Three UTILITARIANISM and LIBERALISM

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Three UTILITARIANISM and LIBERALISM Three UTILITARIANISM AND LIBERALISM Harry Lesser 1. Introduction In both ethics and politics, perhaps especially in bioethics, one common basic theory, or at least basic approach, is a combination of utilitarianism and liber- alism. This way of tackling the problems of bioethics is one that many people, myself included, find attractive: in general, one may expect people who esteem the work of Matti Häyry to find it attractive.1 But there is a serious question as to whether this approach, however great its emotional appeal, holds together rationally; and whether the two positions, utilitarianism and liberalism, are even compatible with each other. Even some of the people who hold both posi- tions do so by assigning them to different spheres. A good example would be Ronald Dworkin, whose position seems to be that we should tackle political and ethical questions using a utilitarian approach, except where rights are in- volved, when these “trump” utilitarian considerations.2 In contrast, there is John Stuart Mill’s On Liberty, perhaps the classic liberal text, which defends liberalism precisely on utilitarian grounds, and not on grounds of abstract right.3 This paper seeks to examine, and as a result defend, Mill’s view that maximizing personal freedom also in the long term maximizes utility. It also seeks to say something about the consequences of this for bioethics. 2. Defining Utilitarianism and Liberalism We need to begin with definitions. In general terms utilitarianism is easy to define, as the theory that what is morally right at any given time is that which maximizes happiness or at any rate minimizes suffering. But then the problems start. Do we apply this to actions, to rules for action or to general policies? For the purposes of bioethics we can say that we are essentially concerned with ways of behaving, with systems and policies rather than individual actions. Secondly, do we define happiness in terms of pleasure and pain, or in terms of satisfaction of preferences? Here, I will assume that the theory of utilitarianism has improved as it has developed, and that contemporary utilitarians are right to see satisfaction of preferences as the better option, given that pleasure is not the only thing we want, and pain, however widely defined, not the only thing Harry Lesser - 9789042027404 Downloaded from Brill.com09/26/2021 06:11:45PM via free access 30 HARRY LESSER we seek to avoid. I will also assume that John Harris, for example in his The Value of Life (1985), and others are right to conclude both that the preferences of each person are of equal importance and that certain preferences, notably the desires for life and for liberty, must be privileged and regarded as of su- preme importance, since if anyone is denied life or liberty they are obviously denied the chance of satisfying any other preferences.4 The more controversial question, of whether there are other wants or preferences that should be privi- leged, because they meet the deepest human needs, will be left undecided. Liberalism can obviously mean very different things. In this paper it will be defined as the theory that all adult members of society should be free to participate in decision making, to compete on equal terms, and to take their own decisions in what concerns themselves entirely or primarily: the first and third of these are particularly relevant to bioethics. (It should be noted that here and elsewhere the words “Liberal” and “Liberalism” have the British, not the American, connotation). Given these definitions, the problem to be addressed is the following: Is the liberal model of health care, in which patients and cli- ents are encouraged to make their own decisions as to what treatment they are given, at all consistent with the utilitarian requirement, that the aim of health care must be to maximize healthy functioning, physical and mental, and mini- mize disease and pain? 3. Wants, Needs, and Liberalism Why should liberalism and utilitarianism, thus defined, not be consistent? This is because of two reasons. First, liberalism, as defined above, seems to entail that at least some—not all but some—crucial decisions should be taken ac- cording to the choices of individuals, regardless of other considerations. Liber- alism, in bioethics as elsewhere, is committed to the existence of individual rights, and to holding that these rights hold irrespective of the consequences. Utilitarianism, in contrast, is committed to the view that there are no absolute rights, and that the general welfare should overrule individual wishes and choices. So it seems that for a liberal, health care should be distributed accord- ing to what people want: patients are entitled to the health care that they choose, if it is available. If there is not enough to go round, so to speak (and there never is), it should be a matter of “first come, first served” or, for those liberals who believe in the “free market,” of health care going to those able to pay. In contrast, a utilitarian must logically hold that health care must be dis- tributed according to need, or according to an expert assessment of what will do the most good; and this will clearly produce a different distribution from the “liberal” one. But is liberalism really committed to this? It is committed to holding that medical treatment may not be forced on a person against their will, even if the experts believe it would be beneficial. (The exceptions to this will be discussed Harry Lesser - 9789042027404 Downloaded from Brill.com09/26/2021 06:11:45PM via free access Utilitarianism and Liberalism 31 later on.) But it is not in any way committed to holding that people are entitled to the treatment that they want, regardless of the claims of others whose condi- tion is more serious, or of the assessment by doctors that the treatment will do no good. Nor is it committed to the view that medical care and resources should be distributed according to the ability to pay. There are liberals who hold both these positions, but they are not essential to liberalism. Notably, they are not part of the liberalism of On Liberty. For what Mill holds is that a per- son should not be compelled to do, or refrain from doing, anything “for their own good,” that is, because in the opinion of others it would be to their benefit, or wise, or right; but once their actions harm others there is a duty to inter- vene.5 Moreover, all that is involved here is the idea that one should not inter- fere with what people do when it does no harm to others, or (though Mill him- self explicitly rejects this formulation and its implications) the idea that people have a right not to be interfered with in this sphere. There is nothing to suggest that people have any positive right to be provided with what they want simply because they want it. Least of all is this the case when they do harm, even un- intentional harm, by taking it, as would be the case if they had a “right” to use- less medical treatments, and could take care and resources away from those who would be helped by them. It is also not the case when other people have a greater claim in justice to the resources, for example by being obviously in greater need. One may add that the ideas that medical resources should be distributed according to the wants of the first-comers, or according to the results of the free market, though they are part of one version of liberalism, are not in fact consistent with its basic principle, that freedom should be maximized. The maximization of freedom requires that the more serious obstacles to it be tack- led in preference to the less serious, if one cannot tackle both; in the area of health this means that the more seriously ill take precedence over the less seri- ously ill, even if this means that the wishes of the less seriously ill are tempo- rarily thwarted. It also requires that inequalities of power be limited; and this in its turn may require that there be limitations both on economic inequality and on how the better off may use their money. There may well be an impor- tant place for the free market; but there is no guarantee that every operation of the free market increases overall freedom, or that every limitation on it will diminish freedom. In particular, there are good reasons for thinking that free- dom is best served by distributing health care according to need rather than according to the market.6 4. Utilitarianism and Individual Rights So we may say that one supposed reason why utilitarianism and liberalism are incompatible should be rejected. Liberalism does not require us to put the mere desires of one person above the real needs (those things which are actually Harry Lesser - 9789042027404 Downloaded from Brill.com09/26/2021 06:11:45PM via free access 32 HARRY LESSER essential to life or health) of others; and those who think it does may well be subscribing to an ultimately inconsistent liberal theory. But there is a further problem. Liberalism seems to be committed to individual rights, whether by holding that there are moral as well as legal rights or by holding that there are some things, such as life and liberty, which ought to be legally protected eve- rywhere: even Mill, though he rejects any appeal to liberty as an abstract right, elsewhere endorses the general notion of rights.7 Now this does seem to be incompatible with utilitarianism, for this commits the liberal to holding that some things may not be done to a person whatever the consequences; and the utilitarian is committed to holding that nothing can be excluded totally, if the circumstances warrant it.
Recommended publications
  • The Centrality of Practical Reason: Dworkin and Kant
    The centrality of practical reason: Dworkin and Kant In one of his latest books Justice for Hedgehogs (2011) Ronald Dworkin presents a thorough critique of contemporary ethical discourse. Explicitly his arguments mostly seek to undermine the main premises of metaethics, especially, the assumption that it is possible to think and talk about ethics from a neutral Archimedian position and to find its grounding in scientific or metaphysical facts. Moreover, he aims to present his own position as a specific revolution – a position which questions all the ways of approaching ethics that dominate or influence the field of moral philosophy since modern times, namely Descartes. There have been many attempts to criticize, question and evaluate this critique, its accuracy and extent.1 However, much less effort have been made to properly and comprehensively evaluate the constructive and potential side of Dworkin’s position. The main question that his critique of contemporary ethical discourse raises is ‘How should we approach ethical questions and problems?’ or ‘How should we do moral philosophy?’ Such questions are essential for the discourse itself. They should determine not only the shape and methods, but also the future and raison d’etre of ethical theory as such. Dworkin himself takes Hume to be the inspiration for his revolution. According to Dworkin, Hume’s distinction between fact and value gives us a clear guidance as to how we should proceed in ethical discourse. Dworkin develops this distinction as his main argument that ethics is an independent domain of thought. However, my paper argues, that despite Dworkin’s appeal of Hume, his position cannot be seen as Humean and is much more akin to Kant as there are several substantial conformities between their theories and premises.
    [Show full text]
  • What Equilibrium Concept for Public Goods Provision? I - the Convex Case
    Walras-Lindahl-Wicksell: What equilibrium concept for public goods provision ? I - The convex case Monique Florenzano To cite this version: Monique Florenzano. Walras-Lindahl-Wicksell: What equilibrium concept for public goods provision ? I - The convex case. 2009. halshs-00367867 HAL Id: halshs-00367867 https://halshs.archives-ouvertes.fr/halshs-00367867 Submitted on 12 Mar 2009 HAL is a multi-disciplinary open access L’archive ouverte pluridisciplinaire HAL, est archive for the deposit and dissemination of sci- destinée au dépôt et à la diffusion de documents entific research documents, whether they are pub- scientifiques de niveau recherche, publiés ou non, lished or not. The documents may come from émanant des établissements d’enseignement et de teaching and research institutions in France or recherche français ou étrangers, des laboratoires abroad, or from public or private research centers. publics ou privés. Documents de Travail du Centre d’Economie de la Sorbonne Walras—Lindahl—Wicksell : What equilibrium concept for public goods provision ? I – The convex case Monique FLORENZANO 2009.09 Maison des Sciences Économiques, 106-112 boulevard de L'Hôpital, 75647 Paris Cedex 13 http://ces.univ-paris1.fr/cesdp/CES-docs.htm ISSN : 1955-611X WALRAS–LINDAHL–WICKSELL: WHAT EQUILIBRIUM CONCEPT FOR PUBLIC GOODS PROVISION? I - THE CONVEX CASE MONIQUE FLORENZANO Centre d’Economie de la Sorbonne, CNRS–Universit´eParis 1, monique.fl[email protected] Abstract. Despite the large number of its references, this paper is less a survey than a systematic exposition, in an unifying framework and assuming convexity as well on the consumption side as on the production side, of the different equilibrium concepts elaborated for studying provision of public goods.
    [Show full text]
  • "Suggestions for Further Reading." Censorship Moments: Reading Texts in the History of Censorship and Freedom of Expression
    "Suggestions for Further Reading." Censorship Moments: Reading Texts in the History of Censorship and Freedom of Expression. Ed. Geoff Kemp. London: Bloomsbury Academic, 2015. 195–202. Textual Moments in the History of Political Thought. Bloomsbury Collections. Web. 26 Sep. 2021. <>. Downloaded from Bloomsbury Collections, www.bloomsburycollections.com, 26 September 2021, 01:37 UTC. Copyright © Geoff Kemp and contributors 2015. You may share this work for non-commercial purposes only, provided you give attribution to the copyright holder and the publisher, and provide a link to the Creative Commons licence. Suggestions for Further Reading Given the substantial quantity of writing on most of the thinkers and many of the works covered in this volume, the following list is necessarily highly selective. For each work an attempt has been made to include a readily available reliable text in English (sometimes available online), in some cases a scholarly edition, and several works which help to contextualize the principal text and scholarly discussion of it. Plutarch’s Life of Cato Plutarch, ‘Marcus Cato’, in Plutarch’s Lives, accessible at www.perseus.tufts.edu/hopper/ text?doc=Perseus%3atext%3a2008.01.0013 [accessed 18 May 2014]. Alan E. Astin, Cato the Censor (Oxford: At the Clarendon Press, 1978). Arlene W. Saxonhouse, Free Speech and Athenian Democracy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2006). Robin Waterfield, Why Socrates Died: Dispelling the Myths (New York: Norton, 2009). Dana Villa, Socratic Citizenship (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2001). Tacitus’s Annals Tacitus, The Annals, translated by A.J. Woodman (Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company, 2004). Shadi Bartsch, Actors in the Audience: Theatricality and Doublespeak from Nero to Hadrian (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1998).
    [Show full text]
  • Public Goods in Everyday Life
    Public Goods in Everyday Life By June Sekera A GDAE Teaching Module on Social and Environmental Issues in Economics Global Development And Environment Institute Tufts University Medford, MA 02155 http://ase.tufts.edu/gdae Copyright © June Sekera Reproduced by permission. Copyright release is hereby granted for instructors to copy this module for instructional purposes. Students may also download the reading directly from https://ase.tufts.edu/gdae Comments and feedback from course use are welcomed: Global Development And Environment Institute Tufts University Somerville, MA 02144 http://ase.tufts.edu/gdae E-mail: [email protected] PUBLIC GOODS IN EVERYDAY LIFE “The history of civilization is a history of public goods... The more complex the civilization the greater the number of public goods that needed to be provided. Ours is far and away the most complex civilization humanity has ever developed. So its need for public goods – and goods with public goods aspects, such as education and health – is extraordinarily large. The institutions that have historically provided public goods are states. But it is unclear whether today’s states can – or will be allowed to – provide the goods we now demand.”1 -Martin Wolf, Financial Times 1 Martin Wolf, “The World’s Hunger for Public Goods”, Financial Times, January 24, 2012. 2 PUBLIC GOODS IN EVERYDAY LIFE TABLE OF CONTENTS 1. INTRODUCTION .........................................................................................................4 1.1 TEACHING OBJECTIVES: .....................................................................................................................
    [Show full text]
  • A Critique of John Stuart Mill Chris Daly
    Southern Illinois University Carbondale OpenSIUC Honors Theses University Honors Program 5-2002 The Boundaries of Liberalism in a Global Era: A Critique of John Stuart Mill Chris Daly Follow this and additional works at: http://opensiuc.lib.siu.edu/uhp_theses Recommended Citation Daly, Chris, "The Boundaries of Liberalism in a Global Era: A Critique of John Stuart Mill" (2002). Honors Theses. Paper 131. This Dissertation/Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the University Honors Program at OpenSIUC. It has been accepted for inclusion in Honors Theses by an authorized administrator of OpenSIUC. For more information, please contact [email protected]. r The Boundaries of Liberalism in a Global Era: A Critique of John Stuart Mill Chris Daly May 8, 2002 r ABSTRACT The following study exanunes three works of John Stuart Mill, On Liberty, Utilitarianism, and Three Essays on Religion, and their subsequent effects on liberalism. Comparing the notion on individual freedom espoused in On Liberty to the notion of the social welfare in Utilitarianism, this analysis posits that it is impossible for a political philosophy to have two ultimate ends. Thus, Mill's liberalism is inherently flawed. As this philosophy was the foundation of Mill's progressive vision for humanity that he discusses in his Three Essays on Religion, this vision becomes paradoxical as well. Contending that the neo-liberalist global economic order is the contemporary parallel for Mill's religion of humanity, this work further demonstrates how these philosophical flaws have spread to infect the core of globalization in the 21 st century as well as their implications for future international relations.
    [Show full text]
  • Public Goods for Economic Development
    Printed in Austria Sales No. E.08.II.B36 V.08-57150—November 2008—1,000 ISBN 978-92-1-106444-5 Public goods for economic development PUBLIC GOODS FOR ECONOMIC DEVELOPMENT FOR ECONOMIC GOODS PUBLIC This publication addresses factors that promote or inhibit successful provision of the four key international public goods: fi nancial stability, international trade regime, international diffusion of technological knowledge and global environment. Each of these public goods presents global challenges and potential remedies to promote economic development. Without these goods, developing countries are unable to compete, prosper or attract capital from abroad. The undersupply of these goods may affect prospects for economic development, threatening global economic stability, peace and prosperity. The need for public goods provision is also recognized by the Millennium Development Goals, internationally agreed goals and targets for knowledge, health, governance and environmental public goods. Because of the characteristics of public goods, leaving their provision to market forces will result in their under provision with respect to socially desirable levels. Coordinated social actions are therefore necessary to mobilize collective response in line with socially desirable objectives and with areas of comparative advantage and value added. International public goods for development will grow in importance over the coming decades as globalization intensifi es. Corrective policies hinge on the goods’ properties. There is no single prescription; rather, different kinds of international public goods require different kinds of policies and institutional arrangements. The Report addresses the nature of these policies and institutions using the modern principles of collective action. UNITED NATIONS INDUSTRIAL DEVELOPMENT ORGANIZATION Vienna International Centre, P.O.
    [Show full text]
  • Neoliberalism and the Public Good in Higher Education
    BACHELOR THESIS CTP 01.11.2015 Neoliberalism and the Public Good in Higher Education Name: Svenja Mielke Student Number: 930119571030 Chair Group: Law and Governance Supervisors: Michiel Köhne and Elisabet Rasch Wageningen UR *Cover picture by Van Nispen (2015). Contents Contents ..................................................................................................................................................... 1 Foreword .................................................................................................................................................... 2 Abstract ...................................................................................................................................................... 2 Introduction ................................................................................................................................................ 3 Problem Statement ...................................................................................................................... 4 Methods....................................................................................................................................... 6 Chapter 1. The Public Good and Neoliberalism ........................................................................................ 7 The Public Good ......................................................................................................................... 7 Neoliberalism .............................................................................................................................
    [Show full text]
  • The Restless Liberalism of Alexis De Tocqueville
    FILOZOFIA ___________________________________________________________________________Roč. 72, 2017, č. 9 THE RESTLESS LIBERALISM OF ALEXIS DE TOCQUEVILLE JAKUB TLOLKA, London School of Economics and Political Science, London, UK TLOLKA, J.: The Restless Liberalism of Alexis de Tocqueville FILOZOFIA, 72, No. 9, 2017, pp. 736-747 This essay attempts to contextualise the purported novelty of Alexis de Tocqueville’s particular brand of liberalism. It regards the author not as an heir or precursor to any given political tradition, but rather as a compelled syncretist whose primary philosophical concern was the moral significance of the democratic age. It suggests that Tocqueville devised his ‘new political science’ with a keen view to the existential implications of modernity. In order to support that suggestion, the essay explores the genealogy of Tocqueville’s moral and political thought and draws a relation between his analysis of democracy and his personal experience of modernity. Keywords: A. de Tocqueville – Modernity – Liberalism – Inquiétude – Religion Introduction. Relatively few authors in the history of political thought have produced an intellectual legacy of such overarching resonance as Alexis de Tocqueville. Even fewer, perhaps, have so persistently eluded ordinary analytical and exegetical frameworks, presenting to each astute observer a face so nuanced as to preclude serious interpretive consensus. As writes Lakoff (Lakoff 1998), ‘disagreement over textual interpretation in the study of political thought is not uncommon’. However, ‘it usually arises around those who left writings of a patently divergent character’ (p. 437). When we thus consider the ‘extraordinarily coherent and consistent nature’ of Alexis de Tocqueville’s political philosophy, it appears somewhat odd that the academic consensus surrounding that author relates almost exclusively to the grandeur of his intellectual achievement (Lukacs 1959, 6).
    [Show full text]
  • John Stuart Mill's Evaluations of Poetry
    JOHN STUART MILL'S EVALUATIONS OF POETRY AND THEIR INFLUENCE UPON HIS INTELLECTUAL DEVELOPMENT by MILLO RUNDLE THOMPSON SHAW B.A., University of British Columbia, 1949 A THESIS SUBMITTED IN PARTIAL FULFILMENT OF THE REQUIREMENTS FOR THE DEGREE OF MASTER OF ARTS in the Department of English We accept this thesis as conforming to the required standard THE UNIVERSITY OF BRITISH COLUMBIA April, 1971 In presenting this thesis in partial fulfilment of the requirements for an advanced degree at the University of British Columbia, I agree that the Library shall make it freely available for reference and study. I further agree that permission for extensive copying of this thesis for scholarly purposes may be granted by the Head of my Department or by his representatives. It is understood that copying or publication of this thesis for financial gain shall not be allowed without my written permission. Department of ENGLISH The University of British Columbia Vancouver 8, Canada Date October 1970 i JOHN STUART MILL'S EVALUATIONS OF POETRY AND THEIR INFLUENCE UPON HIS INTELLECTUAL DEVELOPMENT ABSTRACT The education of John Stuart Mill was one of the most unusual ever planned or experienced. Beginning with his learning Greek at the age of three and con• tinuing without a break of any kind to the age of four• teen, it constituted an almost total control of Mill's every waking activity, with the important exception of his visit to France at fourteen, until his appoint• ment to the East India Company in 1823. It emphasized the "tabula rasa" theory, the effect of external cir• cumstances on the developing mind, Hartley's Associa- tionist theory, and the judicious use of the Utilitarian theories of the "pleasure-pain" principle.
    [Show full text]
  • Market Failure Guide
    Market failure guide A guide to categorising market failures for government policy development and evaluation industry.nsw.gov.au Published by NSW Department of Industry PUB17/509 Market failure guide—A guide to categorising market failures for government policy development and evaluation An external academic review of this guide was undertaken by prominent economists in November 2016 This guide is consistent with ‘NSW Treasury (2017) NSW Government Guide to Cost-Benefit Analysis, TPP 17-03, Policy and Guidelines Paper’ First published December 2017 More information Program Evaluation Unit [email protected] www.industry.nsw.gov.au © State of New South Wales through Department of Industry, 2017. This publication is copyright. You may download, display, print and reproduce this material provided that the wording is reproduced exactly, the source is acknowledged, and the copyright, update address and disclaimer notice are retained. To copy, adapt, publish, distribute or commercialise any of this publication you will need to seek permission from the Department of Industry. Disclaimer: The information contained in this publication is based on knowledge and understanding at the time of writing July 2017. However, because of advances in knowledge, users are reminded of the need to ensure that the information upon which they rely is up to date and to check the currency of the information with the appropriate officer of the Department of Industry or the user’s independent advisor. Market failure guide Contents Executive summary
    [Show full text]
  • The Use of Philosophers by the Supreme Court Neomi Raot
    A Backdoor to Policy Making: The Use of Philosophers by the Supreme Court Neomi Raot The Supreme Court's decisions in Vacco v Quill' and Wash- ington v Glucksberg2 held that a state can ban assisted suicide without violating the Due Process or Equal Protection Clauses of the Fourteenth Amendment. In these high profile cases, six phi- losophers filed an amicus brief ("Philosophers'Brief') that argued for the recognition of a constitutional right to die.3 Although the brief was written by six of the most prominent American philoso- phers-Ronald Dworkin, Thomas Nagel, Robert Nozick, John Rawls, Thomas Scanlon, and Judith Jarvis Thomson-the Court made no mention of the brief in unanimously reaching the oppo- site conclusion.4 In light of the Court's recent failure to engage philosophical arguments, this Comment examines the conditions under which philosophy does and should affect judicial decision making. These questions are relevant in considering the proper role of the Court in controversial political questions and are central to a recent de- bate focusing on whether the law can still be considered an autonomous discipline that relies only on traditional legal sources. Scholars concerned with law and economics and critical legal studies have argued that the law is no longer autonomous, but rather that it does and should draw on many external sources in order to resolve legal disputes. Critics of this view have main- tained that legal reasoning is distinct from other disciplines, and that the law has and should maintain its own methods, conven- tions, and conclusions. This Comment follows the latter group of scholars, and ar- gues that the Court should, as it did in the right-to-die cases, stay clear of philosophy and base its decisions on history, precedent, and a recognition of the limits of judicial authority.
    [Show full text]
  • The Contradiction of Classical Liberalism and Libertarianism
    The contradiction of classical liberalism and libertarianism blogs.lse.ac.uk/businessreview/2017/02/01/the-contradiction-of-classical-liberalism-and-libertarianism/ 2/1/2017 A standard assumption in policy analyses and political debates is that classical liberal or libertarian views represent a radical alternative to a progressive or egalitarian agenda. In the political arena, classical liberalism and libertarianism often inform the policy agenda of centre-right and far- right parties. They underpin laissez-faire policies and reject any redistributive action, including welfare state provisions and progressive taxation. This is motivated by a fundamental belief in the value of personal autonomy and protection from (unjustified) external interference, including from the state. It is difficult to overestimate the philosophical and political relevance of classical liberalism and libertarianism. President Trump’s proposal to repeal the “Affordable Care Act (Obamacare)”, for example, is clearly inspired by a libertarian philosophical outlook whereby “No person should be required to buy insurance unless he or she wants to” (Healthcare Reform to Make America Great Again ). More generally, in the last four decades the political consensus, and the spectrum of policy proposals and outcomes, has significantly moved in a less interventionist, more laissez faire direction. The centrality of classical liberal and libertarian views has been such that the historical period after the end of the 1970s – following the election of Margaret Thatcher in the UK and Ronald Reagan in the US – has come to be known as the “Neoliberal era”. Yet the very coherence of the classical liberal and libertarian view of society, and its consistency with the fundamental tenets of modern democracies, have been questioned.
    [Show full text]