Patterns of Perception Nemira Hathor Gasiunas Submitted in Partial

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Patterns of Perception Nemira Hathor Gasiunas Submitted in Partial Patterns of Perception Nemira Hathor Gasiunas Submitted in partial fulfilment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in the Graduate School of Arts and Sciences COLUMBIA UNIVERSITY 2019 © 2019 Nemira Gasiunas All rights reserved ABSTRACT Patterns of Perception Nemira Gasiunas Our ordinary concept of perception contains a seeming tension: we distinguish perception from thought on the grounds that it is a direct awareness of mind-independent objects through their effects on our senses; yet we also allow that what we see (hear, feel, etc) is determined by how we interpret or classify the data that comes through our senses. Theorists of perception disagree over which of these intuitions should prevail, with some maintaining that concepts are in play all the way down and others that perceptual awareness is wholly immediate and concrete. But we do not have to choose. This dissertation argues that the patterns of perception sustain a distinctive form of nonconceptual classification, in which property spaces organize sensory matter so as to preserve rather than discard its concreteness and detail. What then is classification without concepts? What sort of abstraction, generality, representation, or form does it entail? And what ramifications then for thinking about the roots of language and reason, and of our awareness of the external world? TABLE OF CONTENTS List of Figures iii Acknowledgments iv Introduction 2 1. Reconceiving the Nonconceptualism Debate 39 1.1 Introduction 39 1.2 The (Conventional) Nonconceptualism Debate: Evans and McDowell 44 1.3 The Reconceived Nonconceptualism Debate: Travis 58 1.4 Two Perspectives on the Nonconceptual 67 1.5 Two Perspectives on ‘Frege’s Line’ 80 1.6 Conclusion 86 2. Classification Without Concepts 91 2.1 Introduction 91 2.2 Monism 98 2.3 The Argument from Mereology 106 2.4 Attribution without Atomism 113 2.5 The Argument from the Nature of Propositions 129 2.6 Attribution without Propositions 132 2.7 Comparing Conceptual and Nonconceptual Classification 141 2.8 Conclusion 149 3. Rethinking the Generality Constraint 156 3.1 Introduction 156 3.2 The Generality Constraint and Nonconceptual Content 160 i 3.3 The Argument from Systematicity 169 3.4 The Problem 175 3.5 Degrees of Stimulus-Independence 187 3.6 The Argument from Inference 192 3.7 Nonconceptual Content Regained 202 3.8 Conclusion 207 4. The Problem of Perceptual Receptivity 213 4.1 Introduction 213 4.2 The Intuition 218 4.3 The Problem 229 4.4 Redefining the Stimulus 243 4.5 Redefining Receptivity: A Conceptualist Reading of Kant 249 4.6 Redefining Receptivity: A Nonconceptualist Reading of Kant 260 4.7 The ‘Predictive Processing’ Theory 268 4.8 Conclusion 274 Conclusion 279 References 292 ii LIST OF FIGURES Figure 1. Two drawings of a boa-constrictor having swallowed an elephant. The first figure illustrates the author’s drawing in its original form, which is subsequently mistaken by the adults for a drawing of a hat. In the second figure, the snake is drawn in cross-section, so that the true meaning of his figure is impossible to misconstrue, even by the stupidity of adults. ………………………….. 3 Figure 2. A diagram illustrating a ‘digital-conversion system.’ The system takes in the registrations of the speedometer in analog form and generates a digital output that classifies the speed within a general range (tones #1-4). ……………………105 Figure 3. The Kanisza triangle demonstrates the phenomenon of illusory contour. The central figure is seen as a triangle even though no edges are marked on the page. ………………………………………………………………………………………………………216 Figure 4. An illustration of the visual phenomenon of amodal completion. The visual system ‘fills in’ information about the shape of the obscured object, choosing the ‘solution’ in figure B rather than any of those in figures C-E. The illustration comes from Palmer (1997: xiv). ……………………………………………………..…………220 Figure 5. The chessboard illusion illustrates the processes that underwrite normal cases of color constancy. In the left figure, squares A and B are seen as different colors due to visual cues indicating that B is in shadow. In reality, the two squares are the same color, as illustrated in the figure on the right. …………………..………….222 Figure 6. A sequence of four images showing how a figure moving through space receives information that reduces indeterminacy in the retinal image. In this example, the changing size of the doorframe as the subject approaches indicates the effect of distance on retinal size. ……………………………………………………..…..……236 Figure 7. A regular rectangle oriented at an angle of 90 degrees is normally seen as a diamond. ……………………………………………………..…………………………………….…….237 iii ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS The writing of this dissertation challenged me in ways I could not have imagined. So, whilst authors often acknowledge those ‘without whom this work would not have been written,’ I want to stress how literally these words are true for me. At a time when I had nothing but a head full of ideas and a bunch of hang-ups to show for five years of near-constant toil, Lydia Goehr took me on as her student. If I am sitting here not 14 months later putting the finishing touches on a 300-page text, she is the reason why. Lydia believed in me and she fought for me when I had almost no fight left in me. She reignited my love for the written word, and taught me by her example to see that my creativity and intuition are an asset to my philosophical abilities and not a weakness in them. If I can give to my future students even a fraction of what was so freely given to me, I will have done well by them. If writing can be a hell, then my friendship with Manu Chander is steel forged in its fires: his cheers propelled me over the finish line, just as loud as they had been when the starting gun sounded seven years ago. The same goes for Jorge Morales, who walked this path beside me and understands those things I do not know how to communicate in words. Matthew Heeney was wise and impossibly generous in coaxing the real me out from underneath an armour of words. I do not know if he, Simon Brown, Grace Helton and Louise Doust realize how important their lively discussions and compassionate feedback were in making philosophy feel fun — and safe — for me again. Lex Braes kept my eyes and mind open through his intellectual honesty and his passion for perceptual experience. David Rosenthal, through his encouragement and endless wisdom, has helped me in ways I could not have imagined when I first took his class as part of my masters requirements iv many years ago. The support I received from Jessica Collins and Achille Varzi in my hour of need meant more than I could say. Stacey Quartaro’s ingenuity and generous spirit came to my rescue on multiple occasions. My friends and loved-ones outside of my philosophical community played a crucial role in keeping me sane. Where my intellectual world could easily have become drab and dreary, Lavinia Lorch and the CUSP stuff filled it with color and life. The students I taught through CUSP and through my summer classes reminded me over and over again what all of this is really about. Jennifer Friede, Julia Burgdorff and Gabrielle Sullivan never stopped showing up for me, even during the black hole of those final few years; their unconditional love and their loyalty leaves me speechless. Tracey Ober, Anne Kadet, James Bott, Lynne Buckley and Erin Evers have guided me through blind alleys more times than I could possibly count. I owe a special debt of gratitude to those who have had to endure the turbulence of writing a dissertation as the price of loving and living with me. My mother and father, Nijole and Aras, gave unstintingly of themselves to nurture my love of knowledge and to provide the practical support necessary for me to pursue it. My sisters, Saule and Geddie, joined with them in indulging me with discussions of concepts around the dinner table, in patiently providing feedback, and in setting me back on my feet every time I got knocked down. Most of all I thank my husband, George, the man who was there to hit the send button after I had fallen asleep on his shoulder. His huge heart made a home for me when I least expected to find one, and humbles me every day. v PATTERNS OF PERCEPTION NEMIRA GASIUNAS Glory be to God for dappled things— For skies of couple-colour as a brindled cow; For rose-moles all in stipple upon trout that swim; Fresh-firecoal chestnut-falls; finches’ wings; Landscape plotted and pieced—fold, fallow, and plough; And all trades, their gear and tackle and trim. All things counter, original, spare, strange; Whatever is fickle, freckled (who knows how?) With swift, slow; sweet, sour; adazzle, dim; He fathers-forth whose beauty is past change: Praise Him. —Gerard Manley-Hopkins, ‘Pied Beauty’ 1 PATTERNS OF PERCEPTION NEMIRA GASIUNAS INTRODUCTION Our ordinary concept of perception contains two elements which, if not quite contradictory, stand in a seeming tension with one another. In the first place, we regard perception as yielding a direct awareness of objects in our environment, through their effects on our senses. If you see a bird in the tree, then you are aware of an entity, existing independently of you that is directly registered by your visual apparatus. By contrast, if you conclude that there is a bird in the tree on the basis of seeing its droppings on the ground, or if you are told there is a bird in the tree by someone else who can see it, then you apprehend the existence of the bird indirectly; not by perceiving it but by constructing it out of something else you perceive.
Recommended publications
  • 1 the Mind-Body-Body Problem Robert
    1 The Mind-Body-Body Problem Robert Hanna and Evan Thompson∗ Theoria et Historia Scientiarum: International Journal for Interdisciplinary Studies 7 (1) (2003): 23-42. From the point of view of Husserl’s ontology, the traditional mind-body problem looks hopelessly simplistic. Not only must we deal with relations between mind— indeed consciousness, soul [psyche], spirit [human personhood]—and body. We must address different aspects of the body itself as living organism and as material thing. This body-body problem is suppressed in a Cartesian ontology that reduces the body to a mechanism in the sense of seventeenth-century physics, as Descartes sought to reduce all of physics to mechanics. —David Woodruff Smith1 It seems to me that post-Kripke, the most promising line of attack on the mind- body problem is to see whether any sense can be made of the idea that mental processes might be physical processes necessarily but not analytically. —Thomas Nagel2 ∗ We gratefully acknowledge the Center for Consciousness Studies at the University of Arizona, Tucson, which provided a grant for the support of this work. E.T. is also supported by the Social Sciences and Humanities Research Council of Canada, and the McDonnell Project in Philosophy and the Neurosciences. 1 See David Woodruff Smith, “Mind and Body,” in The Cambridge Companion to Husserl (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1995), pp. 323-393, at p. 358. 2 Thomas Nagel, “The Psychophysical Nexus,” in Paul Boghossian and Christopher Peacocke (eds.), New Essays on the A Priori (Oxford: Clarendon/Oxford University Press, 2000), pp. 433-471, at p. 434.
    [Show full text]
  • Magnitudes: Metaphysics, Explanation, and Perception
    Christopher Peacocke Magnitudes: Metaphysics, Explanation, and Perception || Christopher Peacocke: Columbia University, [email protected] 1 Magnitudes: Exposition of a Realistic Ontology I am going to argue for a robust realism about magnitudes, as irreducible ele- ments in our ontology. This realistic attitude, I will argue, gives a better meta- physics than the alternatives. It suggests some new options in the philosophy of science. It also provides the materials for a better account of the mind’s relation to the world, in particular its perceptual relations. As a preliminary, let us distinguish between magnitude-types, magnitudes, and magnitude-tropes. Magnitude-types are generic kinds of magnitudes. Dis- tance is one magnitude-type, whose instances are more specific distances, such as the distance measured by one meter, and the distance measured by ten miles. Gravitational mass is another magnitude-type, whose instances include the magnitude measured by one gram, and the magnitude measured by ten pounds weight. Magnitudes come in types. Every magnitude is of some magnitude type. As Frege said, “Something is a magnitude not all by itself, but only insofar as it belongs with other objects of a class which is a domain of magnitudes” - “Etwas ist eine Grösse nicht für sich allein sondern nur, sofern es mit andern Gegenständen einer Klasse angehört, die ein Grössengebiet ist” (1998: §161:159). If we slice more finely than magnitudes, we reach magnitude-tropes. Just as we distinguish between properties and tropes, between the property of being red and this particular thing’s redness, to be distinguished from a different ob- ject’s redness, so we can equally make the parallel distinction for magnitudes.
    [Show full text]
  • Introduction
    Introduction Paul Boghossian and Christopher Peacocke 1. Identifying the A Priori An a priori proposition is one which can be known to be true without any justification from the character of the subject's experience. This is a brief, pre‐theoretical characterization that needs some refinement; but it captures the core of what many philosophers have meant by the notion. Under this intuitive characterization, propositions which are plausibly a priori include the following: the axioms, inference rules, and theorems of logic; the axioms and theorems of arithmetic, and likewise the axioms and theorems of other parts of mathematics and other sciences of the abstract; the principles of the probability calculus; principles of colour incompatibility and implication; some definitions; and perhaps some truths of philosophy itself. To say that something can be known without any justification from the character of the subject's experience is to say that there is a way of coming to know it which does not rely on any such justification. When we are considering issues about the a priori, it can often help to focus on ways of coming to know and their distinctive properties. Suppose you see someone across a restaurant, and you thereby come to believe and know ‘That's the cellist Yo‐Yo Ma.’ The way in which you come to know this may involve the following: you have a memory image of a photograph of Yo‐Yo Ma; you believe that the face you see across the restaurant is an older version of that remembered face; and you accept the content of your current perception.
    [Show full text]
  • C the JOURNAL of PHILOSOPHY C
    c . c THE JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY volume cv, no. 2, february 2008 c . c THE SITUATION-DEPENDENCY OF PERCEPTION* ow can perception give us knowledge of the world? One of the challenges in answering this question is that we always H perceive objects from a particular location, under particular lighting conditions, and similar features of the environment that de- termine the way objects are presented. Despite this fact, we can per- ceive the shape and color of objects.1 We can perceive the shape of objects although only the facing surfaces are visible, and we can perceive two same-sized objects located at different distances to be the same size. Similarly, we can perceive the uniform color of a yellow wall although parts of it are illuminated more brightly than others, and we can recognize the sound of a cello regardless of whether it is played on a street or in a concert hall. More generally, subjects can perceive the properties objects have regardless of the situational features, al- though the way an object is presented always depends on the situa- tional features. When I speak of objects without further qualification, I mean mind- independent, external objects, such as cats and tables. Let us call the properties that an object has regardless of the situational features the intrinsic properties of the object. An intrinsic property of an object is a * I am indebted to Keith Allen, Robert Audi, Stephen Engstrom, Alan Ha´jek, Benj Hellie, Anjana Jacob, James John, Uriah Kriegel, William Lycan, Mohan Matthen, Anders Nes, Gurpreet Rattan, Sydney Shoemaker, Declan Smithies, Evan Thompson, Timothy Williamson, Wayne Wu, and the members of the Australian National University philosophy of mind reading group for comments on a draft of this paper.
    [Show full text]
  • Proposal for Contemporary Debates in Philosophy of Mind
    Proposal for Contemporary Debates in Philosophy of Mind Edited by Jonathan Cohen∗and Brian McLaughliny This volume will introduce the central debates in contemporary philosophy of mind. The volume will include ten pairs of newly commissioned essays ad- vocating opposing viewpoints | one for each of the ten topics listed below. In addition, the editors will provide a substantive introduction that will lay out the necessary background for the debates and locate the individual topics within philosophy of mind and in relation to one another. The essays will each be around 6000 to 8000 words in length, and will be accessible to upper-level undergraduates and graduate students. Consequently, we expect that the volume could be used as text for advanced courses in phi- losophy of mind. However, the essays will also represent the state of play in the areas, and will contain original argumentation by eminent philosophers, so it will also be an important text for academics working in philosophy of mind and adjoining areas. We have organized our questions under the three headings that, in our minds, structure the central debates in contemporary philosophy of mind: questions about the ontology of the mental, questions about the nature of mental content, and questions about the nature of consciousness. For many of the questions on our list, we have suggested a number of backup authors in case our first choices are unable to write the essays. Although some names appear more than once on our list (including appearances as backup authors) we would not allow more than one piece by a single author in the volume.
    [Show full text]
  • Forthcoming in American Philosophical Quarterly
    Forthcoming in American Philosophical Quarterly Scents and Sensibilia ∗ Clare Batty University of Kentucky Beauty is an ecstasy; it is as simple as hunger. There is really nothing to be said about it. It is like the perfume of a rose: you can smell it and that is all. - W. Somerset Maugham, Cakes and Ale An ongoing debate in the philosophy of perception is the one concerning how we should account for the phenomenal character—or the ‘what it is like’—of perceptual experience. Within this debate, there are those who think that qualia exist and those who do not. Qualia realists claim that there are introspectible properties of experience that play a crucial role in determining phenomenal character. Intentionalists are among those who think that there are no such properties. Intentionalism is the view that there is nothing more to the phenomenal character of a perceptual experience than its representational content—that is, the way that things in the world appear to be. In arguing that qualia do not exist, intentionalists have drawn attention to the alleged transparency of experience. Experience is said to be transparent in the sense that you ‘see right through it’ and onto the objects and properties in the external world. Qualia simply aren’t there to be found. This paper explores the notion of transparency. Most of the discussions of transparency have focused on vision, a sense modality for which transparency can seem intuitive. But most intentionalists take it that intentionalism is true for all of the sensory modalities. This is in keeping with what we can call the Unification Thesis—namely, the thesis that certain philosophical questions about perception will shake out in the same way for each of the sensory modalities.
    [Show full text]
  • 1 Does Perception Outstrip Our Concepts in Fineness Of
    DOES PERCEPTION OUTSTRIP OUR CONCEPTS IN FINENESS OF GRAIN? Kevin Connolly Abstract We seem perfectly able to perceive fine-grained shades of colour even without possessing precise concepts for them. The same might be said of shapes. I argue that this is in fact not the case. A subject can perceive a colour or shape only if she possesses a concept of that type of colour or shape. I provide new justification for this thesis, and do not rely on demonstrative concepts such as THIS SHADE or THAT SHAPE, a move first suggested by John McDowell, but rejected by Christopher Peacocke and Richard Heck among others.1 1. Introduction My claim is that a subject can have a perception of a colour or shape only if she possesses a concept of that type of colour or shape. This thesis, which I call Colour and Shape Conceptualism, may seem counter-intuitive. It seems that we can perceive some colours and shapes perfectly well even though we lack precise concepts for them. It seems that in such cases our perceptions outstrip our concepts in terms of their fineness of grain. I think that this is incorrect, and I try to show how we possess precise colour and shape concepts for every shade and shape that we can perceive. I do so without appealing to demonstrative concepts such as THIS SHADE or THAT SHAPE, a solution first suggested by John McDowell,2 but rejected by Christopher Peacocke,3 Richard Heck,4 Jerome Dokic and Elizabeth Pacherie,5 and Sean Kelly.6 I call Nonconceptualism the view that a subject can have a perception of some property even if she lacks a concept of that type of property.
    [Show full text]
  • Subjects and Consciousness
    OUP CORRECTED PROOF – FINAL, 27/3/2012, SPi 3 Subjects and Consciousness Christopher Peacocke What is it to represent oneself as oneself? And what is the nature of the entity, if any, so represented? These are the two questions to be addressed in this chapter. The first is a question about the nature of intentional content; the second concerns the metaphysics of the self. We should aim for an integrated pair of answers to these questions, an integration that makes it clear why the content elucidated in answering the first question is a way of representing an entity of the sort characterized in answering the second question. In this particular area, I believe that reflection on the question about content yields some important resources for answering the second question. So I will begin with the question about content. I A creature may see something as coming towards it. It may have an apparent memory of being involved in an earlier encounter at a particular location. It may have an apparent action-awareness of moving its head. All these conscious events have a content concerning a subject. The content in question has an intermediate status. The content is more than merely one which concerns the object that is in fact the subject. The content involves less than the full conceptual first person content. Merely seeing something that is in fact the subject includes the case of seeing something that is in fact oneself, say in a mirror, without one’s realizing that it is oneself. That can occur without the object being in any way represented as oneself in the perceptual experi- ence.
    [Show full text]
  • Empiricism and Experience (Henceforth, E&E)
    Equivalence, Reliability, and Convergence: Replies to McDowell, Peacocke, and Neta Anil Gupta University of Pittsburgh I am grateful to John McDowell, Ram Neta, and Christopher Peacocke for their critical attention to my book.1 Their objections and questions are exactly on the mark, and they help me to place the proposals I have made in a clearer light. McDowell and Peacocke challenge fundamental principles I use to motivate my account, and I should address their arguments first. Then I shall turn to Neta’s objection, which concerns a central element of my account. I. McDowell and the Equivalence Constraint McDowell claims that the very first steps leading to the account I offer are deeply flawed and, furthermore, that my account is unattractive when compared to his own version of disjunctivism.2 I want to examine the argument McDowell mounts for these claims. One of my first steps in the book is to accept the following Equivalence constraint. Let the given in an experience e of a subject S be the total rational contribution of e to S’s view of the world. Then the Equivalence constraint is as follows: Equivalence constraint: Experiences that are subjectively identical yield the same given. Consider an experiencing subject S in two possible situations: in one, S undergoes a veridical experience e, say of a pink cube, and rationally arrives at the belief that there is a pink cube; in the other, S undergoes a subjectively identical experience e*, say an illusion, and arrives at the same 1Empiricism and Experience (henceforth, E&E). 2“The Given in Experience: Comment on Gupta.” All parenthetical references to McDowell are to the pages of this paper.
    [Show full text]
  • 1 Explaining Perceptual Entitlement Christopher Peacocke © 2003 New
    Explaining Perceptual Entitlement Christopher Peacocke © 2003 New York University How do perceptual experiences entitle us to form beliefs about the objective world? It is this question, perennial and fundamental, that I will be addressing. I will be offering an answer to the question that brings to bear externalism in the theory of intentional content upon the theory of the normative relation of entitlement. The account draws on some more general considerations about explanation and rationality, considerations applicable in many domains far beyond the mental. If the principles underlying the account are correct, they will apply also to entitlement in some other areas, including beliefs about our own actions. The very first step in addressing our question must, however, involve some clarification of the several levels at which issues about the entitlement relation can be addressed. 1. Entitlement: The Three Levels The three levels at which we may characterize the entitlement relation are levels which we can distinguish for any property or relation. For any property or relation, there is an increase in generality and explanatory power as one proceeds through these three levels of characterization. Level (1). The first of the three levels I distinguish is simply the level of instances or examples of the entitlement relation. So characterizations at this level comprises true statements of the form ‘a thinker in such-and-such circumstances with so-and-so background information is entitled to judge that p’. These examples involve a specification of types of circumstances in which an entitlement exists. The types may concern the thinker’s environment, his other conscious states characterized in terms of content and his general capacities.
    [Show full text]
  • Demonstrative Concepts and Experience Author(S): Sean Dorrance Kelly Source: the Philosophical Review, Vol
    Philosophical Review Demonstrative Concepts and Experience Author(s): Sean Dorrance Kelly Source: The Philosophical Review, Vol. 110, No. 3 (Jul., 2001), pp. 397-420 Published by: Duke University Press on behalf of Philosophical Review Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/2693650 Accessed: 10/11/2008 18:43 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use. Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=duke. Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission. JSTOR is a not-for-profit organization founded in 1995 to build trusted digital archives for scholarship. We work with the scholarly community to preserve their work and the materials they rely upon, and to build a common research platform that promotes the discovery and use of these resources. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. Duke University Press and Philosophical Review are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to The Philosophical Review. http://www.jstor.org ThePhilosophical Review, Vol.
    [Show full text]
  • The Role of Concepts in Perception
    The Role of Concepts in Perception by Kevin Connolly A thesis submitted in conformity with the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy Department of Philosophy University of Toronto © Copyright by Kevin Connolly 2011 The Role of Concepts in Perception Kevin Connolly Doctor of Philosophy Department of Philosophy University of Toronto 2011 Abstract The claim of my dissertation is that some basic concepts are required for perception. Non-basic concepts, we acquire, and I give an account as to how that process changes our perception. Suppose you are looking at the Mona Lisa. It might seem that you can perceive a lot more shades of color and a lot more shapes than for which you possess precise concepts. I argue against this. For every color or shape in appearance you have the ability to categorize it as that color or shape. It’s just that this is done by your sensory system prior to appearance. I argue that empirical studies show this. Blindsighted patients, for instance, are blind in part of their visual field. But they can use color and shape information received through the blind portion. I take this, along with other studies, to show that once you perceive a color or shape, it has already been categorized. I then argue that we perceive only low-level properties like colors and shapes. For in- stance, we don’t perceive high-level kind properties like being a table or being a wren. I do think that wrens or tables might look different to you after you become disposed to recognize them.
    [Show full text]