Historicizing Judicial Scrutiny

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Historicizing Judicial Scrutiny South Carolina Law Review Volume 57 Issue 1 Article 3 Fall 2005 Historicizing Judicial Scrutiny G. Edward White University of Virginia School of Law Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarcommons.sc.edu/sclr Part of the Law Commons Recommended Citation White, G. Edward (2005) "Historicizing Judicial Scrutiny," South Carolina Law Review: Vol. 57 : Iss. 1 , Article 3. Available at: https://scholarcommons.sc.edu/sclr/vol57/iss1/3 This Article is brought to you by the Law Reviews and Journals at Scholar Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in South Carolina Law Review by an authorized editor of Scholar Commons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. White: Historicizing Judicial Scrutiny HISTORICIZING JUDICIAL SCRUTINY G. EDWARD WHITE* I. INTRODUCTION .............................................. 2 II. REPUBLICAN CONSTITUTIONAL THEORY AND JUDICIAL REVIEW: THE TRADITIONAL REGIME ...................................... 7 A. Republican ConstitutionalThought and the Principleof DepartmentalDiscretion ................................... 7 1. The Role of Judges in American Constitutional Republicanism ........................................ 8 2. DepartmentalDiscretion Cases, 1819-1855 ................ 16 a. McCulloch v. M aryland ............................ 16 b. Foster v. Neilson .................................. 21 c. Luther v. Borden .............................. 27 d. Murray's Lessee v. Hoboken Land & Improvement Co ... 31 B. The DepartmentalDiscretion Principle and JudicialReview of Police Powers Legislation ................................. 35 1. The Impact of the Reconstruction Amendments ............. 35 2. Municipal Bond Cases ................................. 39 3. Rate Regulation Cases ................................. 40 4. The Emergence of JudicialBoundary Tracing .............. 44 5. James Bradley Thayer and the "ClearMistake" Rule: The DepartmentalDiscretion Principleand DeferentialJudicial Scrutiny ............................................ 46 C. The End of the TraditionalRegime .......................... 50 III. MODERN DEMOCRATIC CONSTITUTIONAL THEORY AND THE COLLAPSE OF DOCTRINAL FORMULAS IN CONSTITUTIONAL INTERPRETATION ............................................. 53 A. The Emergence of Democratic ConstitutionalTheory ............ 53 1. Modernity, Republican ConstitutionalTheory, and CausalAgency ................................... 54 2. Toward Democratic ConstitutionalTheory ................. 54 3. Democratic Theory and ConstitutionalAdaptivity ........... 55 4. Democratic Theory and DoctrinalFormulas I: "Liberty of Contract". ................................ 57 5. Democratic Theory and DoctrinalFormulas II: "Liberties of the Mind".... ............................ 60 * David and Mary Harrison Distinguished Professor of Law, University of Virginia School of Law. B.A., Amherst College; M.A., Ph.D., Yale University; J.D., Harvard Law School. My thanks to Bethany Bryant for research assistance, and to my colleagues at the University of Virginia School of Law for their comments on an earlier draft, which was delivered at a faculty workshop in February 2005. Particular thanks to Curtis Bradley, Norm Harrison, Caleb Nelson, and Ann Woolhandler. Published by Scholar Commons, 2005 1 South Carolina Law Review, Vol. 57, Iss. 1 [2005], Art. 3 SOUTH CAROLINA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 57: 1 B. Democratic Theory and the Collapse of DoctrinalFormulas ...... 63 1. Comm entary ........................................ 63 2. The Abandonment of DoctrinalFormulas .................. 65 IV. THE ORIGINS OF SCRUTINY LEVELS JURISPRUDENCE ................ 65 A. IncorporatedRights Cases ................................. 65 B. Police Power Cases ...................................... 68 C. Cases Involving Executive Discretion in Foreign Relations ....... 76 V. CONCLUSION: THE EMERGENCE OF SCRUTINY LEVELS JURISPRUDENCE ............................................... 80 I. INTRODUCTION The practice ofjudicial scrutiny of legislation and executive action challenged on constitutional or other legal grounds has long been understood to be a necessary corollary of the principle of judicial review.' But judicial scrutiny stands in a curious position in contemporary constitutional scholarship. On the one hand, anyone who teaches or writes about constitutional law recognizes that, at least since the 1930s, the decision by a majority of Supreme Court justices to apply a particular level of scrutiny to constitutionally challenged actions of the other branches is an essential first step in the Court's analysis of the constitutionality of that action, and often the crucial factor driving the analysis. Moreover, constitutional law specialists recognize that the scrutiny level decision, once made, brings a set of doctrinal baggage with it. Levels of scrutiny come with their own doctrinal tests for evaluating legislation; those tests come with their own refinements. The scrutiny level decision, in sum, spawns a complex web of formulas and judicial guidelines for the levels' application that takes up a lot of the doctrinal space in modem constitutional law. It seems not much of an overstatement to say that the Supreme Court's constitutional jurisprudence for the last sixty-odd years has been consistently preoccupied with what level of judicial scrutiny to afford constitutionally challenged actions by other branches of government.2 Nonetheless, there has been very little discussion among commentators-and most of that attenuated-about how or why the Court's scrutiny levels jurisprudence emerged. There has been ample discussion of the particular scrutiny level choices Court majorities have made and some effort to instruct the Court about the 1. At least after Marbury v. Madison, 5 U.S. (1 Cranch) 137 (1803), Martin v. Hunter'sLessee, 14 U.S. (1 Wheat.) 304 (1816), and Cohens v. Virginia, 19 U.S. (6 Wheat.) 264 (1821). For more detail, see DAVIDP. CURRIE, THECONSTITUTION INTHESUPREME COURT: THEFIRSTHUNDREDYEARS 1789-1888, at 67-74, 91-102 (1985); G. EDWARD WHITE, THE MARSHALL COURT AND CULTURAL CHANGE, 1815-1835, at 495-524 (abr. ed., Oxford Univ. Press 1991) (1988). 2. This preoccupation may be underrecognized because Court opinions often do not openly acknowledge the scrutiny levels decision but instead merely employ a particular doctrinal framework associated with the level. But opinions in which the scrutiny levels decision is contested (which have consistently surfaced) reveal that the scrutiny level decision drives the Court's doctrinal framework. See, for example, the debate among the justices in Frontiero v. Richardson, 411 U.S. 677 (1973), and Craig v. Boren, 429 U.S. 190 (1976), as to the appropriate level of scrutiny to be afforded in gender discrimination cases. https://scholarcommons.sc.edu/sclr/vol57/iss1/3 2 White: Historicizing Judicial Scrutiny 2005] HISTORICIZING JUDICIAL SCRUTINY appropriate level of scrutiny to apply to a given line of cases There has been widespread recognition that the Court's scrutiny levels have changed over time, both in their formulation and in their application.4 There has been abundant criticism of the coherence of the levels, especially as the Court has applied them to cases. Recently, several commentators suggested that the Court's established scrutiny levels typology, which features at least three and possibly as many as six levels of scrutiny, is on the verge of degeneration! But there have been few efforts to analyze the scrutiny levels practice as a historical phenomenon.6 This seems all the more striking because for a time span of 150 years, in which the Court rendered numerous decisions reviewing the acts of legislatures on constitutional grounds, it made a quite different set of scrutiny level choices from the sets it has employed since the 1930s. During the period from Marbury v. Madison7 to United States v. Carolene Products, Co.,' the Court essentially subjected all challenged decisions of other branches to the same standard of review, but at the same time it often lingered over the question of whether it could constitutionally review a decision by the Executive or Legislature at all. Although the Court's posture of review during that time period can fairly be described as heightened, that description would be misleading because no other levels of scrutiny existed.9 Further, the Court did not employ any of the 3. Gerald Gunther's article, The Supreme Court, 1971 Term-Forward: In Search of Evolving Doctrine on a ChangingCourt: A Modelfor a Newer Equal Protection,86 HARV. L. REV. 1 (1972), is an influential example of scholarship that seeks to instruct the Court about relevant factors in a scrutiny levels decision. 4. See, e.g., JEFFREY M. SHAMAN, CONSTITUTIONAL INTERPRETATION: ILLUSION AND REALITY 74-102 (2001) [hereinafter SHAMAN, CONSTITUTIONAL INTERPRETATION] (discussing the Court's development and use of the multiple scrutiny levels); Jeffrey M. Shaman, Cracks in the Structure: The Coming Breakdown of the Levels of Scrutiny, 45 OHIO STATE L.J. 161, 162-63 (1984) [hereinafter Shaman, Cracks in the Structure] (discussing the changes in scrutiny levels jurisprudence from the Warren Court to the Burger Court and the creation of intermediate scrutiny). 5. See Shaman, Cracks in the Structure, supra note 4, at 172-77, 182-83; R. Randall Kelso, Filling Gaps in the Supreme Court's Approach to ConstitutionalReview of Legislation: Standards, Ends, and Burdens Reconsidered, 33 S. TEX. L. REV. 493, 514-16, 540-47 (1992); Calvin Massey, The New Formalism: Requiem For Tiered
Recommended publications
  • Substantive Equality As a Principle of Fundamental Justice
    411 Constitutional Coalescence: Substantive Equality as a Principle of Fundamental Justice KERRI A. FROC* In this article, the author posits that the principles of Dans cet article, I'auteure soutient que les principes fundamental justice present tantalizing possibilities de justice fondamentale pr6sentent des possibilit6s in the quest to use constitutional law to ameliorate tentantes dans le cadre de la quote visant ase servir the real conditions of disadvantage and subordination du droit constitutionnel pour am6liorer la condition faced by women. As a way out of the stultified sociale de d6savantage et de subordination des femmes. comparative analysis in equality cases and a sec- A titre de solution pour s'6carter de I'analyse com- tion 7 analysis that has often been impervious to parke, figbe, des causes en matibre d'6galit6 Ct d'une gendered relations of domination, she proposes a analyse de I'article 7 souvent imperm6able aux rela- new use for the right to substantive equality repre- tions de domination fond6es sur lc genre, elle pro- sented in section 15(1) of the Canadian Charter of pose un nouvel usage pour Ic droit i l'galit& rclile Rights and Freedoms: as a principle of fundamental garanti par le paragraphe 15(1) de la Charte canadienne justice. Using the examples of the 1988 decision des droits et libertis : soit en tant que principe de justice in R v Morgentaler, 119881 I SCR 30 and subsequent fondamentale. A I'aide d'exemples comme la d6ci- abortion litigation and proposed legislation as a case sion de 1988 dans I'affaire R c Morgentaler, 119881 1 study, she addresses the questions of the difference it RCS 30, les litiges subs6quents concernant la ques- would make to have substantive equality recognized tion de l'avortement ct les projets de lois aff6rents as a principle of fundamental justice in granting women prises comme 6tudes de cas, elleexplore Ia diff6rence equal access to Charter rights.
    [Show full text]
  • The Justice of Administration: Judicial Responses to Excute Claims of Independent Authority to Intrepret the Constitution
    Florida State University Law Review Volume 33 Issue 1 Article 4 2005 The Justice of Administration: Judicial Responses to Excute Claims of Independent Authority to Intrepret the Constitution Brian Galle [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://ir.law.fsu.edu/lr Part of the Law Commons Recommended Citation Brian Galle, The Justice of Administration: Judicial Responses to Excute Claims of Independent Authority to Intrepret the Constitution, 33 Fla. St. U. L. Rev. (2005) . https://ir.law.fsu.edu/lr/vol33/iss1/4 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by Scholarship Repository. It has been accepted for inclusion in Florida State University Law Review by an authorized editor of Scholarship Repository. For more information, please contact [email protected]. FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW THE JUSTICE OF ADMINISTRATION: JUDICIAL RESPONSES TO EXCUTE CLAIMS OF INDEPENDENT AUTHORITY TO INTREPRET THE CONSTITUTION Brian Galle VOLUME 33 FALL 2005 NUMBER 1 Recommended citation: Brian Galle, The Justice of Administration: Judicial Responses to Excute Claims of Independent Authority to Intrepret the Constitution, 33 FLA. ST. U. L. REV. 157 (2005). THE JUSTICE OF ADMINISTRATION: JUDICIAL RESPONSES TO EXECUTIVE CLAIMS OF INDEPENDENT AUTHORITY TO INTERPRET THE CONSTITUTION BRIAN GALLE* I. INTRODUCTION.................................................................................................. 157 II. SOME BACKGROUND ON THE BACKGROUND RULES ........................................... 164 III.
    [Show full text]
  • Lessons for Bivens and Qualified Immunity Debates from Nineteenth-Century Damages Litigation Against Federal Officers
    Notre Dame Law Review Volume 96 Issue 5 Article 1 5-2021 Lessons for Bivens and Qualified Immunity Debates from Nineteenth-Century Damages Litigation Against Federal Officers Andrew Kent Professor and John D. Feerick Research Chair, Fordham Law School Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarship.law.nd.edu/ndlr Part of the Constitutional Law Commons, and the Supreme Court of the United States Commons Recommended Citation 96 Notre Dame L. Rev. 1755 (2021) This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Notre Dame Law Review at NDLScholarship. It has been accepted for inclusion in Notre Dame Law Review by an authorized editor of NDLScholarship. For more information, please contact [email protected]. \\jciprod01\productn\N\NDL\96-5\NDL501.txt unknown Seq: 1 13-MAY-21 10:15 FEDERAL COURTS, PRACTICE & PROCEDURE LESSONS FOR BIVENS AND QUALIFIED IMMUNITY DEBATES FROM NINETEENTH-CENTURY DAMAGES LITIGATION AGAINST FEDERAL OFFICERS Andrew Kent* This Essay was written for a symposium marking the fiftieth anniversary of the Supreme Court’s decision in Bivens v. Six Unknown Named Agents of Federal Bureau of Narcot- ics. As the current Court has turned against Bivens—seemingly confining it to three specific contexts created by Bivens and two follow-on decisions in 1979 and 1980—scholars and liti- gants have developed a set of claims to respond to the Court’s critique. The Court now views the judicially created Bivens cause of action and remedy as a separation-of-powers foul; Congress is said to be the institution which should weigh the costs and benefits of allowing constitutional tort suits against federal officers for damages, especially in areas like national security or foreign affairs in which the political branches might be thought to have constitutional primacy.
    [Show full text]
  • INFORMATION to USERS This Manuscript Has Been Reproduced
    INFORMATION TO USERS This manuscript has been reproduced from the microfilm master. UMI films the text directly from the original or copy submitted. Thus, some thesis and dissertation copies are in typewriter face, while others may be from arty type of computer printer. Hie quality of this reproduction is dependent upon the quality o f the copy submitted. Broken or indistinct print, colored or poor quality illustrations and photographs, print bleedthrough, substandard margins, and improper alignment can adversely affect reproduction. In the unlikely event that the author did not send UMI a complete manuscript and there are missing pages, these will be noted. Also, if unauthorized copyright material had to be removed, a note will indicate the deletion. Oversize materials (e.g, maps, drawings, charts) are reproduced by sectioning the original, beginning at the upper left-hand comer and continuing from left to right in equal sections with small overlaps. Each original is also photographed in one exposure and is included in reduced form at the bade of the book. Photographs included in the original manuscript have been reproduced xerographically in this copy. Higher quality 6" x 9" black and white photographic prints are available for any photographs or illustrations appearing in this copy for an additional charge. Contact UMI directly to order. A Beil & Howell information Company 300 Nortn Zeetj Road. Ann Arbor. Ml 48106-1346 USA 313/761-4700 800/521-0600 Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without
    [Show full text]
  • The Right to Reasons in Administrative Law H.L
    1986] RIGHT TO REASONS 305 THE RIGHT TO REASONS IN ADMINISTRATIVE LAW H.L. KUSHNER* It is generally accepted that there is no common Jaw right to reasons in administrative Jaw. The author reviews the Jaw to determine whether such a right exists and whether it has been changed by the enactment of the Charter of Rights. He questions whether a statutory obligation to give reasons should be enacted. FinaJJy,he looks at the effect of failing to comply with such a requirement. He concludes that although the rules of natural justice and the enactment of s. 7 of the Charter of Rights would support a right to reasons, the courts are reluctant to impose such an obligation on the administrative decision-makers. He feels that the legislatures should require reasons. An ad­ ministrative decision should be ineffective without reasons if such a requirement were imposed either by the courts or the legislatures. "It may well be argued that there is a third principle of natural justice, 1 namely, that a party is entitled to know the reason for the decision, be it judicial or quasi-judicial". 2 As early as 1875 it is possible to find case authority to support the proposition that if not reasons, at least the grounds upon which a decision has been made must be stated. 3 Certainly there is an abundant number of governmental reports and studies, 4 as well as academic writings 5 which support the value of reasons. However, the majority of these adopt the view that a requirement for reasons does oc.
    [Show full text]
  • A General History of the Burr Family, 1902
    historyAoftheBurrfamily general Todd BurrCharles A GENERAL HISTORY OF THE BURR FAMILY WITH A GENEALOGICAL RECORD FROM 1193 TO 1902 BY CHARLES BURR TODD AUTHOB OF "LIFE AND LETTERS OF JOBL BARLOW," " STORY OF THB CITY OF NEW YORK," "STORY OF WASHINGTON,'' ETC. "tyc mis deserves to be remembered by posterity, vebo treasures up and preserves tbe bistort of bis ancestors."— Edmund Burkb. FOURTH EDITION PRINTED FOR THE AUTHOR BY <f(jt Jtnuhtrboclur $«88 NEW YORK 1902 COPYRIGHT, 1878 BY CHARLES BURR TODD COPYRIGHT, 190a »Y CHARLES BURR TODD JUN 19 1941 89. / - CONTENTS Preface . ...... Preface to the Fourth Edition The Name . ...... Introduction ...... The Burres of England ..... The Author's Researches in England . PART I HISTORICAL AND BIOGRAPHICAL Jehue Burr ....... Jehue Burr, Jr. ...... Major John Burr ...... Judge Peter Burr ...... Col. John Burr ...... Col. Andrew Burr ...... Rev. Aaron Burr ...... Thaddeus Burr ...... Col. Aaron Burr ...... Theodosia Burr Alston ..... PART II GENEALOGY Fairfield Branch . ..... The Gould Family ...... Hartford Branch ...... Dorchester Branch ..... New Jersey Branch ..... Appendices ....... Index ........ iii PART I. HISTORICAL AND BIOGRAPHICAL PREFACE. HERE are people in our time who treat the inquiries of the genealogist with indifference, and even with contempt. His researches seem to them a waste of time and energy. Interest in ancestors, love of family and kindred, those subtle questions of race, origin, even of life itself, which they involve, are quite beyond their com prehension. They live only in the present, care nothing for the past and little for the future; for " he who cares not whence he cometh, cares not whither he goeth." When such persons are approached with questions of ancestry, they retire to their stronghold of apathy; and the querist learns, without diffi culty, that whether their ancestors were vile or illustrious, virtuous or vicious, or whether, indeed, they ever had any, is to them a matter of supreme indifference.
    [Show full text]
  • The Principles of Fundamental Justice, Societal Interests and Section I of the Charter
    THE PRINCIPLES OF FUNDAMENTAL JUSTICE, SOCIETAL INTERESTS AND SECTION I OF THE CHARTER Thomas J. Singleton* Halifax In this article, the authordiscusses the approach ofthe Supreme Court ofCanada to the treatment ofsocietal interests in cases involving section 7 ofthe Charter. From a review of the cases where the Court has considered the issue of where to balance societal interests - in the determination of whether there has been a violation ofthe principles offundamentaljustice or in the analysis under section 1 - it becomes apparent that the Court is far from having any conceptually coherent approach to this issue, which is often determinative ofindividual rights under section 7. The author demonstrates that there are, in fact, two radically different approaches to the treatment of societal interests in section 7 cases, resulting in a situation where the lower courts and the profession at large are effectively without directionfrom the Court on this extremely important issue. The author argues that the tendency ofsomejustices to import societal interests into the determination ofthe principles offundamentaljustice effectively emasculates the rights guaranteedby section 7because the resulting additional burden ofproof on the individual rights claimant is excessively onerous. Dans cet article, l'auteur discute du traitement qu'accorde la Cour suprême du Canada aux intérêts de la société dans les causes impliquant l'article 7 de la Charte. L'auteurpasse en revue les arrêts où la Cour a considéré la question de savoiroù les intérêts de la société devaient êtrepris en compte - en déterminant s'il .y a eu ou non violation des principes de la justice fondamentale ou dans l'analyse aux termes de l'article 1.
    [Show full text]
  • The Constitution and Administrative Law – Unfulled Promises
    The Charter in Administrative Law: Unfulfilled Promises and Future Prospects David Stratas∗ The unfulfilled promise of s. 7 of the Charter When the Charter first became part of our law, many administrative law practitioners were optimistic that s. 7 of the Charter might have wide application in Charter proceedings. However, this promise has not been fulfilled. The limited scope of the rights to liberty and security of the person Administrative tribunals and civil courts are subject to obligations to afford procedural fairness at common law but those obligations can be ousted by clear statutory wording. Can the Charter limit such statutes and guarantee procedural fairness? The answer to that question depended on how the Court interprets s. 7 of the Charter. Section 7 is the one right under the Charter that theoretically speaks to the issue of procedural fairness. Section 7 guarantees the application of the principles of fundamental justice to those whose rights to liberty and security of the person are infringed. The principles of fundamental justice seem susceptible to an interpretation that would include procedural fairness. Obviously, the broader the interpretation of the rights to liberty and security of the person, the broader the scope of constitutional protection for procedural fairness. A bold court in the area of procedural matters would be inclined to give the rights to liberty and security of the person a broad interpretation to ensure that the standards of "fundamental justice" have a broad application. However, the rights to liberty and security of the person have been given a fairly narrow interpretation. Perhaps the best way to illustrate this is a close examination of the recent administrative law case of Blencoe v.
    [Show full text]
  • Petitioner, V
    NO. 20-______ In the Supreme Court of the United States ________________ JUSTIN MICHAEL WOLFE, Petitioner, v. COMMONWEALTH OF VIRGINIA, Respondent. ________________ On Petition for Writ of Certiorari to the Supreme Court of Virginia ________________ PETITION FOR WRIT OF CERTIORARI ________________ MARVIN D. MILLER ASHLEY C. PARRISH THE LAW OFFICES OF Counsel of Record MARVIN D. MILLER JILL R. CARVALHO 1203 Duke Street KING & SPALDING LLP Alexandria, VA 22314 1700 Pennsylvania Ave. NW (703) 548-5000 Washington, DC 20006 [email protected] (202) 737-0500 [email protected] [email protected] Counsel for Petitioner January 29, 2021 QUESTION PRESENTED After petitioner Justin Wolfe obtained federal habeas relief because of “abhorrent” prosecutorial misconduct, the Commonwealth of Virginia vindictively brought six new charges with more severe penalties against Wolfe. Instead of requiring the Commonwealth to justify the new charges, the trial court rejected the vindictive prosecution claim on grounds that are manifestly wrong. With no chance of a fair trial, Wolfe entered a plea and then, on appeal, argued that the trial court had no authority to convict or sentence him because of the vindictive prosecution. Instead of addressing the federal constitutional issues raised by that claim, the Virginia courts concluded that Wolfe’s guilty plea waived his right to appeal. This Court granted certiorari, vacated the judgment, and directed the Virginia courts to consider Class v. United States, 138 S. Ct. 798 (2018). On remand, the Virginia courts recognized that Wolfe’s guilty plea does not bar his appeal. But they invented another reason not to address Wolfe’s vindictive prosecution claim, holding that Wolfe forfeited his appellate rights because he purportedly did not preserve an argument in favor of his position.
    [Show full text]
  • Introduction the Foundations of Diplomatic Security
    INTRODUCTION THE FOUNDATIONS OF DIPLOMATIC SECURITY INTRODUCTION 8 THE FOUNDATIONS OF DIPLOMATIC SECURITY Diplomatic security is as old as diplomacy itself. Initially, diplomatic security was primarily the secure conveyance of government communications using couriers and codes. The Persian, Babylonian, Egyptian, Chinese, Greek, Roman, Aztec, and Incan empires developed courier services to carry imperial messages. The Greeks and Romans also developed ciphers to preserve confidentiality of diplomatic messages.1 By the Renaissance (1500s), codes had emerged, and Spanish, French, English, Vatican, and Venetian foreign ministers routinely used ciphers and codes when writing to their diplomats abroad. The European monarchies also developed courier networks to carry messages. Courier work was seen as a training ground for diplomats because couriers had to exercise discretion, know the local language, and employ disguises to avoid detection.2 Colonial-era leaders in North America were acutely aware of the need to protect their correspondence. As tensions escalated between Great Britain and its American colonies in the 1760s, the Sons of Liberty communicated with each other by Figure 1: Henry Laurens, U.S. Commissioner to the dropping letters at secretly designated coffee houses or Netherlands. Laurens and his papers were captured by the British while en route to Europe. His papers provided taverns, where sympathetic postmen or ship captains evidence of Dutch aid to the American Revolution and led would pick up and deliver the letters. During the Great Britain to declare war on the Netherlands. Portrait by Pierre Eugène du Simitière, 1783. Source: Library of American Revolution, the small fleet of sympathetic Congress, Prints and Photographs Division.
    [Show full text]
  • On the Connection Between Law and Justice Anthony D'amato Northwestern University School of Law, [email protected]
    Northwestern University School of Law Northwestern University School of Law Scholarly Commons Faculty Working Papers 2011 On the Connection Between Law and Justice Anthony D'Amato Northwestern University School of Law, [email protected] Repository Citation D'Amato, Anthony, "On the Connection Between Law and Justice" (2011). Faculty Working Papers. Paper 2. http://scholarlycommons.law.northwestern.edu/facultyworkingpapers/2 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by Northwestern University School of Law Scholarly Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Faculty Working Papers by an authorized administrator of Northwestern University School of Law Scholarly Commons. On the Connection Between Law and Justice, by Anthony D'Amato,* 26 U. C. Davis L. Rev. 527-582 (1992-93) Abstract: What does it mean to assert that judges should decide cases according to justice and not according to the law? Is there something incoherent in the question itself? That question will serve as our springboard in examining what is—or should be—the connection between justice and law. Legal and political theorists since the time of Plato have wrestled with the problem of whether justice is part of law or is simply a moral judgment about law. Nearly every writer on the subject has either concluded that justice is only a judgment about law or has offered no reason to support a conclusion that justice is somehow part of law. This Essay attempts to reason toward such a conclusion, arguing that justice is an inherent component of the law and not separate or distinct from it.
    [Show full text]
  • Habeas Corpus Law for Prison Administrators
    Habeas Corpus Law for Prison Administrators 2018 CanLIIDocs 246 Gerard Mitchell Case comment: Mission Institute v. Khela, [2014] 1 S.C.R. 502 2018 CanLIIDocs 246 [1] Habeas Corpus proceedings are the way in which prisoners can challenge the lawfulness of their confinement. [2] In the last few years federal penitentiary administrators have found themselves spending a lot of time and resources defending their decisions in habeas corpus proceedings before provincial superior courts. [3] The trend is likely to continue because the March 27, 2014 decision of the Supreme Court of Canada in the case of Mission Institute v. Khela, [2014] 1 S.C.R. 502 strongly supports a broad scope for habeas corpus review by affirming that provincial courts can assess both the procedural fairness and the reasonableness of a decision in order to determine if an individual’s detention is lawful. 2018 CanLIIDocs 246 [4] The Court also ruled that correctional authorities have significant disclosure obligations in an involuntary transfer context, and that information can only be withheld when the commissioner of Corrections or his or her representative has reasonable grounds to believe that should the information be released it might threaten the security of the prison, the safety of any person, or interfere with the conduct of an investigation. [5] Section 10(c) of the Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms guarantees everyone detained the right to have the validity of their detention determined by way of habeas corpus and to be released if the detention is not lawful. Everyone includes prisoners. [6] Prisoners have a Charter right not to be deprived of their residual liberties except in accordance with the principles of fundamental justice (s.7) and they have a Charter right not to be arbitrarily detained (s.9).
    [Show full text]