Animal Emotion Descriptive and Prescriptive Definitions and Their

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Animal Emotion Descriptive and Prescriptive Definitions and Their Paul, E. S. , & Mendl, M. T. (2018). Animal emotion: Descriptive and prescriptive definitions and their implications for a comparative perspective. Applied Animal Behaviour Science, 205, 202-209. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.applanim.2018.01.008 Version created as part of publication process; publisher's layout; not normally made publicly available License (if available): CC BY Link to published version (if available): 10.1016/j.applanim.2018.01.008 Link to publication record in Explore Bristol Research PDF-document This is the final published version of the article (version of record). It first appeared online via Elsevier at https://www.sciencedirect.com/science/article/pii/S0168159118300285 . Please refer to any applicable terms of use of the publisher. University of Bristol - Explore Bristol Research General rights This document is made available in accordance with publisher policies. Please cite only the published version using the reference above. Full terms of use are available: http://www.bristol.ac.uk/red/research-policy/pure/user-guides/ebr-terms/ Applied Animal Behaviour Science xxx (xxxx) xxx–xxx Contents lists available at ScienceDirect Applied Animal Behaviour Science journal homepage: www.elsevier.com/locate/applanim Animal emotion: Descriptive and prescriptive definitions and their implications for a comparative perspective ⁎ Elizabeth S. Paul , Michael T. Mendl School of Veterinary Sciences, University of Bristol, Langford House, Langford, Bristol, BS40 5DU, UK ARTICLE INFO ABSTRACT Keywords: In recent years there has been a growing research interest in the field of animal emotion. But there is still little Emotion agreement about whether and how the word “emotion” should be defined for use in the context of non-human Animal emotion species. Here, we make a distinction between descriptive and prescriptive definitions. Descriptive definitions ff A ect delineate the ways in which the word emotion is used in everyday life. Prescriptive definitions are used to pick Definition out the set of events that scientific theories of emotion purport to explain. Picking out three prescriptive defi- Animal behaviour nitions, we show that the different ways in which emotions are defined correspond to processes that are dis- Consciousness tributed differentially across the animal kingdom. We propose that these definitions provide a useful starting point for investigating the varying emotional capacities of a wide range of animals, providing a basis for a new, comparative science of emotion. 1. Introduction term memory, abstract learning and concept formation (e.g. see Olmstead and Kuhlmeier, 2015; Pearce, 2008), but very little on emo- Whether and to what extent different animals experience emotions tional ones. However, interest in the emotions of animals has increased of one kind or another is an important scientific question; it is also one considerably in recent years, and the time is right to start to redress this that to date has proven extremely difficult to answer. This is a key imbalance (Panksepp, 2011). To do this, we need to be clear about what problem for the study and practice of animal welfare, as an animal’s we mean when we talk about animal “emotions”. Our starting point is capacity to experience suffering is a prerequisite for any welfare con- the search for a definition of emotion that can be applied to both human cern. But the extent to which different species share facets of the and non-human animals alike (e.g. de Waal, 2011; Lang, 2010; LeDoux, emotional processes identified in humans is also a question for com- 2012). In this paper, we address the often controversial issue of defining parative psychology and neuroscience. What are the fundamental fea- emotions in animals by focusing on the distinction between two types of tures of emotions, and how far into our evolutionary past do they definition; prescriptive definitions and descriptive definitions. First, we stretch? When emotional disorders occur in people (as in major de- offer a descriptive definition which sets out a broad area of interest for pression, generalised anxiety disorder, bipolar disorder, etc.) can they comparative emotion research across humans and other species. We be understood in terms of the responses of emotional processing sys- then go on to consider in detail three prescriptive definitions of emo- tems that were originally adapted for a more ancient, even pre-mam- tion. Each of these contemporary definitions has been designed to de- malian, way of life? And to what extent are the behavioural and neu- lineate the types of processing that should be considered “emotional”, ropharmacological facets of emotions shared between people and the and each has the potential for drawing a different line between species species used as models to study these disorders? When we can answer that can and cannot be considered to have the capacity for emotions. No questions about the similarities and differences between humans and one of these definitions is superior to the others; we argue that they are other species in their emotional processing, it may be possible to find all valuable in illustrating the layers of processing that comprise human out, not just about the emotional lives of different animals and the emotional processing, components of which are likely to be present to implications this has for their welfare, but also about the building differing degrees in different species across the animal kingdom. blocks, limitations and potential sources of disorder of human emo- tional processes too. 2. Defining emotion in animals To date, comparative studies of psychological processes have fo- cused most extensively on cognitive capacities such as short and long- What is an emotion? And how can we make use of our human ⁎ Corresponding author. E-mail address: [email protected] (E.S. Paul). https://doi.org/10.1016/j.applanim.2018.01.008 Received 31 May 2017; Received in revised form 16 November 2017; Accepted 21 January 2018 0168-1591/ © 2018 Published by Elsevier B.V. Please cite this article as: Paul, E.S., Applied Animal Behaviour Science (2018), https://doi.org/10.1016/j.applanim.2018.01.008 E.S. Paul, M.T. Mendl Applied Animal Behaviour Science xxx (xxxx) xxx–xxx understanding of the word to talk about and investigate such processes to, but perhaps not perfectly encapsulate, the meaning of the word, e.g. in animals? For many early ethologists and experimental psychologists, see Izard, 2010). For example, “Emotions are affectively charged, emotion was too human and too quintessentially subjective to be in- subjectively experienced states of awareness (LeDoux, p291, in Ekman corporated into the scientific investigation of animals. When Tinbergen and Davidson, 1994); ‘Emotion is a complex set of interactions among was constructing his four questions of ethology (Tinbergen, 1963), the subjective and objective factors …. which can (a) give rise to affective discussion and use of emotion terms in the context of animals was al- experiences such as feelings of arousal, pleasure/displeasure; (b) gen- ready largely taboo, and worries about the legitimacy of discussing erate cognitive processes such as emotionally relevant perceptual ef- emotion within the animal sciences continued for many years there- fects, appraisals, labelling processes; (c) activate widespread physiolo- after. So, definitions can be problematic and need to be applied to gical adjustments to the arousing conditions; and (d) lead to behaviour constructs like emotion with caution. Even attempting to define emo- that is often, but not always, expressive, goal directed and adaptive’ tion in the human context has caused problems (e.g. see Gendron, 2010; (Kleinginna and Kleinginna, 1981, p355); “Emotions are typically eli- Izard, 2010), and the difficulty is magnified in non-human animals who cited by external events……typical emotion episodes contain a number cannot tell us whether or what they feel. In these cases, notions of the of components. There are thoughts, bodily changes, action tendencies, internal or consciously experienced states are essentially inaccessible. modulations of mental processes such as attention, and conscious Nevertheless, the past decade or so has seen a dramatic increase in feelings” (Prinz, 2004, p3). interest, particularly within the neurosciences, but also in ethology, in By de fining emotion in the way we have done, we can point to sorts the topic of emotion and how it can be studied translationally in both of comparative problems of emotion that interest or concern us. For humans and animals (e.g. Anderson and Adolphs, 2014; de Waal, 2011; example, we might want to say “I am interested in whether certain Lang, 2010; LeDoux, 2012; Rolls, 2014). animals experience emotions in a similar way to humans” or “I want to A major and pertinent distinction when attempting to define emo- find out whether birds and mammals differ in the range of emotions tion is the possibility of constructing both descriptive and prescriptive that they show”. This is a useful shorthand; a way of indicating that we definitions (Widen and Russell, 2010). A descriptive definition is a are interested in this domain of research because of our own human dictionary-style definition – one that aims to set out, as comprehen- experience of it. It is also a convenient way of outlining the structure sively and accurately as possible, the ways in which a word is used by and scope of the domain that we want to investigate; the term “emo- people, in a given language, and in everyday life (e.g. see LeDoux et al., tion” circumscribes a domain that is separate from other English lan- 2016). A prescriptive definition is somewhat different; it is a definition guage terms such as “motivation”, “sensation”, “perception” and of the concept or construct that is used to pick out the set of events that “cognition”. A descriptive definition such as this can help researchers of a scientific theory (in this case of emotion) purports to explain. Here, emotion delineate the issues they propose to explore.
Recommended publications
  • Animal Welfare and the Paradox of Animal Consciousness
    ARTICLE IN PRESS Animal Welfare and the Paradox of Animal Consciousness Marian Dawkins1 Department of Zoology, University of Oxford, Oxford, UK 1Corresponding author: e-mail address: [email protected] Contents 1. Introduction 1 2. Animal Consciousness: The Heart of the Paradox 2 2.1 Behaviorism Applies to Other People Too 5 3. Human Emotions and Animals Emotions 7 3.1 Physiological Indicators of Emotion 7 3.2 Behavioral Components of Emotion 8 3.2.1 Vacuum Behavior 10 3.2.2 Rebound 10 3.2.3 “Abnormal” Behavior 10 3.2.4 The Animal’s Point of View 11 3.2.5 Cognitive Bias 15 3.2.6 Expressions of the Emotions 15 3.3 The Third Component of Emotion: Consciousness 16 4. Definitions of Animal Welfare 24 5. Conclusions 26 References 27 1. INTRODUCTION Consciousness has always been both central to and a stumbling block for animal welfare. On the one hand, the belief that nonhuman animals suffer and feel pain is what draws many people to want to study animal welfare in the first place. Animal welfare is seen as fundamentally different from plant “welfare” or the welfare of works of art precisely because of the widely held belief that animals have feelings and experience emotions in ways that plants or inanimate objectsdhowever valuableddo not (Midgley, 1983; Regan, 1984; Rollin, 1989; Singer, 1975). On the other hand, consciousness is also the most elusive and difficult to study of any biological phenomenon (Blackmore, 2012; Koch, 2004). Even with our own human consciousness, we are still baffled as to how Advances in the Study of Behavior, Volume 47 ISSN 0065-3454 © 2014 Elsevier Inc.
    [Show full text]
  • Scientific Evaluation of Animal Emotions: Brief History and Recent New Zealand Contributions
    Scientific evaluation of animal emotions: Brief history and recent New Zealand contributions Beausoleil, N.J., Stratton, R.B., Guesgen, M.J., Sutherland, M.A., Johnson, C.B. Abstract The idea of animals having emotions was once rejected as being anthropomorphic and unscientific. However, with society’s changing views and advances in scientific knowledge and technology, the idea of animal emotions is becoming more accepted. Emotions are subjective internal experiences that can’t be measured directly. Animal welfare scientists must infer emotions by measuring the behavioural, physiological and neurobiological components of emotional experience. In this paper, we describe innovative ways in which these indicators have been used by New Zealand scientists to facilitate a more holistic understanding of the emotions and welfare of animals. Introduction From a scientific perspective, emotion is defined as an innate response to an event or situation (internal or external) that comprises behavioural, physiological, subjective (the feeling) and cognitive (subsequent decision-making) components.1 Emotions are the result of complex processing, by the nervous system, of sensory information gathered from within and outside the animal’s body. The capture and processing of this sensory information are influenced by the biology of the animal species, as well as by individual factors such as the animal’s genetic predispositions, life stage, sex, previous experience, learning and memory.2 The emotion or emotions resulting from these processes of mental evaluation are thus uniquely personal to the individual, but can be broadly characterized by their valence (pleasant or unpleasant) and the degree of arousal generated.3 While the behavioural, physiological and, in some cases, cognitive components of an emotional response can be scientifically evaluated using observable indicators, the subjective component cannot.
    [Show full text]
  • Emotions: from Brain to Robot
    Review TRENDS in Cognitive Sciences Vol.8 No.12 December 2004 Emotions: from brain to robot Michael A. Arbib1 and Jean-Marc Fellous2 1Computer Science, Neuroscience and USC Brain Project, University of Southern California, Los Angeles, CA 90089-2520, USA 2Biomedical Engineering Department and Center for Cognitive Neuroscience, Duke University, Durham, NC 27708-0281, USA Some robots have been given emotional expressions in noting that not all emotions need be like human emotions. an attempt to improve human–computer interaction. In We analyze emotion in two main senses: this article we analyze what it would mean for a robot to (1) Emotional expression for communication and social have emotion, distinguishing emotional expression for coordination. communication from emotion as a mechanism for the (2) Emotion for organization of behavior (action organization of behavior. Research on the neurobiology selection, attention and learning). of emotion yields a deepening understanding of inter- The first concerns ‘external’ aspect of emotions; the acting brain structures and neural mechanisms rooted in second ‘internal’ aspects. In animals, these aspects have neuromodulation that underlie emotions in humans and co-evolved. How might they enter robot design? Both other animals. However, the chemical basis of animal robots and animals need to survive and perform efficiently function differs greatly from the mechanics and compu- within their ‘ecological niche’ and, in each case, patterns of tations of current machines. We therefore abstract from coordination will greatly influence the suite of relevant biology a functional characterization of emotion that emotions (if such are indeed needed) and the means does not depend on physical substrate or evolutionary whereby they are communicated.
    [Show full text]
  • How Do Humans Represent the Emotions of Dogs? The
    Applied Animal Behaviour Science 162 (2015) 37–46 Contents lists available at ScienceDirect Applied Animal Behaviour Science jou rnal homepage: www.elsevier.com/locate/applanim How do humans represent the emotions of dogs? The resemblance between the human representation of the canine and the human affective space a,∗ b a,c,1 Veronika Konok , Krisztina Nagy , Ádám Miklósi a Eötvös University, Department of Ethology, H-1117, Pázmány P. s. 1/c Budapest, Hungary b Szent István University, Faculty of Veterinary Science, H-1078, István u 2. Budapest, Hungary c MTA-ELTE Comparative Ethology Research Group, Hungary a r t i c l e i n f o a b s t r a c t Article history: As (critical) anthropomorphism provides a useful hypothesis for looking at animal behav- Accepted 9 November 2014 ior, people’s reports about how they see animals’ emotions can provide a start point in the Available online 24 November 2014 direction of experiment-oriented studies. It has been shown that humans attribute a wide range of emotions to animals. The concept of ‘affective space’ is often used to model human Keywords: emotional states in a dimensional way. However, there has been no study carried out on Emotion how humans may construct non-human animals’ affective space. Our aim was to assess Dog owners’ attribution of emotions to their dogs (Canis familiaris), and to construct the affec- Affective space tive space for dogs. We used two questionnaires to investigate owners’ opinion about (1) Correspondence analysis the emotions that humans can recognize in dogs and dogs can recognize in humans, and (2) the behavior elements that characterize certain emotions.
    [Show full text]
  • The Ethics of Pain: Moral Status, Emotion, Cognition, And
    THE ETHICS OF PAIN: MORAL STATUS, EMOTION, COGNITION, AND THE LAW OF LABORATORY ANIMALS IN PAIN RESEARCH BY ERIKA A. MOSES A Thesis Submitted to the Graduate Faculty of WAKE FOREST UNIVERSITY GRADUATE SCHOOL OF ARTS AND SCIENCES in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of MASTER OF ARTS Bioethics May 2013 Winston-Salem, North Carolina Approved By: Nancy M.P. King, JD, Advisor Mark Hall, JD, Chair Ana S. Iltis, PhD ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS I would like to thank everyone at Wake Forest Center for Bioethics, Health, and Society. I would like to give a special thank you to my advisor, Professor Nancy M.P. King, and to my committee members, Professor Mark Hall and Professor Ana Iltis. I literally could not have completed this thesis without your support, knowledge, patience, and guidance. I would also like to thank my family members for all of their encouragement and support, especially my mom, dad, and my three loves, Gabriel, Lily, and Baby Christian. ii TABLE OF CONTENTS Abstract iv Introduction Pain Research and Animals: A Brief Overview v Chapter One Moral Status: Leveling the Ethical Playing Field 1 Chapter Two Animal Emotion: Bridging the Species Gap 16 Chapter Three Cognition and Emotion: Linking Process to Experience 36 Chapter Four U.S. Legislation: A Work in Progress 52 Chapter Five The Right Not to be Harmed without Significant Justification 68 References 77 Curriculum Vitae 82 iii ABSTRACT Moses, Erika A. THE ETHICS OF PAIN: MORAL STATUS, EMOTION, COGNITION, AND THE LAW OF LABORATORY ANIMALS IN PAIN RESEARCH Thesis under the direction of Nancy M.P.
    [Show full text]
  • Explicating Emotions
    EXPLICATING EMOTIONS by Andrea Scarantino B.S., Economics, Bocconi University, 1994 M.S., Philosophy of the Social Sciences, London School of Economics and Political Science, 1997 Ph.D., Economics, Universita’ Cattolica, 2000 M.A., Philosophy, University of Pittsburgh, 2005 Submitted to the Graduate Faculty of University of Pittsburgh in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy University of Pittsburgh 2005 UNIVERSITY OF PITTSBURGH FACULTY OF ARTS AND SCIENCES This dissertation was presented by Andrea Scarantino It was defended on July 20, 2005 and approved by Paul Griffiths, ARC Federation Fellow and Professor of Philosophy, Department of Philosophy, University of Queensland (Co-Director) Peter Machamer, Professor of Philosophy, Department of History and Philosophy of Science, University of Pittsburgh (Co-Director) Bob Brandom, Distinguished Service Professor of Philosophy, Department of Philosophy, University of Pittsburgh Ruth Millikan, Emeritus Professor of Philosophy, Department of Philosophy, University of Connecticut (Outside Reader) ii Copyright © by Andrea Scarantino 2005 iii EXPLICATING EMOTIONS Andrea Scarantino, PhD University of Pittsburgh, 2005 In the course of their long intellectual history, emotions have been identified with items as diverse as perceptions of bodily changes (feeling tradition), judgments (cognitivist tradition), behavioral predispositions (behaviorist tradition), biologically based solutions to fundamental life tasks (evolutionary tradition), and culturally specific social artifacts (social constructionist tradition). The first objective of my work is to put some order in the mare magnum of theories of emotions. I taxonomize them into families and explore the historical origin and current credentials of the arguments and intuitions supporting them. I then evaluate the methodology of past and present emotion theory, defending a bleak conclusion: a great many emotion theorists ask “What is an emotion?” without a clear understanding of what counts as getting the answer right.
    [Show full text]
  • Explicating Emotions
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by D-Scholarship@Pitt EXPLICATING EMOTIONS by Andrea Scarantino B.S., Economics, Bocconi University, 1994 M.S., Philosophy of the Social Sciences, London School of Economics and Political Science, 1997 Ph.D., Economics, Universita’ Cattolica, 2000 M.A., Philosophy, University of Pittsburgh, 2005 Submitted to the Graduate Faculty of University of Pittsburgh in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy University of Pittsburgh 2005 UNIVERSITY OF PITTSBURGH FACULTY OF ARTS AND SCIENCES This dissertation was presented by Andrea Scarantino It was defended on July 20, 2005 and approved by Paul Griffiths, ARC Federation Fellow and Professor of Philosophy, Department of Philosophy, University of Queensland (Co-Director) Peter Machamer, Professor of Philosophy, Department of History and Philosophy of Science, University of Pittsburgh (Co-Director) Bob Brandom, Distinguished Service Professor of Philosophy, Department of Philosophy, University of Pittsburgh Ruth Millikan, Emeritus Professor of Philosophy, Department of Philosophy, University of Connecticut (Outside Reader) ii Copyright © by Andrea Scarantino 2005 iii EXPLICATING EMOTIONS Andrea Scarantino, PhD University of Pittsburgh, 2005 In the course of their long intellectual history, emotions have been identified with items as diverse as perceptions of bodily changes (feeling tradition), judgments (cognitivist tradition), behavioral predispositions (behaviorist tradition), biologically based solutions to fundamental life tasks (evolutionary tradition), and culturally specific social artifacts (social constructionist tradition). The first objective of my work is to put some order in the mare magnum of theories of emotions. I taxonomize them into families and explore the historical origin and current credentials of the arguments and intuitions supporting them.
    [Show full text]
  • The Neural Circuits of Innate Fear: Detection, Integration, Action, and Memorization
    Downloaded from learnmem.cshlp.org on September 28, 2021 - Published by Cold Spring Harbor Laboratory Press Review The neural circuits of innate fear: detection, integration, action, and memorization Bianca A. Silva,1 Cornelius T. Gross,2 and Johannes Gra¨ff1 1Laboratory of Neuroepigenetics, Brain Mind Institute, Faculty of Life Sciences, Ecole Polytechnique Fe´de´rale Lausanne, CH-1015 Lausanne, Switzerland; 2Mouse Biology Unit, European Molecular Biology Laboratory (EMBL), 00015 Monterotondo, Italy How fear is represented in the brain has generated a lot of research attention, not only because fear increases the chances for survival when appropriately expressed but also because it can lead to anxiety and stress-related disorders when inade- quately processed. In this review, we summarize recent progress in the understanding of the neural circuits processing innate fear in rodents. We propose that these circuits are contained within three main functional units in the brain: a detection unit, responsible for gathering sensory information signaling the presence of a threat; an integration unit, responsible for incorporating the various sensory information and recruiting downstream effectors; and an output unit, in charge of initiating appropriate bodily and behavioral responses to the threatful stimulus. In parallel, the experience of innate fear also instructs a learning process leading to the memorization of the fearful event. Interestingly, while the detection, integration, and output units processing acute fear responses to different threats tend to be harbored in distinct brain cir- cuits, memory encoding of these threats seems to rely on a shared learning system. The term “fear” refers to a human emotion characterized by the will not be repeated here.
    [Show full text]
  • Scientific Evaluation of Animal Emotions: Brief History and Recent New Zealand Contributions
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Open Journal Systems at the Victoria University of Wellington Library Scientific evaluation of animal emotions: Brief history and recent New Zealand contributions Beausoleil, N.J., Stratton, R.B., Guesgen, M.J., Sutherland, M.A., Johnson, C.B. Abstract The idea of animals having emotions was once rejected as being anthropomorphic and unscientific. However, with society’s changing views and advances in scientific knowledge and technology, the idea of animal emotions is becoming more accepted. Emotions are subjective internal experiences that can’t be measured directly. Animal welfare scientists must infer emotions by measuring the behavioural, physiological and neurobiological components of emotional experience. In this paper, we describe innovative ways in which these indicators have been used by New Zealand scientists to facilitate a more holistic understanding of the emotions and welfare of animals. Introduction From a scientific perspective, emotion is defined as an innate response to an event or situation (internal or external) that comprises behavioural, physiological, subjective (the feeling) and cognitive (subsequent decision-making) components.1 Emotions are the result of complex processing, by the nervous system, of sensory information gathered from within and outside the animal’s body. The capture and processing of this sensory information are influenced by the biology of the animal species, as well as by individual factors such as the animal’s genetic predispositions, life stage, sex, previous experience, learning and memory.2 The emotion or emotions resulting from these processes of mental evaluation are thus uniquely personal to the individual, but can be broadly characterized by their valence (pleasant or unpleasant) and the degree of arousal generated.3 While the behavioural, physiological and, in some cases, cognitive components of an emotional response can be scientifically evaluated using observable indicators, the subjective component cannot.
    [Show full text]
  • Self-Regulation and Toxic Stress
    TABLE OF CONTENTS INTRODUCTION ............................................................................................................................................. 7 Stress ........................................................................................................................................................ 8 Self-Regulation and Its Development ....................................................................................................... 9 Relationship between Stress and Self-Regulation .................................................................................. 10 Important Unanswered Questions ......................................................................................................... 12 PROCEDURE FOR EMPIRICAL LITERATURE REVIEW .................................................................................... 12 Search Terms .......................................................................................................................................... 13 Search Procedure ................................................................................................................................... 13 How and Why we included Psychiatric Disorders defined by Stress and Dysregulation ................... 14 How and Why We Included Animal Studies ....................................................................................... 15 FINDINGS ....................................................................................................................................................
    [Show full text]
  • The Assessment of Cognitive Bias in Capuchin Monkeys Using a Computerized Task
    Georgia State University ScholarWorks @ Georgia State University Psychology Theses Department of Psychology 5-8-2020 The Assessment of Cognitive Bias in Capuchin Monkeys Using a Computerized Task Kristin French Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarworks.gsu.edu/psych_theses Recommended Citation French, Kristin, "The Assessment of Cognitive Bias in Capuchin Monkeys Using a Computerized Task." Thesis, Georgia State University, 2020. https://scholarworks.gsu.edu/psych_theses/216 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Department of Psychology at ScholarWorks @ Georgia State University. It has been accepted for inclusion in Psychology Theses by an authorized administrator of ScholarWorks @ Georgia State University. For more information, please contact [email protected]. THE ASSESSMENT OF COGNITIVE BIAS IN CAPUCHIN MONKEYS USING A COMPUTERIZED TASK by KRISTIN A. FRENCH Under the Direction of Michael J. Beran, PhD ABSTRACT Cognitive bias refers to the influence of affective state on the interpretation of ambiguous stimuli and has been used to assess emotional state in nonhuman animals. The current study assessed cognitive bias in 12 brown-tufted capuchin monkeys using three distinct computerized psychophysical tasks and a novel manipulation to affect that involved giving moneys gelatin foods that tasted either pleasant or unpleasant. In addition, monkeys were trained on several positive and negative training cues. Results showed that food type was not a factor in monkeys’ responses to ambiguous stimuli. Behavioral observation during test sessions revealed the unpleasant food may have acted as a form of enrichment, thereby providing the monkeys with two pleasant activities prior to assessments of their emotional states.
    [Show full text]
  • Implications for the Study of Emotions in Animals1
    Psicologia USP http://dx.doi.org/10.1590/0103-656420140079 286 Reflections on a footnote: implications for the study of emotions in animals1 Emma Otta* Universidade de São Paulo, Instituto de Psicologia, Departamento de Psicologia Experimental. São Paulo, SP, Brasil Abstract: A footnote (FN) originally submitted as a comment to the article “Parsing Reward” led me to write this essay. The comment was rejected by the editor of a prestigious scientific journal in the area of behavioral neuroscience with the suggestion that it would be more appropriate for an “idle talk”. I believe that the core issues involved are important to address explicitly in a debate within the broad domain of the frontiers of human and biological sciences. The protagonists involved in the didactic episode of the FN, whose articles and books I have been reading over the years, are leaders in the field of neuroscience. In this essay the episode is historically contextualized and discussed in terms of potential implications for ethology, psychology and neuroscience. Keywords: emotion, animals, ethology, psychology, neuroscience. A footnote added to the article “Affective conscious- ago, but I decided to write it because I believe that the in- ness: Core emotional feelings in animals and humans”, volved core issues are important and remain current. published in the journal Consciousness and Cognition (Panksepp, 2005), led me to write this essay in order to The suggestive Footnote discuss the study of emotions in animals and implications of this type of research for understanding human psycho- My reading of this paper was that the authors ad- logical processes.
    [Show full text]