More Than You Ever Wanted to Know About Epistemic Two-Dimensionalism

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

More Than You Ever Wanted to Know About Epistemic Two-Dimensionalism More than you ever wanted to know about epistemic two-dimensionalism phil 93515 Jeff Speaks February 12, 2007 1 From contextual to epistemic two-dimensionalism . 1 2 Epistemic two-dimensionalism and the status of [T1] . 2 2.1 The epistemic understanding of scenarios . 3 2.2 The metaphysical understanding of scenarios . 4 3 Some more detail about epistemic intensions . 5 3.1 Canonical descriptions . 5 3.2 The epistemic intensions of names . 6 3.3 Epistemic intensions and definite descriptions . 7 4 Potential explanatory roles for epistemic intensions . 8 4.1 Explaining a priori knowledge . 8 4.2 Solving Frege’s puzzle . 8 4.3 Playing a role in the semantics of attitude ascriptions . 9 4.4 Giving a level of mental content which can explain behavior . 10 4.5 Providing a link between conceivability and possibility . 10 5 Objections to epistemic two-dimensionalism . 11 5.1 Problems with contextual two-dimensionalism revisited . 11 5.2 Consequences of denying supervenience without a priori deducibility . 12 5.3 The nature of the ‘possibilities’ ruled out by de re assertions . 12 5.4 Contents vs. intensions . 13 5.5 A posteriori necessities in semantically neutral vocabulary . 13 1 From contextual to epistemic two-dimensionalism In response to the problems with the two dimensionalist system which (I suggested) is found in The Conscious Mind, Chalmers has modified his views. The main change is that he now rejects his earlier close association of primary intensions with Kaplan- style characters, and consequently also rejects the view that a sentence is a priori iff it is true whenever it is uttered. Because the earlier version of two-dimensionalism took primary intensions to be functions from contexts to extensions, he calls this contextual two- dimensionalism. Because the later version of two-dimensionalism takes primary intensions to be functions from epistemic possibilities to extensions, he calls this the epistemic version of two-dimensionalism. To keep things straight: primary intension = epistemic intension scenario = epistemic possibility = the kind of thing which is argument for an epistemic intension secondary intension = subjunctive intension So we hold in place the two central theses of The Conscious Mind: [T1] A sentence is a priori iff it has a necessary primary inten- sion. [T2] A sentence is (metaphysically) necessary iff it has a neces- sary secondary intension. But we now reject the third: [T3] Truth conditions for primary intensions can be defined in terms of Kaplan’s characters. A sentence’s primary inten- sion is true at a world w iff relative to w as context, the sentence delivers a secondary intension which is true at w. And replace it with: [T3*] Primary intensions are epistemic intensions. Epistemic in- tensions are functions from epistemic possibilities — hy- potheses about the world that cannot be ruled out a priori — to extensions. The primary intension of S is true at a scenario e iff e epistemically necessitates S. Combining [T3*] rather than [T3] with [T1], we get that a sentence is a priori iff every epistemic possibility epistemically necessitates the sentence. 2 Epistemic two-dimensionalism and the status of [T1] The key question about the framework concerns the nature of epistemic possibilities — the things which epistemic intensions take as arguments, and deliver extensions as values — which Chalmers calls ‘scenarios.’ Regarding scenarios, we have two possibilities: (i) define them in epistemic terms, taking epistemic possibility as a primitive, or (ii) define them in terms of centered possible worlds (Chalmers (2006a), §3.4). 2 2.1 The epistemic understanding of scenarios Here we consider the first possibility, which we can call the epistemic understanding of scenarios: [T4] e is a scenario ≡df e is an epistemically possible and com- plete hypothesis about the world that cannot be ruled out a priori. Think of these maximal hypotheses of being long sentences of an ideally expressive lan- guage that are both epistemically possible (not ruled out a priori) and epistemically complete (such that there is no sentence S which is such that both it and its negation can be conjoined to the scenario to yield an epistemically possible sentence). If the language is indeed ideally expressive, then we can assume the following Epistemic Plenitude principle: [EP] Every epistemic possibility is epistemically necessitated by some epistemically possible and complete hypothesis. Let’s add to this the view that epistemic necessitation is a priori entailment, so that S epistemically necessitates e iff the material conditional (S → e is a priori). This gives us a definition of truth at a world for primary intensions: [T5] e epistemically necessitates S ≡df (e → S) is a priori. Recall our discussion of contextual two-dimensionalism. There we had an understanding of what primary intensions were supposed to be which was independent of [T1], and we could go on to ask whether we could assign primary intensions to expressions in some way which would make [T1] come out true. This turned out to be difficult to do. By contrast, now there is no problem at all in reconciling the present view of primary intensions with [T1]. After all, [T4], [T5], and [EP] jointly entail [T1]. To see that, consider the following argument by cases (the connection between primary and epistemic intensions is taken for granted): Suppose that S is a priori. S is true at every scenario iff for any scenario e, e epistemically necessitates S iff for any scenario e, the conditional (e → S) is a priori. But if S is a priori, then any conditional with S as consequent will be a priori. So S is true at every scenario. Suppose now that S is not a priori. Then the negation of S is epistemically possible. So, by [EP], the negation of S is epistemically necessitated, and therefore true at, some scenario w. But scenarios are always epistemically possible, so no scenarios contain both S and its negation. So S is false at w. This gives us both directions of [T1]. However, it does not give us both directions of [T1] in an especially impressive way. Epistemic intensions are simply defined in such a way that [T1] comes out true. Anyone who grants that epistemically possible and complete sentences make sense, and that some conditionals are a priori knowable, should therefore concede that, on this understanding of primary intensions, every a priori truth has a necessary primary intension. 3 Does this mean that the two-dimensionalist has won the day? No. All that has been shown so far is that we can define a property of sentences (the property of having a necessary epistemic intension) such that a sentence has it iff it is a priori. Given that this property was defined using the property of a priority, this by itself does not show anything. Chalmers (2006a) (§3.11) recognizes that [T1] is simply made true by definition on this approach. But, he says, this does not make two-dimensionalism trivial. Rather, the value of epistemic two-dimensionalism consists in its giving us a well-defined value of expressions which can be used to explain various phenomena. The value of the system consists in how well it explains those phenomena. We will return at the end to the question of how well epistemic intensions, on the present interpretation, can explain the phenomena in question. 2.2 The metaphysical understanding of scenarios First we turn to a different understanding of scenarios, which does not seem to make [T1] true by definition. This is what Chalmers (2006a), §3.4 calls the metaphysical understand- ing of scenarios. [T4*] e is a scenario ≡df e is a centered possible world (a meta- physically possible world with a designated agent and time). We then need to replace Epistemic Plenitude with Metaphysical Plenitude: [MP] Every epistemic possibility is epistemically necessitated by some centered metaphysically possible world. [MP] should not be understood to entail the false thesis that ‘It is metaphysically possible that water is not H2O’ is true. On the present view what is required is not that there be possible world with respect to which what we say by ‘Water is not H2O’ is true, but only one which is such that, were that world actual, and were we to know everything about it, it would be a priori that ‘Water is not H2O’ is true. We keep for now the definition of epistemic necessitation in terms of the a priori given by [T5]. It is clear that just as [T4], [T5], and [EP] imply [T1], so also [T4*], [T5], and [MP] imply [T1], so long as we assume one further plausible thesis: [T6] Every centered metaphysically possible world is also epis- temically possible. We can then argue as follows: Suppose that S is a priori. S is true at every scenario iff for any scenario e, e epistemically necessitated S iff for any scenario e, the conditional (e → S) is a priori. But if S is a priori, then any conditional with S as consequent will be a priori. So S is true at every scenario. 4 Suppose now that S is not a priori. Then the negation of S is epistemically possible. So, by [MP], the negation of S is epistemically necessitated, and therefore true at, some scenario w. But by [T4*] and [T6] scenarios are always epistemically possible, so no scenarios contain both S and its negation. So S is false at w. Again, we pretty much have the ‘core thesis’ of two-dimensionalism, [T1], entailed by the definitions of primary intension, scenarios, and epistemic necessitation. The only difference between this case and the case of the epistemic understanding of scenarios is that here we also have to assume [T6], which is plausible, and [MP], which is less clearly true.
Recommended publications
  • A General Framework for the Semantics of Type Theory
    A General Framework for the Semantics of Type Theory Taichi Uemura November 14, 2019 Abstract We propose an abstract notion of a type theory to unify the semantics of various type theories including Martin-L¨oftype theory, two-level type theory and cubical type theory. We establish basic results in the semantics of type theory: every type theory has a bi-initial model; every model of a type theory has its internal language; the category of theories over a type theory is bi-equivalent to a full sub-2-category of the 2-category of models of the type theory. 1 Introduction One of the key steps in the semantics of type theory and logic is to estab- lish a correspondence between theories and models. Every theory generates a model called its syntactic model, and every model has a theory called its internal language. Classical examples are: simply typed λ-calculi and cartesian closed categories (Lambek and Scott 1986); extensional Martin-L¨oftheories and locally cartesian closed categories (Seely 1984); first-order theories and hyperdoctrines (Seely 1983); higher-order theories and elementary toposes (Lambek and Scott 1986). Recently, homotopy type theory (The Univalent Foundations Program 2013) is expected to provide an internal language for what should be called \el- ementary (1; 1)-toposes". As a first step, Kapulkin and Szumio (2019) showed that there is an equivalence between dependent type theories with intensional identity types and finitely complete (1; 1)-categories. As there exist correspondences between theories and models for almost all arXiv:1904.04097v2 [math.CT] 13 Nov 2019 type theories and logics, it is natural to ask if one can define a general notion of a type theory or logic and establish correspondences between theories and models uniformly.
    [Show full text]
  • Frege's Theory of Sense
    Frege’s theory of sense Jeff Speaks August 25, 2011 1. Three arguments that there must be more to meaning than reference ............................1 1.1. Frege’s puzzle about identity sentences 1.2. Understanding and knowledge of reference 1.3. Opaque contexts 2. The theoretical roles of senses .........................................................................................4 2.1. Frege’s criterion for distinctness of sense 2.2. Sense determines reference, but not the reverse 2.3. Indirect reference 2.4. Sense, force, and the theory of speech acts 3. What are senses? .............................................................................................................6 We have now seen how a theory of reference — a theory that assigns to each expression of the language a reference, which is what it contributes to determining the truth or falsity of sentences in which it occurs — might look for a fragment of English. (The fragment of English includes proper names, n-place predicates, and quantifiers.) We now turn to Frege’s reasons for thinking that a theory of reference must be supplemented with a theory of sense. 1. THREE ARGUMENTS THAT THERE MUST BE MORE TO MEANING THAN REFERENCE 1.1. Frege’s puzzle about identity sentences As Frege says at the outset of “On sense and reference,” identity “gives rise to challenging questions which are not altogether easy to answer.” The puzzle raised by identity sentences is that, if, even though “the morning star” and “the evening star” have the same reference — the planet Venus — the sentences [1] The morning star is the morning star. [2] The morning star is the evening star. seem quite different. They seem, as Frege says, to differ in “cognitive value.” [1] is trivial and a priori; whereas [2] seems a posteriori, and could express a valuable extension of knowledge — it, unlike [1], seems to express an astronomical discovery which took substantial empirical work to make.
    [Show full text]
  • A Formal Mereology of Potential Parts
    Not Another Brick in the Wall: an Extensional Mereology for Potential Parts Contents 0. Abstract .................................................................................................................................................................................................. 1 1. An Introduction to Potential Parts .......................................................................................................................................................... 1 2. The Physical Motivation for Potential Parts ............................................................................................................................................ 5 3. A Model for Potential Parts .................................................................................................................................................................... 9 3.1 Informal Semantics: Dressed Electron Propagator as Mereological Model ...................................................................................... 9 3.2 Formal Semantics: A Join Semi-Lattice ............................................................................................................................................ 10 3.3 Syntax: Mereological Axioms for Potential Parts ............................................................................................................................ 14 4. Conclusions About Potential Parts .......................................................................................................................................................
    [Show full text]
  • Challenging the Principle of Compositionality in Interpreting Natural Language Texts Françoise Gayral, Daniel Kayser, François Lévy
    Challenging the Principle of Compositionality in Interpreting Natural Language Texts Françoise Gayral, Daniel Kayser, François Lévy To cite this version: Françoise Gayral, Daniel Kayser, François Lévy. Challenging the Principle of Compositionality in Interpreting Natural Language Texts. E. Machery, M. Werning, G. Schurz, eds. the compositionality of meaning and content, vol II„ ontos verlag, pp.83–105, 2005, applications to Linguistics, Psychology and neuroscience. hal-00084948 HAL Id: hal-00084948 https://hal.archives-ouvertes.fr/hal-00084948 Submitted on 11 Jul 2006 HAL is a multi-disciplinary open access L’archive ouverte pluridisciplinaire HAL, est archive for the deposit and dissemination of sci- destinée au dépôt et à la diffusion de documents entific research documents, whether they are pub- scientifiques de niveau recherche, publiés ou non, lished or not. The documents may come from émanant des établissements d’enseignement et de teaching and research institutions in France or recherche français ou étrangers, des laboratoires abroad, or from public or private research centers. publics ou privés. Challenging the Principle of Compositionality in Interpreting Natural Language Texts Franc¸oise Gayral, Daniel Kayser and Franc¸ois Levy´ Franc¸ois Levy,´ University Paris Nord, Av. J. B. Clement,´ 93430 Villetaneuse, France fl@lipn.univ-paris13.fr 1 Introduction The main assumption of many contemporary semantic theories, from Montague grammars to the most recent papers in journals of linguistics semantics, is and remains the principle of compositionality. This principle is most commonly stated as: The meaning of a complex expression is determined by its structure and the meanings of its constituents. It is also adopted by more computation-oriented traditions (Artificial Intelli- gence or Natural Language Processing – henceforth, NLP).
    [Show full text]
  • Difference Between Sense and Reference
    Difference Between Sense And Reference Inherent and manipulable Blayne often overspend some boyfriend octagonally or desiccate puffingly. Lev never grangerized any opprobrium smash-up stagily, is Thorn calefactive and quick-tempered enough? Phillipe is Deuteronomic: she canalize parabolically and colligating her phosphite. What other languages tend to reference and specialisations of a description theory of two months ago since it can see how to transmit information retrieval and connect intensions are conjured up questions So given relevant information about the physical and mental states of individuals in the community, there will be no problem evaluating epistemic intensions. Of the sense of a member of conditional and between sense and reference changing the reference; but an aspect is commutative and. When they differ in german inflected words can say that difference between sense. Philosophy Stack Exchange is a question and answer site for those interested in the study of the fundamental nature of knowledge, reality, and existence. Edited by Michael Beaney. The difference in this number zero is not leave his main burden is always review what using. These contributions are local by certain content like Russell. The end is widespread whereas the reference changes One enemy more objects in the already world headquarters which a brief can sense its bishop The different examples of people word. Gottlob Frege ON sow AND REFERENCE excerpt 25. Contemporary American philosophers like Saul Kripke however submit that sense theory impliesthe description theory. The basic unit of syntax. One crucial distinction is a sense and reference. If you can comment moderation is that parthood and also served as discussed later noticed by another reason, as far from putnam argues as agents and.
    [Show full text]
  • The Logic of Sense and Reference
    The Logic of Sense and Reference Reinhard Muskens Tilburg Center for Logic and Philosophy of Science (TiLPS) Days 4 and 5 Reinhard Muskens (TiLPS) The Logic of Sense and Reference Days 4 and 5 1 / 56 Overview 1 Introduction 2 Types and Terms 3 Models 4 Proofs 5 Model Theory 6 Applications 7 Worlds 8 Conclusion Reinhard Muskens (TiLPS) The Logic of Sense and Reference Days 4 and 5 2 / 56 Introduction Intensional Models for the Theory of Types When we looked at Thomason's work, we saw that it is possible to work with propositions as primitive entities within the framework of classical type theory. Today and tomorrow we'll develop an alternative. We will generalize standard type theory so that a sense-reference distinction becomes available. We shall give up the Axiom of Extensionality. And we shall generalize the `general models' of Henkin (1950) in order to make our models match the weaker logic. Many desired notions will become available in the generalized logic and logical omniscience problems will disappear. See Muskens (2007) for references and technical details. Reinhard Muskens (TiLPS) The Logic of Sense and Reference Days 4 and 5 3 / 56 Introduction Intensionality and Extensionality Whitehead and Russell (1913) call a propositional function of propositional functions F extensional if, in modern notation: 8XY (8~x(X~x $ Y ~x) ! (FX ! FY )). (This is slightly generalized to the case where X and Y take an arbitrary finite number of arguments, not just one.) In a relational version of type theory (Orey 1959; Sch¨utte1960) the formula above defines the extensionality of relations of relations.
    [Show full text]
  • Intension, Extension, and the Model of Belief and Knowledge in Economics
    Erasmus Journal for Philosophy and Economics, Volume 5, Issue 2, Autumn 2012, pp. 1-26. http://ejpe.org/pdf/5-2-art-1.pdf Intension, extension, and the model of belief and knowledge in economics IVAN MOSCATI University of Insubria Bocconi University Abstract: This paper investigates a limitation of the model of belief and knowledge prevailing in mainstream economics, namely the state-space model. Because of its set-theoretic nature, this model has difficulties in capturing the difference between expressions that designate the same object but have different meanings, i.e., expressions with the same extension but different intensions. This limitation generates puzzling results concerning what individuals believe or know about the world as well as what individuals believe or know about what other individuals believe or know about the world. The paper connects these puzzling results to two issues that are relevant for economic theory beyond the state-space model, namely, framing effects and the distinction between the model-maker and agents that appear in the model. Finally, the paper discusses three possible solutions to the limitations of the state-space model, and concludes that the two alternatives that appear practicable also have significant drawbacks. Keywords : intension, extension, belief, knowledge, interactive belief, state-space model JEL Classification: B41, C70, D80 Much of current mathematical economic analysis is based, in one way or another, on the theory of sets initiated by Georg Cantor (1883) and Richard Dedekind (1888) in the late nineteenth century, axiomatically developed by Ernst Zermelo (1908), Abraham Fraenkel (1923), John von Neumann (1928), and others in the early twentieth century, and usually AUTHOR ’S NOTE : I am grateful to Robert Aumann, Pierpaolo Battigalli, Giacomo Bonanno, Richard Bradley, Paolo Colla, Marco Dardi, Alfredo Di Tillio, Vittorioemanuele Ferrante, Francesco Guala, Conrad Heilmann, and Philippe Mongin for helpful discussions and suggestions on previous drafts.
    [Show full text]
  • The Limits of Classical Extensional Mereology for the Formalization of Whole–Parts Relations in Quantum Chemical Systems
    philosophies Article The Limits of Classical Extensional Mereology for the Formalization of Whole–Parts Relations in Quantum Chemical Systems Marina Paola Banchetti-Robino Department of Philosophy, Florida Atlantic University, Boca Raton, FL 33431, USA; [email protected]; Tel.: +1-561-297-3868 Received: 9 July 2020; Accepted: 12 August 2020; Published: 13 August 2020 Abstract: This paper examines whether classical extensional mereology is adequate for formalizing the whole–parts relation in quantum chemical systems. Although other philosophers have argued that classical extensional and summative mereology does not adequately formalize whole–parts relation within organic wholes and social wholes, such critiques often assume that summative mereology is appropriate for formalizing the whole–parts relation in inorganic wholes such as atoms and molecules. However, my discussion of atoms and molecules as they are conceptualized in quantum chemistry will establish that standard mereology cannot adequately fulfill this task, since the properties and behavior of such wholes are context-dependent and cannot simply be reduced to the summative properties of their parts. To the extent that philosophers of chemistry have called for the development of an alternative mereology for quantum chemical systems, this paper ends by proposing behavioral mereology as a promising step in that direction. According to behavioral mereology, considerations of what constitutes a part of a whole is dependent upon the observable behavior displayed by these entities.
    [Show full text]
  • Algebraic Type Theory and the Gluing Construction 2
    JONATHANSTERLING ALGEBRAIC TYPE THEORY & THE GLUING CONSTRUCTION algebraic type theory and the gluing construction 2 The syntactic metatheory of type theory comprises several components, which are brutally intertwined in the dependent case: closed canonicity, normalization, decidability of type checking, and initiality (soundness and completeness). While these standard results play a scientific role in type theory essentially analogous to that of cut elimination in structural proof theory, they have historically been very difficult to obtain and scale using purely syntactic methods. The purpose of this lecture is to explain a more abstract and tractable methodology for obtaining these results: generalized algebraic theories and categorical gluing. Introduction Type theory is not any specific artifact, to be found in the “great book of type theories”, but is instead a tradition of scientific practice which is bent toward pro- viding useful language for mathematical construction, and nurturing the dualities of the abstract and the concrete, and of syntax and semantics. Syntax itself is an exercise in brutality, and to study it in the concrete for too long is a form of in- tellectual suicide — as we will see in the following sections, the concrete view of syntax offers dozens of unforced choices, each of which is exceedingly painful to develop in a precise way. If that is the case, what is it that type theorists are doing? How do we tell if our ideas are correct, or mere formalistic deviations? In structural proof theory, the practice of cut elimination separates the wheat from the chaff (Girard, The Blind Spot: Lectures on Logic); type theorists, on the other hand, do not have a single answer to this question, but pay careful attention to a number of (individually defeasible) syntactic properties which experience has shown to be important in practice: 1.
    [Show full text]
  • Strategic Brand Ambiguity, the Gateway to Perceived Product Fit? a Brand Extension Study
    Running Head: STRATEGIC BRAND AMBIGUITY, THE GATEWAY TO PERCEIVED PRODUCT FIT? A BRAND EXTENSION STUDY Strategic Brand Ambiguity, the Gateway to Perceived Product fit? A Brand Extension Study Graduate School of Communication Master’s program Communication Science Melissa das Dores Student number 10617442 Supervisor Dr. Daan Muntinga Date of completion: 29-01-2016 STRATEGIC BRAND AMBIGUITY, THE WAY TO PERCEIVED FIT AND TO BRAND EXTENSION SUCCES? Abstract An experiment was conducted exploring the effects of strategic brand ambiguity, the use of intended multiplicity in brand meaning. It is hypothesized that strategic brand ambiguity leads to an increase in perceived fit of brand extensions through the activation and integration of multiple brand associations. In addition, the moderating effects of brand familiarity and the individual difference variable, the self-construal are examined. Results showed strategic brand ambiguity did not predict number of brand associations nor did brand ambiguity predict the number of products perceived to fit. Strategic brand ambiguity- brand associations- brand familiarity- Self-construal 1 STRATEGIC BRAND AMBIGUITY, THE WAY TO PERCEIVED FIT AND TO BRAND EXTENSION SUCCES? Introduction For fast moving consumer goods the launch of brand extensions are an integral part of business (Sing et al 2012). This approach represents one of the most frequently employed branding strategies (Aaker & Keller, 1990; Kim & Yoon 2013). This is due to brand extensions generating financial, distributional and promotional benefits as well as increasing parent brand equity. Unfortunately, the failure rate of brand extensions in many fast moving industries is high: a recent report showed that in 2012, only four percent of consumer packaged goods met the AC Nielsen requirements for innovation breakthrough (ACNielsen, 2014).
    [Show full text]
  • Sense and Reference a Picture of the Grammar a Picture of the Grammar
    A picture of the grammar grammar context Sense and Reference SYNTAX SEMANTICS PRAGMATICS Foundations of Semantics But remember what we had to do to get from linguistically LING 130 encoded meaning to the proposition expressed: James Pustejovsky ! Assign reference Norman talked to her in the bedroom. Norman Bates talked to the mother of Norman Bates in the master bedroom of Norman Bates’ house. Thanks to Dan Wedgewood of U. Edinburgh for use of some slides A picture of the grammar A revised picture grammar context grammar context SYNTAX SEMANTICS PRAGMATICS SYNTAX LINGUISTIC PROPOSITIONAL PRAGMATICS SEMANTICS SEMANTICS reference assignment implicature Kinds of meaning Kinds of meaning dog (n.): domesticated, four-legged dog (n.): domesticated, four-legged carnivorous mammal of the species carnivorous mammal of the species canis familiaris canis familiaris ! Two kinds of definition here ! Two kinds of definition here: 1. listing essential properties Kinds of meaning Kinds of meaning dog (n.): domesticated, four-legged dog (n.): domesticated, four-legged carnivorous mammal of the species carnivorous mammal of the species canis familiaris canis familiaris ! Two kinds of definition here: In fact, stating properties also assigns 1. listing essential properties an entity to a class or classes: 2. stating membership of a class " domesticated things, 4-legged things, carnivores, mammals… Properties and sense Sense and denotation On the other hand, properties determine So we have two kinds of meaning, which relationships between linguistic look
    [Show full text]
  • HISTORY of LOGICAL CONSEQUENCE 1. Introduction
    HISTORY OF LOGICAL CONSEQUENCE CONRAD ASMUS AND GREG RESTALL 1. Introduction Consequence is a, if not the, core subject matter of logic. Aristotle's study of the syllogism instigated the task of categorising arguments into the logically good and the logically bad; the task remains an essential element of the study of logic. In a logically good argument, the conclusion follows validly from the premises; thus, the study of consequence and the study of validity are the same. In what follows, we will engage with a variety of approaches to consequence. The following neutral framework will enhance the discussion of this wide range of approaches. Consequences are conclusions of valid arguments. Arguments have two parts: a conclusion and a collection of premises. The conclusion and the premises are all entities of the same sort. We will call the conclusion and premises of an argument the argument's components and will refer to anything that can be an argument component as a proposition. The class of propositions is defined func- tionally (they are the entities which play the functional role of argument compo- nents); thus, the label should be interpreted as metaphysically neutral. Given the platonistic baggage often associated with the label \proposition", this may seem a strange choice but the label is already used for the argument components of many of the approaches below (discussions of Aristotlean and Medieval logic are two ex- amples). A consequence relation is a relation between collections of premises and conclusions; a collection of premises is related to a conclusion if and only if the latter is a consequence of the former.
    [Show full text]