The Mathematical in Heidegger and Badiou

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

The Mathematical in Heidegger and Badiou Louisiana State University LSU Digital Commons LSU Master's Theses Graduate School 2008 The am thematical in Heidegger and Badiou Dylan Armstrong Wade Louisiana State University and Agricultural and Mechanical College, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.lsu.edu/gradschool_theses Part of the Arts and Humanities Commons Recommended Citation Wade, Dylan Armstrong, "The am thematical in Heidegger and Badiou" (2008). LSU Master's Theses. 4201. https://digitalcommons.lsu.edu/gradschool_theses/4201 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Graduate School at LSU Digital Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in LSU Master's Theses by an authorized graduate school editor of LSU Digital Commons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. THE MATHEMATICAL IN HEIDEGGER AND BADIOU A Thesis Submitted to the Graduate Faculty of the Louisiana State University and Agricultural and Mechanical College in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Master of Arts in The Department of Philosophy and Religious Studies by Dylan Armstrong Wade B.A. Tulane University, 2006 August 2008 TABLE OF CONTENTS ABSTRACT ............................................................................................................................. iii CHAPTER 1: FACTICITY AND INTERPRETATION ..............................................................1 1.1 Introduction .......................................................................................................................1 1.2 The Facticity of a Thing .....................................................................................................1 1.3 The Interpretive Structure of Dasein ..................................................................................4 1.4. Language and the Formalization of Facticity ................................................................... 11 CHAPTER 2: THE MATHEMATICAL IN MARTIN HEIDEGGER ....................................... 15 2.1 Introduction ..................................................................................................................... 15 2.2 Mathematical as Pre-theoretical Understanding ................................................................ 16 2.3 Nature in Aristotle and Newton ........................................................................................ 19 2.4 The History of Transcendental Reasoning ........................................................................ 23 2.5 Ontology as Standing-Reserve ......................................................................................... 28 CHAPTER 3: THE MATHEMATICAL IN ALAIN BADIOU.................................................. 31 3.1 Introduction ..................................................................................................................... 31 3.2 Mathematics as Ontolgy................................................................................................... 32 3.3 Truth and Subject ............................................................................................................. 38 3.4 Conclusion ....................................................................................................................... 45 REFERENCES ......................................................................................................................... 48 VITA ........................................................................................................................................ 49 ii ABSTRACT In this thesis I am tracing the historical development of subjectivity from its skeptical foundation in Descartes to Alain Badiou’s subject as fidelity to truth. Drawing from Martin Heidegger’s What is a Thing? , this history begins with the turn from an Aristotelian to a Newtonian apprehension of motion, turning towards an a priori mathematical projection of spatial uniformity, such that there are no longer different places – only quantifiable distance. It is on the basis of this turning away from tradition, or ordinary experience of different phenomena, that Descartes posits the self-certain I-pole. Heidegger criticizes modernity, defined as the merging of the metaphysical and the mathematical, for apprehending the relationship between man and world in only one way, as things. I hope show that this development does not derive from the mathematical alone, but from the project of objects against an objective background secured in an I-pole, further advanced by Kant’s transcendental reflection of the thing-in-itself over this project. I do this by following Alain Badiou’s assessment of Zermelo-Fraenkel’s axiomatic set theory, a particular mathematical model that self-destructs, meaning it cannot become absolute or dogmatic. With this thesis I hope to contribute to the scholarship of facticity, the existential thinking that begins with doubt. If we can dissociate in our ordinary language claims that utilize transcendental reasoning from claims concerning mathematical projection based on speculation alone, perhaps we might find some basis to make existential claims independent of perspective, or subjectivism. iii CHAPTER 1: FACTICITY AND INTERPRETATION 1.1 Introduction In What is a Thing? Martin Heidegger criticizes the heirs of Kant’s legacy, neo-Kantians or positivists, for failing to understand Kant’s original ontological inquiry. While positivists maintained a scientific attitude by holding that the only meaningful assertions were those that could be falsified by experience, Heidegger criticizes this particular school of materialism for a dogmatism of its own, in seeing the relationship between man and world as only describable in terms of discreet units or particular things, that is, mathematically. In order to disclose the historical situation in which thing-ness has come to be apprehended in terms of quantifiable things, I will follow Heidegger’s history of subjectivity as a reaction to the speculation of mathematics, secured in the presentation of the I-pole for Descartes, and formalized in the consistent representation of phenomena as spatial for Kant. By dismissing the thing-in-itself as an object of knowledge, the thing-in-itself becomes the determinate apprehension of thing-ness as a limit for speculation. Yet the question of thing-ness can again be raised by returning to the speculative foundation, pure reason, which Kant critiques. In the second half of this thesis, I hope to demonstrate that the speculation of modernity motivates Alain Badiou’s claim that the one-is-not, promoting a form of non-dogmatic mathematics that may turn our understanding of existential claims away from subjectivism, by returning to the factical situation of pure reason, or doubt. 1.2 The Facticity of a Thing By disclosing the historical situation upon which the linguistic assumptions of our ordinary language are made possible (specifically the subject/object relation), Heidegger thereby underscores the degree to which our everyday approach to things has been historically 1 determined and thus grounded on nothing besides its own history. The question that Heidegger raises to begin paragraph 58 of Being and Time is how Dasein can be called to be itself, defined as care, care for both things and others. In other words, how can we come to recognize that we are involved in a world, not as some merely present object, determined either by external forces or human nature? Moreover, how can we come to recognize this situation, our facticity, without being informed of it – subjecting that information to a general knowledge of objective facts? Heidegger answers that we must begin with the general knowledge, our ordinary way of talking about ourselves as subjects to objects, given in our relationships with the world and others. Take any object given as present, some X. Generally, we would speak of this X as pertaining to a certain category or kind. We would say that X is of a certain kind, distinct from some other kind Y. By categorizing these distinct kinds, we suppose a universal schema for their ordering, thus grounding these present objects in a transcendent structure or logos –a logos of objectivity for the positivists or neo-Kantians. Heidegger opposes to category the notion of the existential. In category, the question of being has been distorted, such that being has been thought of as a universal and a-temporal order. This inauthentic distortion prevents any experience of beings except through that supposed universal ordering. By means of a regressive logic,1 Heidegger opens the relational structure between different kinds of beings, positing existential kinds, that is, different kinds of relations. Existentials relate the whole of being, the facticity of the Dasein,2 while categories may certainly be appropriate for the particular relationship to objects present-at-hand. Heidegger defines Dasein as a thrown project, existing temporally with no before or after, groundless aside from its own history and direction. 1 One example takes place in the third chapter of Martin Heidegger’s Being and Time where the present-at-hand, or useless objects, derives from the breakdown of circumspective concern, or the practical relationship between man and world. 2 Literally translated as being-there, or what we might call the relationship between man and world. 2 In What is a Thing? Heidegger contrasts the two modes (existential and categorical) in terms of the philosopher and the nursemaid. It has been said that one day while
Recommended publications
  • Depopulation: on the Logic of Heidegger's Volk
    Research research in phenomenology 47 (2017) 297–330 in Phenomenology brill.com/rp Depopulation: On the Logic of Heidegger’s Volk Nicolai Krejberg Knudsen Aarhus University [email protected] Abstract This article provides a detailed analysis of the function of the notion of Volk in Martin Heidegger’s philosophy. At first glance, this term is an appeal to the revolutionary mass- es of the National Socialist revolution in a way that demarcates a distinction between the rootedness of the German People (capital “P”) and the rootlessness of the modern rabble (or people). But this distinction is not a sufficient explanation of Heidegger’s position, because Heidegger simultaneously seems to hold that even the Germans are characterized by a lack of identity. What is required is a further appropriation of the proper. My suggestion is that this logic of the Volk is not only useful for understanding Heidegger’s thought during the war, but also an indication of what happened after he lost faith in the National Socialist movement and thus had to make the lack of the People the basis of his thought. Keywords Heidegger – Nazism – Schwarze Hefte – Black Notebooks – Volk – people Introduction In § 74 of Sein und Zeit, Heidegger introduces the notorious term “the People” [das Volk]. For Heidegger, this term functions as the intersection between phi- losophy and politics and, consequently, it preoccupies him throughout the turbulent years from the National Socialist revolution in 1933 to the end of WWII in 1945. The shift from individual Dasein to the Dasein of the German People has often been noted as the very point at which Heidegger’s fundamen- tal ontology intersects with his disastrous political views.
    [Show full text]
  • Beauvoir on Gender, Oppression, and Freedom
    24.01: Classics of Western Philosophy Beauvoir on Gender, Oppression, and Freedom 1. Introduction: Simone de Beauvoir (1908-1986) Beauvoir was born in Paris and studied philosophy at the Sorbonne. She passed exams for Certificates in History of Philosophy, General Philosophy, Greek, and Logic in 1927, and in 1928, in Ethics, Sociology, and Psychology. She wrote a graduate diplôme (equivalent to an MA thesis) on Leibniz. Her peers included Maurice Merleau-Ponty, Claude Lévi-Strauss, and Jean-Paul Sartre. In 1929, she took second place in the highly competitive philosophy agrégation exam, barely losing to Jean-Paul Sartre who took first (it was his second attempt at the exam). At 21 years of age, Beauvoir was the youngest student ever to pass the exam. She taught in high school from 1929-1943, and then supported herself on her writings, and co-editorship of Le Temps Modernes. She is known for her literary writing, and her philosophical work in existentialism, ethics, and feminism. She published The Second Sex in 1949. 2. Gender ‘One is not born, but rather becomes, a woman. No biological, psychological or economic fate determines the future that the human female presents in society.’ (II.iv.1) A. What is a woman? “Tota mulier in utero: she is a womb,” some say. Yet speaking of certain women, the experts proclaim, “They are not women,” even though they have a uterus like the others. Everyone agrees there are females in the human species; today, as in the past, they make up about half of humanity; and yet we are told that “femininity is in jeopardy”; we are urged, “Be women, stay women, become women.” So not every female human being is necessarily a woman… (23) So there seems to be a sort of contradiction in our ordinary understanding of women: not every female is a woman, otherwise they would not be exhorted to be women.
    [Show full text]
  • Between Heidegger and Derrida: on the Impossible Futures of Techne
    KIR KUIKEN Between Heidegger and Derrida: On the Impossible Futures of Techne This paper is not the first to interrogate the term “legacies” in the title of this conference, implying as it does the vast problems of inheritance, of debt and even of mourning. A conference on the “Legacies of Theory” necessarily provokes a meditation on the notion of “legacy” itself. What I do not wish to take issue with in this term is what is implied by the plural: “legacies.” If the concept of “legacy” implies inheritance, then there is the possibility of inheritance only where its contingencies are multiple, contested and even contradictory. This multiplicity is in fact the precondition of inheriting, its very chance or possibility. What I do want to contest, however, is a certain relation to time that the term “legacies” implies. At a moment when the term “post-theory” has entered the academic lexicon, and when books with titles such as Life After Theory (Derrida et al.)1 have begun to mark its retreat or displacement within the institution, the term “legacies” risks collusion with a discourse that seeks to extirpate any real encounter with its “legacy,” multiple, contested or otherwise. And if I might be permitted to replace the term “theory” with the term “deconstruction,” the problematic nature of the concept of “legacy” makes itself clearer. Insofar as the term “legacy” implies a certain “temporality of presence,” with a clear, single, undivided border 1 The book contains an interview with Derrida, who addresses the question of “what comes after” theory very differently than the other contributors.
    [Show full text]
  • Transcendence, Facticity, and Modes of Non-Being
    Massachusetts Institute of Technology Artificial Intelligence Laboratory Working paper 282 March 1986 Transcendence, Facticity, and Modes of Non-Being B. Randall Donaldt J. Francis Cannyt Abstract: Research in artificial intelligence has yet to satisfactorily address the primordial fissure between human consciousness and the material order. How is this split reconciled in terms of human reality? By what duality is Bad Faith possible? We show that the answer is quite subtle, and of particular relevance to certain classical A.I. problems in introspection and intensional belief structure. A principled approach to bad faith and the consciousness of the other is suggested. We present ideas for an implementation in the domain of chemical engineering. A.I. Laboratory working papers are produced for internal circulation, and may contain information that is, for example, too preliminary, too detailed, or too silly for formal publication. This paper handsomely satisfies all three criteria. While it is destined to become a landmark in its genre, readers are cautioned against making reference to this paper in the literature, as the authors would like to rejoin society with a clean slate. This paper could not have been produced without the assistance of many brilliant but unstable individuals who could not be reached for comment, and whose names have been suppressed pending determination of competence. tFormer member, National Rifle Association lFormer member, Australian Amateur Radio Association Transcendence, Facticity and Modes oNon-oein In Being and Nothingness Sartre proposes a primordial split, or fissure, between human (conscious) reality and the material order--that is, between the being-for-itself and the being-in-itself.
    [Show full text]
  • DEVELOPING a HAUNTOLOGY of the BLACK BODY Kashif Jerome
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Carolina Digital Repository SPECTERS AND SPOOKS: DEVELOPING A HAUNTOLOGY OF THE BLACK BODY Kashif Jerome Powell, MA A dissertation submitted to the faculty of the University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in Department of Communication Studies. Chapel Hill 2014 Approved by: Renee Alexander-Craft Ashley Lucas Della Pollock Alvaro Reyes Eric King Watts © 2014 Kashif Jerome Powell ALL RIGHTS RESERVED ii ABSTRACT Kashif Jerome Powell: Specters and Spooks: Developing a Hauntology of The Black Body (Under the direction of Dr. Renee Alexander-Craft) This dissertation utilizes theories of embodiment and performance to develop a “hauntology of blackness,” which investigates imaginative sites of death constructed through the historical, social, and performative facets of institutional slavery in the United States to theorize notions of blackness and the black body. I argue that the relationship between the black body and death have conjured a death-driven specter that manifest historically, performatively, visually, and phenomenally as blackness. The rise and continual return of this “specter of blackness” positions the black body in the United States as a body “haunted” by its own biological and phenotypical disposition. Placing the theory of Jacques Derrida and Frantz Fanon in conversation with scholars such as Avery Gordon, Saidiya Hartman, Toni Morrison, and others, I evoke the language of haunting to consider the profound effect the relationship between the black body and death has had on ontological, psychoanalytic, and phenomenological understandings of blackness within post-modernity.
    [Show full text]
  • Reading Heidegger As an Immigrant, Or 'Displacing Dasein'
    Reading Heidegger as an immigrant, or ‘displacing Dasein’: the phenomenological implications of displacement Mersiye Bora Thesis submitted to Royal Holloway, University of London for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy School of Politics, International Relations, and Philosophy 2017 1 Declaration of authorship I, Mersiye Bora, hereby declare that this thesis and the work presented in it is entirely my own. Where I have consulted the work of others, this is always clearly stated. Mersiye Bora September, 2017 2 Abstract In Being and Time, Heidegger demands that readers reflect on their own experiences. As a response to this demand, I argue that the experience of displacement is missing from Heidegger’s existential analytic of Dasein, and that the phenomenon of displacement creates a rich discussion between Heidegger’s fundamental ontology and his later writings on art and technology. The task of this work is to establish a dialogue between Heidegger’s writings and the phenomenon of displacement. This thesis is a product of thinking about displacement through Heidegger, and thinking of Heidegger through displacement. The first chapter describes how the meaning of immigration as displacement is effaced in everyday political discourse and quantitative approaches, which have an ontological ground in traditional metaphysics. The second chapter explores Heidegger’s phenomenological ontology through his criticism of western ontology, which allows me to show how displacement becomes a philosophical problem. The chapter further argues that the displaced is Dasein, who has lost the world in which it lives and thereby has become homeless. It also considers the primordial homelessness of Dasein, which shows itself in anxiety, and the homelessness of the displaced.
    [Show full text]
  • Rethinking the German Nation As German Dasein: Intellectuals And
    Rethinking the German nation as German Dasein: intellectuals and Heidegger’s philosophy in contemporary German New Right nationalism LSE Research Online URL for this paper: http://eprints.lse.ac.uk/100049/ Version: Accepted Version Article: Göpffarth, Julian (2020) Rethinking the German nation asGerman Dasein: intellectuals and Heidegger’s philosophy in contemporary German New Right nationalism. Journal of Political Ideologies. ISSN 1356-9317 https://doi.org/10.1080/13569317.2020.1773068 Reuse Items deposited in LSE Research Online are protected by copyright, with all rights reserved unless indicated otherwise. They may be downloaded and/or printed for private study, or other acts as permitted by national copyright laws. The publisher or other rights holders may allow further reproduction and re-use of the full text version. This is indicated by the licence information on the LSE Research Online record for the item. [email protected] https://eprints.lse.ac.uk/ Rethinking the German nation as German Dasein: Intellectuals and Heidegger’s philosophy in contemporary German New Right nationalism This is a preliminary version of an article whose final and definite form will be published in The Journal of Political Ideologies, © Informa UK Limited, trading as Taylor & Francis Group. Julian Göpffarth European Institute, London School of Economics and Political Science Address: 30-32 Dresden Road, N19 3BD London Email: [email protected] Phone: 07743540890 Twitter: @JGopffarth LinkedIn: Julian Göpffarth Abstract Most scholarship on far-right parties focuses on populism while largely ignoring the role of intellectualism. Disregarding the increasing support by well-educated voters, much of this literature appears to presume that populism and intellectualism in the far-right are separate rather than complementary phenomena.
    [Show full text]
  • Existential Bases of Human Identity in the Era of Gestell (Based on a Critique and Development of M
    10.25136/1339-3057.2018.4.27050 SENTENTIA. European Journal of Humanities and Social Sciences, 2018 - 4 Existential bases of human identity in the era of Gestell (based on a critique and development of M. Heidegger's ideas). / Экзистенциальные основания человеческой идентичности в эпоху Постава (на основании критики и развития идей М. Хайдеггера). Воронов Василий Михайлович кандидат философских наук доцент кафедры Философии и социальных наук, Федеральное государственное бюджетное образовательное учреждение высшего образования «Мурманский арктический государственный университет» (Россия, г. Мурманск). 183038, Россия, Мурманская Область область, г. Мурманск, ул. Капитана Егрова, 15 [email protected] Статья из рубрики "Philosophy" Аннотация. В статье анализируется проблема экзистенциальных оснований человеческой идентичности в контексте технократических вызовов современной эпохи. В качестве оснований идентичности рассматриваются временность, экстатичность, связанность индивидуального бытия с бытием Других. Внимание уделяется экзистенциальным смыслам смертности и временности Другого, заключающихся в онтологических настроениях боли и тревоги. Эти настроения определяются в качестве оснований подлинного в различных социокультурных идентификациях. Специфика современности определяется в русле философии техники М. Хайдеггера, т.е. в господстве особого способа человеческого бытия – Ge-stell. Антропологические риски и вызовы современной эпохи рассматриваются в возможности поставляемого отношения к любым само-идентификациям. В теоретико-методологическом
    [Show full text]
  • Cristine Celich G. the Face of the Other As Human Facticity: from Husserlian Lebenswelt to Levinasian Alterity . Philos Int J 20
    Philosophy International Journal ISSN: 2641-9130 MEDWIN PUBLISHERS Committed to Create Value for Researchers The Face of the Other as Human Facticity: From Husserlian Lebenswelt to Levinasian Alteritya Cristine Celich G* Post Degree Program of Philosophy of the Federal University of Santa Maria, Brazil Research Article Volume 4 Issue 2 *Corresponding author: Grasiela Cristine Celich, Philosophy PhD student at the post degree Received Date: April 13, 2021 program of Philosophy of the Federal University of Santa Maria. City: Santa Maria. State: Rio Published Date: May 10, 2021 Grande do Sul, Brazil, Email: [email protected] DOI: 10.23880/phij-16000176 Abstract This article aims to demonstrate the possibility of a connection between phenomenology, human facticity and ethics. The possibility of connection between the concepts becomes pertinent from the philosophy of Husserl and the philosophy of Levinas, for both are inserted in the phenomenological theme. Since Husserl’s discovery that science, when based on concepts, on reason, has separated itself from the concrete world and the experiences of the subjects, it has lost its ethical dimension. sphere is characterized by being richer and wider than the objective world of science. Facing this, Levinas, having Husserl as Therefore, Husserl, in formulating the phenomenological method, sought to recover the pre-scientific sphere of life. This his master, managed, based on some Husserlian concepts such as Lebenswelt and the “return to the same things”, to find in the figure of the Face of the Other an irreducible human facticity to all apprehension and understanding by the concept. Thus, concepts are presented regarding Lebenswelt, so that later, the Levinasian concepts which lead to the meeting of irreducible Levinas explains that ethics focuses on the Face of otherness.
    [Show full text]
  • 1 World and Paradigm in Heidegger and Kuhn Mateo Belgrano Universidad Católica Argentina – CONICET Buenos Aires, Argentina Ab
    World and Paradigm in Heidegger and Kuhn Mateo Belgrano Universidad Católica Argentina – CONICET Buenos Aires, Argentina Para citar este artículo: Belgrano, Mateo. «World and Paradigm in Heidegger and Kuhn». Franciscanum 175, Vol. 63 (2021): 1-16. Abstract The aim of this article is to compare Heidegger's philosophy of science with that of Thomas Kuhn. This comparison has two objectives: 1) to use Kuhn's conceptual arsenal to make Heidegger's position clearer; and 2) to show that Heidegger's and Kuhn's positions are not as different as might be expected. Consequently, I may suggest that these philosophies can be compatible. I will show that while there are differences, also there are many continuities. I will address three issues: 1) the differences and similarities between Kuhn's notion of the paradigm and Heidegger's notion of the world; 2) the analogous concepts of «normal science» and «calculating thought»; and 3) the source of intelligibility in both authors. The main difference between the two thinkers, I believe, lies therein. Keywords Science, Paradigm, World, Being, Thinking. Mundo y paradigma en Heidegger y Kuhn Resumen Mi objetivo en este artículo es comparar la filosofía de la ciencia de Heidegger con la de Thomas Kuhn. Con esta comparación quiero perseguir dos objetivos: 1) usar el arsenal conceptual de Kuhn para hacer más clara la posición de Heidegger; y 2) mostrar que las posiciones de Heidegger y Kuhn no son tan diferentes como cabría esperar. Por lo tanto, La presente investigación es parte del proyecto de investigación Cuestiones fundamentales de Filosofía contemporánea: Lenguaje, praxis, cuerpo y poder, a cargo del Dr.
    [Show full text]
  • Hermeneutics of Heidegger's Facticity and Its Religious Aspects
    Studia Philosophiae Christianae UKSW 50(2014)1 POVILAS AleksandravičIUS HERMENEUTICS OF HEIDEGGer’s FACTICITY AND ITS RELIGIOUS ASPECTS Abstract. The concept of facticity that was developed by Heidegger from 1919 to 1923 composes the basis of all his further thought: the conceptions of Dasein and ontological temporality will originate namely from this concept. The article analyzes various expressions of the factitious life (care, Er-eignis, life, Self- Destruction, meaningfulness, death), yet the special consideration is paid to its religious aspects. Really the essence of facticity is treated by Heidegger as a temporality that is essentially correlated with the Christian experience. The influence of Saint Augustine to Heidegger and the Heideggerian concept of methodical atheism are analyzed and this analysis raises the intricate problem of the relation of the Black Forest philosopher to Christian faith and to God. Keywords: Heidegger, hermeneutics, facticity, religious, care, Er-eignis, life, temporality 1. The emergence of the concept of facticity in Heidegger’s work. 2. The account of facticity. 3. Facticity as movement: care. 4. Er-eignis and the formation of the living world. 5. Facticity as life 6. Factical life as self-destruction. 7. Meaningfulness of factical life or the hermeneutic dimension of facticity. 8. Facticity as temporality. 9. Factical life and death. 10. Christian facticity. 11. St. Augustine’s influence on hermeneutics of facticity and the issue of God. 12. Methodological atheism and the mystery of life’s facticity. Povilas Aleksandravicius Mykolas Romeris University, [email protected] Institute of Philosophy and Humanities Ateities g. 20, LT-08303 Vilnius, Lithuania 174 Povilas aleksandravičius [2] On 9 January, 1919, a 30-year old Martin Heidegger wrote a letter to his friend, the canon Engelbert Krebs, informing him of his withdrawal from the Catholic Church and indicating the main reason for his choice: a scholastic system, where the Church aimed to squeeze Christian be- liefs, had become “problematic and unacceptable”1 to him.
    [Show full text]
  • The Question Concerning Technology
    The Question Concerning Technology Martin Heidegger In what follows we shall be questioning concerning technology. Questioning builds a way. We would be advised, therefore, above all to pay heed to the way, and not to fix our attention on isolated sentences and topics. The way is one of thinking. All ways of thinking, more or less perceptibly, lead through language in a manner that is extraordinary. We shall be questioning concerning technology, and in so doing we should like to prepare a free relationship to it. The relationship will be free if it opens our human existence to the essence of technology. When we can respond to this essence, we shall be able to experience the technological within its own bounds. Technology is not equivalent to the essence of technology. When we are seeking the essence of "tree," we have to become aware that what pervades every tree, as tree, is not itself a tree that can be encountered among all the other trees. Likewise, the essence of technology is by no means anything technological. Thus we shall never experience our relationship to the essence of technology so long as we merely represent and pursue the technological, put up with it, or evade it. Everywhere we remain unfree and chained to technology, whether we passionately affirm or deny it. But we are delivered over to it in the worst [288] possible way when we regard it as something neutral; for this conception of it, to which today we particularly like to pay homage, makes us utterly blind to the essence of technology.
    [Show full text]