also tell you that the men are jesting); and I call these things “frivolity” (padia^n) because even if a man were to learn many or even all such things, he would be none the wiser as to how matters stand but would only be able to make fun of people, tripping them up and overturning them by means of distinctions in words, just like people who pull the chair out from under a man who is going to sit down and then laugh gleefully when they see him sprawling on his back…They said they would give a demonstration of hortatory skill (protreptikh^n sofia&n), but now it seems to me that they have thought it necessary to make fun of you before beginning. So, Euthydemus and Dionysodorus, put an end to this joking; I think we have had enough of it. (278b2-278d1) Neither is anyone to laugh at Socrates‟ protreptic counter-demonstration: The next thing to do is to give an exhibition of persuading the young man that he ought to devote himself to wisdom and virtue (e0pidei&caton protre&ponte to\ meira&kion o$pwj xrh\ sofi&aj te kai\ a0reth=j e0pimelhqh=nai). But first I shall give you two a demonstration of the way in which I conceive the undertaking and of the sort of thing I want to hear. And if I seem to you to be doing this in an unprofessional and ridiculous way, don‟t laugh at me (i0diwtikw=j te kai\ geloi&wj au0to\ poiei=n, mh& mou katagela=te)---it is out of a desire to hear your wisdom that I have the audacity to improvise in front of you. Therefore, you and your disciples restrain yourselves and listen without laughing… (278d1-278e2) We are led to expect therefore that the dialogue has a serious moral purpose. We are also led to expect that this purpose is two-fold: somewhere in the eristic scenes, the sophists will be refuted; in the protreptic scenes, Cleinias will be persuaded to devote himself to philosophy. On both counts, however, our expectations seem to be dashed. Socrates‟ encounters with the sophists seem more designed as a comic demonstration that they are incorrigible candidates for elenctic refutation, irredeemable by the elenctic art. And while the first protreptic scene ends on a promising note… Now then, since you [Cleinias] believe both that [wisdom] can be taught and that it is the only existing thing which makes a man happy and fortunate, surely you would agree that it is necessary to love wisdom and you mean to do this yourself (a0nangkai=on ei0=nai filosofei=n). 3 This is just what I mean to do, Socrates, as well as ever I can! (282c8-282d3) …Socrates‟ second protreptic speech (288d5-292e7) ends in aporia; worse still, the very respondent to whom his speech is addressed is mysteriously supplanted at a critical juncture, his answers impersonated by a „superior being‟—thinly disguised as Socrates himself: What do you mean, Socrates? Did that boy utter all this? You‟re not convinced of it, Crito? Good heavens, no! Because, in my opinion, if he spoke like that, he needs no education (paidei&an), either from Euthydemus or anyone else.
Recommended publications
  • CHAPTER XXX. of Fallacies. Section 827. After Examining the Conditions on Which Correct Thoughts Depend, It Is Expedient to Clas
    CHAPTER XXX. Of Fallacies. Section 827. After examining the conditions on which correct thoughts depend, it is expedient to classify some of the most familiar forms of error. It is by the treatment of the Fallacies that logic chiefly vindicates its claim to be considered a practical rather than a speculative science. To explain and give a name to fallacies is like setting up so many sign-posts on the various turns which it is possible to take off the road of truth. Section 828. By a fallacy is meant a piece of reasoning which appears to establish a conclusion without really doing so. The term applies both to the legitimate deduction of a conclusion from false premisses and to the illegitimate deduction of a conclusion from any premisses. There are errors incidental to conception and judgement, which might well be brought under the name; but the fallacies with which we shall concern ourselves are confined to errors connected with inference. Section 829. When any inference leads to a false conclusion, the error may have arisen either in the thought itself or in the signs by which the thought is conveyed. The main sources of fallacy then are confined to two-- (1) thought, (2) language. Section 830. This is the basis of Aristotle's division of fallacies, which has not yet been superseded. Fallacies, according to him, are either in the language or outside of it. Outside of language there is no source of error but thought. For things themselves do not deceive us, but error arises owing to a misinterpretation of things by the mind.
    [Show full text]
  • The Roles of Solon in Plato's Dialogues
    The Roles of Solon in Plato’s Dialogues Dissertation Presented in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the Degree Doctor of Philosophy in the Graduate School of The Ohio State University By Samuel Ortencio Flores, M.A. Graduate Program in Greek and Latin The Ohio State University 2013 Dissertation Committee: Bruce Heiden, Advisor Anthony Kaldellis Richard Fletcher Greg Anderson Copyrighy by Samuel Ortencio Flores 2013 Abstract This dissertation is a study of Plato’s use and adaptation of an earlier model and tradition of wisdom based on the thought and legacy of the sixth-century archon, legislator, and poet Solon. Solon is cited and/or quoted thirty-four times in Plato’s dialogues, and alluded to many more times. My study shows that these references and allusions have deeper meaning when contextualized within the reception of Solon in the classical period. For Plato, Solon is a rhetorically powerful figure in advancing the relatively new practice of philosophy in Athens. While Solon himself did not adequately establish justice in the city, his legacy provided a model upon which Platonic philosophy could improve. Chapter One surveys the passing references to Solon in the dialogues as an introduction to my chapters on the dialogues in which Solon is a very prominent figure, Timaeus- Critias, Republic, and Laws. Chapter Two examines Critias’ use of his ancestor Solon to establish his own philosophic credentials. Chapter Three suggests that Socrates re- appropriates the aims and themes of Solon’s political poetry for Socratic philosophy. Chapter Four suggests that Solon provides a legislative model which Plato reconstructs in the Laws for the philosopher to supplant the role of legislator in Greek thought.
    [Show full text]
  • Teachers' Pay in Ancient Greece
    University of Nebraska - Lincoln DigitalCommons@University of Nebraska - Lincoln Papers from the University Studies series (The University of Nebraska) University Studies of the University of Nebraska 5-1942 Teachers' Pay In Ancient Greece Clarence A. Forbes Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.unl.edu/univstudiespapers Part of the Arts and Humanities Commons This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the University Studies of the University of Nebraska at DigitalCommons@University of Nebraska - Lincoln. It has been accepted for inclusion in Papers from the University Studies series (The University of Nebraska) by an authorized administrator of DigitalCommons@University of Nebraska - Lincoln. Teachers' Pay In Ancient Greece * * * * * CLARENCE A. FORBES UNIVERSITY OF NEBRASKA STUDIES Ma y 1942 STUDIES IN THE HUMANITIES NO.2 Note to Cataloger UNDER a new plan the volume number as well as the copy number of the University of Nebraska Studies was discontinued and only the numbering of the subseries carried on, distinguished by the month and the year of pu blica tion. Thus the present paper continues the subseries "Studies in the Humanities" begun with "University of Nebraska Studies, Volume 41, Number 2, August 1941." The other subseries of the University of Nebraska Studies, "Studies in Science and Technology," and "Studies in Social Science," are continued according to the above plan. Publications in all three subseries will be supplied to recipients of the "University Studies" series. Corre­ spondence and orders should be addressed to the Uni­ versity Editor, University of Nebraska, Lincoln. University of Nebraska Studies May 1942 TEACHERS' PAY IN ANCIENT GREECE * * * CLARENCE A.
    [Show full text]
  • There Is No Fallacy of Arguing from Authority
    There is no Fallacy ofArguing from Authority EDWIN COLEMAN University ofMelbourne Keywords: fallacy, argument, authority, speech act. Abstract: I argue that there is no fallacy of argument from authority. I first show the weakness of the case for there being such a fallacy: text-book presentations are confused, alleged examples are not genuinely exemplary, reasons given for its alleged fallaciousness are not convincing. Then I analyse arguing from authority as a complex speech act. R~iecting the popular but unjustified category of the "part-time fallacy", I show that bad arguments which appeal to authority are defective through breach of some felicity condition on argument as a speech act, not through employing a bad principle of inference. 1. Introduction/Summary There's never been a satisfactory theory of fallacy, as Hamblin pointed out in his book of 1970, in what is still the least unsatisfactory discussion. Things have not much improved in the last 25 years, despite fallacies getting more attention as interest in informal logic has grown. We still lack good answers to simple questions like what is a fallacy?, what fallacies are there? and how should we classifY fallacies? The idea that argument from authority (argumentum ad verecundiam) is a fallacy, is well-established in logical tradition. I argue that it is no such thing. The second main part of the paper is negative: I show the weakness of the case made in the literature for there being such a fallacy as argument from authority. First, text-book presentation of the fallacy is confused, second, the examples given are not genuinely exemplary and third, reasons given for its alleged fallaciousness are not convincing.
    [Show full text]
  • Plato's Euthydemus
    PLATO’S EUTHYDEMUS: A STUDY ON THE RELATIONS BETWEEN LOGIC AND EDUCATION Plato’s Euthydemus is an unlucky dialogue. Few dealt with it in its own right, not just as part of a wider discussion of Plato, and fewer still saw in it more than a topic of sophistic fallacies. Some, of course, paid attention to the constructive sections of the dialogue, but only rarely do we come across a real attempt to unify its different aspects.1 In this paper I propose to show how, in the Euthydemus, Plato tries to distinguish between the Socratic and the Sophistic conceptions of education, by tracing them to their roots in the opposing views of the Sophists — and especially those of the second generation — and of Socrates about truth and about the role of logic. And although the eristic techniques of Euthydemus and Dionysodorus are obviously fallacious, they turn out to be developments of Protagoras’ views and follow from philosophical positions worthy of serious examination. The Euthydemus is a caricature, to be sure. But, as all good caricature, it has a serious intent. It sketches the degeneration of the Sophistic approach to education, in some of its aspects. More important­ ly, it distinguishes Socratic education from the methods and effects of its Sophistic counterpart. Euthydemus and Dionysodorus, the two sophist brothers, are reminis­ cent of the great Sophists of the Protagoras in more than one way. They are polymaths like Hippias, and at one time or another have taught a variety of arts, from forensic rhetoric to armed combat. Also, they have Prodicus’ penchant for linguistic analysis.
    [Show full text]
  • On the Arrangement of the Platonic Dialogues
    Ryan C. Fowler 25th Hour On the Arrangement of the Platonic Dialogues I. Thrasyllus a. Diogenes Laertius (D.L.), Lives and Opinions of Eminent Philosophers 3.56: “But, just as long ago in tragedy the chorus was the only actor, and afterwards, in order to give the chorus breathing space, Thespis devised a single actor, Aeschylus a second, Sophocles a third, and thus tragedy was completed, so too with philosophy: in early times it discoursed on one subject only, namely physics, then Socrates added the second subject, ethics, and Plato the third, dialectics, and so brought philosophy to perfection. Thrasyllus says that he [Plato] published his dialogues in tetralogies, like those of the tragic poets. Thus they contended with four plays at the Dionysia, the Lenaea, the Panathenaea and the festival of Chytri. Of the four plays the last was a satiric drama; and the four together were called a tetralogy.” b. Characters or types of dialogues (D.L. 3.49): 1. instructive (ὑφηγητικός) A. theoretical (θεωρηµατικόν) a. physical (φυσικόν) b. logical (λογικόν) B. practical (πρακτικόν) a. ethical (ἠθικόν) b. political (πολιτικόν) 2. investigative (ζητητικός) A. training the mind (γυµναστικός) a. obstetrical (µαιευτικός) b. tentative (πειραστικός) B. victory in controversy (ἀγωνιστικός) a. critical (ἐνδεικτικός) b. subversive (ἀνατρεπτικός) c. Thrasyllan categories of the dialogues (D.L. 3.50-1): Physics: Timaeus Logic: Statesman, Cratylus, Parmenides, and Sophist Ethics: Apology, Crito, Phaedo, Phaedrus, Symposium, Menexenus, Clitophon, the Letters, Philebus, Hipparchus, Rivals Politics: Republic, the Laws, Minos, Epinomis, Atlantis Obstetrics: Alcibiades 1 and 2, Theages, Lysis, Laches Tentative: Euthyphro, Meno, Io, Charmides and Theaetetus Critical: Protagoras Subversive: Euthydemus, Gorgias, and Hippias 1 and 2 :1 d.
    [Show full text]
  • The Birth of Rhetoric: Gorgias, Plato and Their Successors
    THE BIRTH OF RHETORIC ISSUES IN ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY General editor: Malcolm Schofield GOD IN GREEK PHILOSOPHY Studies in the early history of natural theology L.P.Gerson ANCIENT CONCEPTS OF PHILOSOPHY William Jordan LANGUAGE, THOUGHT AND FALSEHOOD IN ANCIENT GREEK PHILOSOPHY Nicholas Denyer MENTAL CONFLICT Anthony Price THE BIRTH OF RHETORIC Gorgias, Plato and their successors Robert Wardy London and New York First published 1996 by Routledge 11 New Fetter Lane, London EC4P 4EE This edition published in the Taylor & Francis e-Library, 2005. “To purchase your own copy of this or any of Taylor & Francis or Routledge’s collection of thousands of eBooks please go to www.eBookstore.tandf.co.uk.” Simultaneously published in the USA and Canada by Routledge 29 West 35th Street, New York, NY 10001 First published in paperback 1998 © 1996 Robert Wardy All rights reserved. No part of this book may be reprinted or reproduced or utilized in any form or by any electronic, mechanical, or other means, now known or hereafter invented, including photocopying and recording, or in any information storage or retrieval system, without permission in writing from the publishers. British Library Cataloguing in Publication Data A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library Library of Congress Cataloguing in Publication Data Wardy, Robert. The birth of rhetoric: Gorgias, Plato, and their successors/ Robert Wardy. p. cm.—(Issues in ancient philsophy) Includes bibliographical rerferences (p. ) and index. 1. Plato. Gorgias. 2. Rhetoric, Ancient.
    [Show full text]
  • Critical Review All While Still Others Are Characterized Inadequately Or Incompletely
    12 Some should not be classified as fallacies of relevance at critical review all while still others are characterized inadequately or incompletely. Copi maintains that in all fallacies of rele­ vance "their premisses are logically irrelevant to, and therefore incapable of establishing the truth of their conclusions" (pp. 9S-99). But this definition does not apply to the most important of the fallacies of relevance, the irrelevant conclusion (ignoratio elenchi). According to Copi, this fallacy is committed "when an argument sup­ Copi's Sixth Edition posedly intended to establish a particular conclusion is directed to proving a different conclusion" (p. 110). Copi even allows that the fallacy can be committed by one who may" succeed in proving his (irrelevant) conclusion" (my italics). The fault then is not that the premisses of such Ronald Roblin arguments are logically irrelevant to the conclusion drawn State University College at Buffalo from them, but that the conclusion drawn is insufficient to justify the conclusion called for by the context. If a prosecutor, purporting to prove the defendant guilty of murder, shows on Iy that he had sufficient opportunity and Copi, Irving. Introduction to l~gic. 6th edition. New motive to commit the crime, he (the prosecutor) commits York: Macmillan, 19S2. x. 604 pp.ISBN o-02-324920-X the fallacy of insufficient conclusion. If, on the other hand, he succeeds only in "proving" that murder is a horrible crime, he is guilty of an ignoratio elenchi. In effect, then, The sixth edition of this widely used and influential text Copi does not distinguish between two different fal­ is worth reviewing, first.
    [Show full text]
  • 1 Argumentation in the Framework of Deliberation
    1 ARGUMENTATION IN THE FRAMEWORK OF DELIBERATION DIALOGUE Douglas Walton, Katie Atkinson, Trevor Bench-Capon, Adam Wyner and Dan Cartwright According to argumentation theory, reasoning takes place in different types of dialogue: persuasion dialogue, negotiation, deliberation, information-seeking dialogue, inquiry, and eristic dialogue. These different dialogue types may be nested within one another. Current research in artificial intelligence is building formal models corresponding to each of these types of dialogue and showing how they can be implemented in, for example, multi-agent communications systems. In this paper, we (1) clarify the distinction between deliberation dialogue and persuasion dialogue, (2) survey some recent research in artificial intelligence studying formal properties of deliberation dialogue, (3) present a model of argumentation in deliberation dialogue that has proved to be useful in electronic democracy, and (4) argue that this model provides an attractive alternative to the dominant cost-benefit model of rational argumentation traditionally accepted in economics and other fields as the basis for evaluating argumentation of the kind used in policy decision making. One of the most important lessons of argumentation theory has been that arguments need to be analyzed and evaluated not only by identifying the logical form of an argument in abstraction from its context of use, but also by paying attention to the purpose for which an argument was supposedly used in a conversational setting. In particular, as we will show in this paper, it is vitally important to distinguish between two different types of conversational frameworks called persuasion dialogue and deliberation dialogue. As we will show, logical fallacies can easily be committed in the most common kinds of everyday reasoning by failing to take this distinction into account.
    [Show full text]
  • Reading the Proemium of Plato's Theaetetus: Euclides in Action
    Reading the Proemium of Plato’s Theaetetus: Euclides in Action Eleni Kaklamanou and Maria Pavlou HE FRAMES of the Platonic dialogues constitute a vexed and contentious issue and have been variously treated T by students of Plato throughout the centuries. Proclus classified Plato’s ancient commentators as those who pay little or no attention to the prefatory parts, those who acknowledge their moral aspect but deem them irrelevant to a dialogue’s subject-matter, and those who contend that they have a bear- ing on the main philosophical discussion.1 Modern scholars have adopted a similar stance: while some either completely ignore or attribute little philosophical significance to the proemia, others consider them to be an integral part of the dialogues and not merely ‘trimmings’ or decorative literary devices.2 This paper focuses on the opening of the Theaetetus, one of the most peculiar and paradoxical of the Platonic proemia.3 Two friends, the Megarians Euclides and Terpsion, acci- 1 Proclus In Prm. 658–659 (I 46 Steel); for comments see G. R. Morrow and J. M. Dillon, Proclus Commentary on Plato’s Parmenides (Princeton 1987) 11 and 47 n.40. For ancient views on the importance of Plato’s prologues in general see H. Tarrant, Plato’s First Interpreters (Cornell 2000) 39–40. 2 See e.g. D. Clay, “Plato’s First Words,” in F. M. Dunn and T. Cole (eds.), Beginnings in Classical Literature (Cambridge 1992) 115: “to write com- petently about the beginning of [any] Platonic Dialogue is to understand the other extremity of the dialogue, its middle, and the unity of the dialogue as a whole.” For further bibliography see W.
    [Show full text]
  • Answers and Solutions
    ANSWERS AND SOLUTIONS A Foul Ghoul Soul Loves Good Blood Food R. Lederer A FOUL GHOUL SOUL LOVES GOOD BLOOD FOOD (Other answers are possible) 1. swamp 2. boot 3. heard 4. golf 5. bowl 6. mint 7. brooch 8. breast 9. earth 10. hoof 11. kook 12. down 13. wool 14. boss 15. hog 16. cheese 17. wash 18. keen 19. break 20. font 21. sew 22. watch 23. gouge 24. scarf 25. heath 26. choose 27. doll 28. rouse 29. caste 30. are 3 1. fiend 32. drought 33. broad 34. salve 3 5. coup 36. waft 37. warm 3 8. aunt 39. dull 40. tow 41. indict 42. believe 43. again 44. segue 45. obese 46. second 47. pureed 48. parfait 49. entourage 50. eunuch 51. karaoke 52. syllable 53. calliope 54. fever 55. mousy 56. matinee 57. pastiche 58. heroin 59. layer 60. devil 61. imply 62. demon 63. frozen 64. menial 65. viscount 66. bury 67. quarry 68. beady 69. gully 70. jowly 71. ginger 72. pinto 73. wicked 74. solder 75. yodel 76. patent 77. squalor 78. daughter 79. tinder 80. bother 81. gallop 82. deface 83. dumber 84. seven 85. suet 86. whether 87. pudding 88. stingy 89. waddle 90. wattle 91. breather 92. gelato 93. malaria 94. wander 95. plunger 96. younger 97. swollen 98. warden 99. silo 100. chamber 316 Preposterous Precincts J. Puder Alifiay: Salman Rushdie, Haroun and the Sea of Stories, 1990 Atlantis: Plato, Critias, 4thcent. B.C.E. Back of the North Wind: George Macdonald, At the Back of the North Wind, 1870 Bengodi: Giovanni Boccaccio, Decameron, 185 8 Broc6liande: Alfred, Lord Termyson, The Idylls of the King, 1859-85 Centrum Terrae: Hans von Grimmelshausen, Simplicissimus, 1688 Cloudcuckooland: Aristophanes, The Birds, 414 B.C.E.
    [Show full text]
  • Quantifying Aristotle's Fallacies
    mathematics Article Quantifying Aristotle’s Fallacies Evangelos Athanassopoulos 1,* and Michael Gr. Voskoglou 2 1 Independent Researcher, Giannakopoulou 39, 27300 Gastouni, Greece 2 Department of Applied Mathematics, Graduate Technological Educational Institute of Western Greece, 22334 Patras, Greece; [email protected] or [email protected] * Correspondence: [email protected] Received: 20 July 2020; Accepted: 18 August 2020; Published: 21 August 2020 Abstract: Fallacies are logically false statements which are often considered to be true. In the “Sophistical Refutations”, the last of his six works on Logic, Aristotle identified the first thirteen of today’s many known fallacies and divided them into linguistic and non-linguistic ones. A serious problem with fallacies is that, due to their bivalent texture, they can under certain conditions disorient the nonexpert. It is, therefore, very useful to quantify each fallacy by determining the “gravity” of its consequences. This is the target of the present work, where for historical and practical reasons—the fallacies are too many to deal with all of them—our attention is restricted to Aristotle’s fallacies only. However, the tools (Probability, Statistics and Fuzzy Logic) and the methods that we use for quantifying Aristotle’s fallacies could be also used for quantifying any other fallacy, which gives the required generality to our study. Keywords: logical fallacies; Aristotle’s fallacies; probability; statistical literacy; critical thinking; fuzzy logic (FL) 1. Introduction Fallacies are logically false statements that are often considered to be true. The first fallacies appeared in the literature simultaneously with the generation of Aristotle’s bivalent Logic. In the “Sophistical Refutations” (Sophistici Elenchi), the last chapter of the collection of his six works on logic—which was named by his followers, the Peripatetics, as “Organon” (Instrument)—the great ancient Greek philosopher identified thirteen fallacies and divided them in two categories, the linguistic and non-linguistic fallacies [1].
    [Show full text]