Teaching As Abductive Reasoning: the Role of Argumentation Chrysi Rapanta
Total Page:16
File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb
Document generated on 09/27/2021 12:43 p.m. Informal Logic Teaching as Abductive Reasoning: The Role of Argumentation Chrysi Rapanta Volume 38, Number 2, 2018 Article abstract The view that argumentation is a desired reasoning practice in the classroom is URI: https://id.erudit.org/iderudit/1057041ar well reported in the literature. Nonetheless, it is still not clear what type of DOI: https://doi.org/10.22329/il.v38i2.4849 reasoning supports classroom argumentation. The paper discusses abductive reasoning as the most adequate for students’ arguments to emerge in a See table of contents classroom discussion. Abductive reasoning embraces the idea of plausibility and defeasibility of both the premises and the conclusion. As such, teachers’ role becomes the one of guiding students through formulating relevant Publisher(s) hypotheses and selecting the most plausible one according to criteria. Argumentation schemes are proposed as useful tools in this process. Informal Logic ISSN 0824-2577 (print) 2293-734X (digital) Explore this journal Cite this article Rapanta, C. (2018). Teaching as Abductive Reasoning: The Role of Argumentation. Informal Logic, 38(2), 293–311. https://doi.org/10.22329/il.v38i2.4849 Copyright (c), 2018 Chrysi Rapanta This document is protected by copyright law. Use of the services of Érudit (including reproduction) is subject to its terms and conditions, which can be viewed online. https://apropos.erudit.org/en/users/policy-on-use/ This article is disseminated and preserved by Érudit. Érudit is a non-profit inter-university consortium of the Université de Montréal, Université Laval, and the Université du Québec à Montréal. Its mission is to promote and disseminate research. https://www.erudit.org/en/ Teaching as Abductive Reasoning: The Role of Argumentation CHRYSI RAPANTA Reasoning and Argumentation Lab Institute of Philosophy Universidade Nova de Lisboa (IFILNOVA) Lisbon, Portugal [email protected] Abstract: The view that argumenta- Résumé: L'idée que l'argumentation tion is a desired reasoning practice in est une pratique de raisonnement the classroom is well reported in the souhaitée en classe est bien documen- literature. Nonetheless, it is still not tée dans la littérature. Néanmoins, il clear what type of reasoning supports n'est toujours pas clair quel type de classroom argumentation. The paper raisonnement soutient l'argumentation discusses abductive reasoning as the en classe. Dans cet article on discute most adequate for students’ arguments du raisonnement abductif comme étant to emerge in a classroom discussion. le plus adéquat pour que les arguments Abductive reasoning embraces the des élèves émergent dans une discus- idea of plausibility and defeasibility of sion en classe. Le raisonnement both the premises and the conclusion. abductif emploie l'idée de plausibilité As such, the teachers’ role becomes et de la révocabilité des prémisses et one of guiding students through de la conclusion. En tant que tel, le formulating relevant hypotheses and rôle des enseignants consiste à guider selecting the most plausible one les élèves à formuler des hypothèses according to criteria. Argumentation pertinentes et à sélectionner le plus schemes are proposed as useful tools plausible selon des critères. Les in this process. schèmes d'argumentation sont propo- sés comme des outils utiles dans ce processus. Keywords: abductive reasoning; argumentation; education; teachers 1. Introduction The relation between argumentation and education has been vastly explored during the last decades (Rapanta and Macagno 2016; Chinn 2006; Clark and Sampson et al. 2007; Erduran and Jimenez- © Chrysi Rapanta. Informal Logic, Vol. 38, No. 2 (2018), pp. 293-311. 294 Rapanta Aleixandre 2008; Muller-Mirza and Perret-Clermont 2009). Much emphasis has been placed on the types of skills or strategies that both teachers and students may adopt for constructive dialogical argumentation in the classroom to take place (Rapanta, Garcia-Mila and Gilabert 2013; Felton, Garcia-Mila, et al. 2015; Kuhn, Hem- berger and Khait 2014). Although argumentation and reasoning are not equivalent, their relation is indisputable due to the necessary condition that any argument, as a product of argumentation, shall be based on inference, as a product of reasoning (Mercier and Sperber 2011; Voss and Means 1991). The present essay focuses on this three-fold relationship be- tween reasoning, education, and argumentation, providing well- established theories of reasoning and argumentation as the basis of justification for a pedagogical mode of teaching based on logical inferences. Moreover, it is claimed that the nature of these infer- ences is mainly abductive, and their structure may be sought for in existing reasoning representations, such as the one provided by the so-called argumentation schemes (Walton 1996; Walton Reed and Macagno 2008). 2. Abductive reasoning In a definition attributed to the philosopher Charles Peirce, cited in (Psillos 2011), “reasoning is a process in which the reasoner is conscious that a judgment, the conclusion, is determined by other judgment or judgments, the premises, according to a general habit of thought” (pp. 121-122). This general habit of thought, or rule of reasoning, must be truth-conducive, and truth must be based on knowledge and justification. In general, there are two ways in which a process of reasoning can confer justification on a belief. The first is by making the case that if the premises are true, the conclusion must be true. The second is by rendering a belief plausible and thus making it available for further testing (Psillos 2011). According to Peirce (1878), only the second way, which is called abduction or abductive reasoning, may produce new knowledge, and thus may be related to scientific reasoning. © Chrysi Rapanta. Informal Logic, Vol. 38, No. 2 (2018), pp. 293-311. Teaching as abductive reasoning 295 The difference between deduction, induction and abduction is well illustrated in the example given by Preyer and Mans cited in (Walton 2001) as presented in Table 1. Deductive Inductive Abductive Suppose a bag contains Suppose you do not Suppose you find a red only red marbles, and know the color of the marble in the vicinity you take one out. You marbles in the bag, and of a bag of red marbles. may infer that the you take one out and it is You may infer that the marble is red. red. You may infer that marble is from the bag. all the marbles in the bag are red. Table 1. Distinction between deductive, inductive and ab- ductive reasoning (Walton 2001) For Walton (2001), abduction is different than deduction and induction because the conclusion is just a hypothesis, a best guess, based on the given knowledge and evidence at that moment. For this reason, abductive inferences are defeasible, meaning that they are “subject to retraction if further investigation of the facts in the case shows that another of the alternative explanations is ‘better’” (p. 145). Moreover, abductive reasoning resembles a continuous deliberation process that needs to be open to revision as new evi- dence of the factual circumstances of the case enters into the calcu- lations. Abductive reasoning is similar to the reasoning of a detec- tive looking for the best data that would give the best explanation possible. The decision for what counts as the best explanation in a given context is based on the criterion of plausibility, rather than possibility, as in deductive inferences, or probability, as in most inductive inferences (Walton, 2001). According to the general definition of reasoning stated in the very beginning of this article, any inference must lead to some type of truth, or better said, true knowledge. In both deductive and inductive inferences, although the knowledge is true as it refers to facts, it is not novel knowledge, and as such, it does not require further justification. On the other hand, abductive reasoning is the only one that leads to new knowledge, and as such it needs further justification, using deductive, inductive or even additional abduc- © Chrysi Rapanta. Informal Logic, Vol. 38, No. 2 (2018), pp. 293-311. 296 Rapanta tive reasoning. In this sense, abductive reasoning is the most complete type of reasoning, including all types of inferences that are possible to emerge both in everyday life and in science. First of all, it relates to deduction, as abductive reasoning is mainly about reasoning from effect to cause. However, what counts as cause in abductive reasoning is much broader than a deductive cause, be- cause they are causes selected based on hypotheses (Josephson and Josephson 1996). Second, abduction may include induction, be- cause it is through abductive reasoning that the claim that “all A´s are B´s” is considered a better, more plausible hypothesis based on the given evidence that “at least generally A’s are B’s”1 (p. 19). For these reasons, abductive reasoning has been highly valued as a different type of reasoning which: May be used as a general umbrella for all types of plausible inferences when it comes to arriving at the best explanation for a phenomenon or event, may produce novel knowledge, and may represent scientific reasoning at least when it comes to the discovery phase (Josephson and Josephson 1996; Peirce 1931; Walton 2005). However, its relation to and use for teaching has not been explicitly brought to light. Given the increasing evidence that students’ quality of argumentative reasoning is generally low (Rapanta and Walton 2016; Glassner and Schwarz 2007; Kuhn, Goh et al. 2008), any attempt to apply knowledge from the field of reasoning and argumentation theory in education is extremely valuable (Rapanta and Macagno 2016). This is most pertinent to current society, as life situations become more and more fluid and ask for the consideration of multiple factors before arriving at a conclusion or a decision. The goal of this article is to show that the use of reasoning in pedagogical contexts, especially in the form of scientific argumen- tation, resembles abductive reasoning more than any other type of reasoning described so far.