CV and Publications, Leitgeb Hannes (July 2021)

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

CV and Publications, Leitgeb Hannes (July 2021) Curriculum Vitae and List of Publications Hannes Leitgeb July 2021 Department Address Chair of Logic and Philosophy of Language, Alexander von Humboldt Professor, and Founder/Co-Director of the Munich Center for Mathematical Philosophy Faculty of Philosophy, Philosophy of Science and the Study of Religion Ludwig-Maximilians-University Munich Ludwigstr. 31 D-80539 Munich Germany Phone: (+49)(0)89 2180 6171 Email: [email protected] Personal Information Date of birth: 26/06/72.1 Nationality: Austrian. Married (to Conny). Two children (Sebastian and Victoria). 1All dates are stated in dd/mm/yy format. 1 Areas of Specialization Logic, Epistemology, Philosophy of Language, Philosophy of Science, Philosophy of Mathematics, Metaphysics, Cognitive Science. Areas of Competence History of Logical Empiricism, Carnap, Quine. Education Ph.D. (with distinction), Philosophy, University of Salzburg, 02/07/01 Dissertation: Inference on the Low Level Committee: Gerhard Schurz (D¨usseldorf/Salzburg),Georg Dorn (Salzburg). Ph.D. (with distinction), Mathematics, University of Salzburg, 09/07/98 Dissertation: Truth as Translation Committee: Johannes Czermak (Salzburg), Peter Woodruff (UC Irvine). M.Sc. (with distinction), Mathematics, University of Salzburg, 20/02/97 Thesis: Another Approach to Many-Valued Logic Supervisor: Johannes Czermak (Salzburg). Academic Positions and Offers Offers from the Department of Philosophy, Rutgers University, and from the Department of Philosophy, University of California at Davis, November 2017. Declined. Chair of Logic and Philosophy of Language, and Alexander von Humboldt Professor, Faculty of Philosophy, Ludwig-Maximilians University Munich. Founder & (Co-)Director of Munich Center for Mathematical Philosophy (01/10/10{). Offers from the Department of Philosophy, Stanford University, and from the Faculty of Philosophy, University of Groningen, (both Full Professorships), November 2009. Declined. Offer from the Logic and Philosophy of Science Department, University of California at Irvine (Full Professorship), February 2009. Declined. Professor, Departments of Philosophy & Mathematics, Univ. of Bristol (01/08/07{30/09/10). Reader, Departments of Philosophy & Mathematics, University of Bristol (01/09/05{31/07/07). Offers from Stanford University (tenure-track Associate Professorship), declined, and the University of Bristol (tenured Readership), March 2005. 2 Assistant Professor, Department of Philosophy, University of Salzburg (13/10/02{31/08/05). Post-doctoral scholar, Department of Philosophy, University of Salzburg. Project: Logic and Cognitive Science (May 1999{August 2002). Post-doctoral scholar, Department of Mathematics, University of Salzburg. Project: Formal Theories of Truth (February 1999{April 1999). Research Assistant, Department of Forensic Neuropsychiatry, University of Salzburg. Project: Logical Methods in Biocybernetic Brain Research (1995{1997). Visiting Appointments Visiting Professor, Department of Philosophy, University of D¨usseldorf (February 2009{July 2009). Visiting scholar, Department of Philosophy & CSLI, Stanford University (September 2004{August 2005). Honors and Awards Philosophy Students' Award for Excellence in Teaching, Faculty of Philosophy, Philosophy of Science and Study of Religion, LMU Munich, July 2020. Philosophy Students' Award for Excellence in Teaching, Faculty of Philosophy, Philosophy of Science and Study of Religion, LMU Munich, July 2018. Member of Leopoldina, Deutsche Akademie der Naturforscher, 2016. Philosophy Students' Award for Excellence in Teaching, Faculty of Philosophy, Philosophy of Science and Study of Religion, LMU Munich, July 2015. Article \A Lottery Paradox for Counterfactuals Without Agglomeration" chosen for The Philosopher's Annual Vol. 34, 2014. Member of Academia Europaea, 2014. Philosophy Students' Award for Excellence in Teaching, Faculty of Philosophy, Philosophy of Science and Study of Religion, LMU Munich, July 2012. Member of Acad´emieInternationale de Philosophie des Sciences, 2011. 3 Article \An Objective Justification of Bayesianism II" (with R. Pettigrew) chosen for The Philosopher's Annual Vol. 30, 2010. Alexander von Humboldt Professorship (EUR 3,500,000), Alexander von Humboldt Foundation, Germany, February 2010. Friedrich Wilhelm Bessel Research Award (EUR 45,000), Alexander von Humboldt Foundation, Germany, November 2007. Philip Leverhulme Prize ($ 70,000), Leverhulme Trust, UK, October 2007. University of Bristol candidate for the Leverhulme Research Leadership Award Competition 2007, Leverhulme Trust, UK. Finalist of the G¨odelCentenary Young Scholars Competition (organized and sponsored by the Kurt G¨odelSociety and the John Templeton Foun- dation), Vienna, April 2006. Erwin Schr¨odingerFellowship ($ 36,200), Project: \Carnap's Logischer Aufbau Revived", Austrian Research Fund (J2344-G03), September 2004{August 2005. Austrian Research Fund Post-Doctoral Fellowship, in the Special Re- search Project \Theorien- und Paradigmenpluralismus" (SFB F012), May 1999{August 2002. Austrian Research Fund Post-Doctoral Fellowship (P13431-MAT), February 1999{April 1999. Research Scholarship of the Medical Research Society Salzburg, 1995{1997. M.Sc. Thesis Research Prize (“F¨orderungspreis"), Department of Mathematics, University of Salzburg, December 1994. Publications Books: 1. In preparation: Reviving Logical Empiricism. 2. In preparation: Logik f¨urPhilosophen: Eine Einf¨uhrungin die klassi- sche Aussagen- und Pr¨adikatenlogik (with A. Hieke). 334 pp. I use the draft for my Logic 1 lecture in Munich. 4 3. The Stability of Belief. How Rational Belief Coheres with Probability. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2017, 384 pp. 4. Reduction { Abstraction { Analysis (edited, with A. Hieke), Frankfurt a. M.: Ontos Press, 2009, 414 pp. 5. Reduction. Between the Mind and the Brain (edited, with A. Hieke), Frankfurt a. M.: Ontos Press, 2009, 216 pp. 6. Philosophy of Mathematics: 5 Questions (edited, with V. Hendricks), Automatic Press, 2007, 342 pp. 7. Inference on the Low Level. An Investigation into Deduction, Non- monotonic Reasoning, and the Philosophy of Cognition, Dordrecht: Kluwer, Applied Logic Series, 2004, 384 pp. 8. Logik und Grundlagen der Mathematik, Salzburg: Osterreichische¨ Hoch- sch¨ulerschaft, 2004, 83 pp. (based on lectures given to the Department of Mathematics, University of Salzburg, in the summer semester 2002). Journal Articles: 1. \On Non-Eliminative Structuralism. Unlabeled Graphs as a Case Study (Part B)", to appear in Philosophia Mathematica, 31 pages. 2. \A Structural Justification of Probabilism: From Partition Invariance to Subjective Probability", Philosophy of Science 88/2 (2021), 341{365. 3. \On Non-Eliminative Structuralism. Unlabeled Graphs as a Case Study (Part A)", Philosophia Mathematica 28/3 (2020), 317{346. 4. \Why Pure Mathematical Truths Are Metaphysically Necessary: A Set-theoretic Explanation", textitSynthese 197 (2020), 3113{3120. 5. \HYPE: A System of Hyperintensional Logic (With an Application to Semantic Paradoxes)", Journal of Philosophical Logic 48/2 (2019), 305{405. 6. \Probability for the Revision Theory of Truth" (with C. Campbell- Moore and L. Horsten), Journal of Philosophical Logic 48 (2019), 87{ 112. 5 7. \Imaging All the People", Episteme 14/4 (2017), 463{479. 8. \The Humean Thesis on Belief", Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society of Philosophy 89/1 (2015), 143{185. 9. \A Lottery Paradox for Counterfactuals Without Agglomeration", Phi- losophy and Phenomenological Research 89/3 (2014), 605{636. 10. \The Review Paradox. A Note on the Diachronic Costs of Not Closing Rational Belief Under Conjunction", Nous 48/4 (2014), 781{793. 11. \A Way Out of the Preface Paradox?", Analysis 74/1 (2014), 11{15. 12. \The Stability Theory of Belief", The Philosophical Review 123/2 (2014), 131{171. 13. \Reducing Belief Simpliciter to Degrees of Belief", Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 164 (2013), 1338{1389. 14. \Scientific Philosophy, Mathematical Philosophy, and All That", Metaphi- losophy 44/3 (2013), 267{275. 15. \Criteria of Identity, Strong and Wrong", British Journal for the Phi- losophy of Science 64/1 (2013), 61{68. 16. \Revision Revisited" (with L. Horsten, G. Leigh, P. Welch), Review of Symbolic Logic 5/4 (2012), 642{664. 17. \How Serious is the Paradox of Serious Possibility?" (with S. Duca), Mind 121/481 (2012), 1{36. 18. \A Probabilistic Semantics for Counterfactuals. Part B", Review of Symbolic Logic 5 (2012), 85{121. 19. \A Probabilistic Semantics for Counterfactuals. Part A", Review of Symbolic Logic 5 (2012), 16{84. 20. \God − Moore = Ramsey. (A Reply to Chalmers and H´ajek)", Topoi 30/1 (2011), 47{51. 21. \New Life for Carnap's Aufbau?", Synthese 180/2 (2011), 265{299. 6 22. \Logic in General Philosophy of Science: Old Things and New Things", Synthese (2011) 179/2, 339{350. (The paper will also appear in: V. Hendricks et al. (eds.), PHIBOOK, Yearbook of Philosophical Logic, Copenhagen: Automatic Press.) 23. \On the Ramsey Test Without Triviality", Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 51/1 (2010), 21{54. 24. \Logic and Philosophy of Mathematics", Journal of the Indian Coun- cil of Philosophical Research 27/2 (2010), special issue on Logic and Philosophy Today, A. Gupta and J. van Benthem (eds.), 129{154. 25. \Sleeping Beauty and Eternal Recurrence", Analysis 70/2 (2010), 203{ 205. 26. \An Objective Justification of Bayesianism II: The Consequences of Minimizing Inaccuracy" (with R. Pettigrew), Philosophy of Science 77/2 (2010), 236{272. 27. \An Objective Justification of Bayesianism I: Measuring
Recommended publications
  • 1 Psychological Operationisms at Harvard: Skinner, Boring, And
    [Forthcoming in Journal of the History of the Behavioral Sciences] Psychological operationisms at Harvard: Skinner, Boring, and Stevens Sander Verhaegh Tilburg University Abstract: Contemporary discussions about operational definition often hark back to Stanley Smith Stevens’ classic papers on psychological operationism (1935ab). Still, he was far from the only psychologist to call for conceptual hygiene. Some of Stevens’ direct colleagues at I would like to thank Julie Vargas, anonymous referees for the Journal of the History of the Behavioral Sciences, and the staff at the Harvard University Archives for their help with this project. Drafts of this paper were presented at the 2019 conference of the History of Science Society (Utrecht University) and the 2019 conference of the Canadian Society for the History and Philosophy of Science (University of British Columbia). I would like to thank the audiences at both events for their valuable suggestions. This research is funded by The Netherlands Organisation for Scientific Research (grant 275–20–064). My archival research was funded by a Kristeller-Popkin Travel Fellowship from the Journal of the History of Philosophy, by a Rodney G. Dennis Fellowship in the Study of Manuscripts from Houghton Library, and a travel grant from the Evert Willem Beth Foundation. Correspondence concerning this paper should be addressed to Tilburg University, Department of Philosophy, Warandelaan 2, 5037AB, Tilburg, The Netherlands or to [email protected]. 1 Harvard⎯ most notably B. F. Skinner and E. G. Boring⎯ were also actively applying Bridgman’s conceptual strictures to the study of mind and behavior. In this paper, I shed new light on the history of operationism by reconstructing the Harvard debates about operational definition in the years before Stevens published his seminal articles.
    [Show full text]
  • Prime Numbers and Implication Free Reducts of Mvn-Chains.Pdf
    SYSMICS2019 Syntax Meets Semantics Amsterdam, The Netherlands 21-25 January 2019 Institute for Logic, Language and Computation University of Amsterdam SYSMICS 2019 The international conference “Syntax meet Semantics 2019” (SYSMICS 2019) will take place from 21 to 25 January 2019 at the University of Amsterdam, The Nether- lands. This is the closing conference of the European Marie Sk lodowska-Curie Rise project Syntax meets Semantics – Methods, Interactions, and Connections in Sub- structural logics, which unites more than twenty universities from Europe, USA, Brazil, Argentina, South Africa, Australia, Japan, and Singapore. Substructural logics are formal reasoning systems that refine classical logic by weakening structural rules in a Gentzen-style sequent calculus. Traditionally, non- classical logics have been investigated using proof-theoretic and algebraic methods. In recent years, combined approaches have started to emerge, thus establishing new links with various branches of non-classical logic. The program of the SYSMICS conference focuses on interactions between syntactic and semantic methods in substructural and other non-classical logics. The scope of the conference includes but is not limited to algebraic, proof-theoretic and relational approaches towards the study of non-classical logics. This booklet consists of the abstracts of SYSMICS 2019 invited lectures and contributed talks. In addition, it also features the abstract of the SYSMICS 2019 Public Lecture, on the interaction of logic and artificial intelligence. We thank all authors, members of the Programme and Organising Committees and reviewers of SYSMICS 2019 for their contribution. Apart from the generous financial support by the SYSMICS project, we would like to acknowledge the sponsorship by the Evert Willem Beth Foundation and the Association for Symbolic Logic.
    [Show full text]
  • (01.01.2020- 31.12.2020) Munich Center for Mathematical Philosophy
    Academic Report for 2020 (01.01.2020- 31.12.2020) Since 2016 we provide access to more than 650 video recordings on virtually any kind of philosophical problem. Munich Center for Mathematical Philosophy 3. MCMP @ Facebook Prof. DDr. Hannes Leitgeb & Prof. Dr. Stephan Hartmann The MCMP regularly posts news and events on Facebook. Currently January 30, 2021 we have more than 3.300 people following our page, where we are This year has been exceptional and has shaken all of us from our usual sharing announcements and events. routines. With the appearance and spread of Coronavirus (Sars-CoV- 4. M-Phi Blog 2) the MCMP has followed the suggested rules and regulations by LMU Munich and the State of Bavaria. As a result, the centre was The MCMP maintains a blog on current topics in mathematical closed and everybody encouraged to work from home. Thanks to philosophy. everybody we could keep the spirit up and stay connected. 5. What’s Hot in Mathematical Philosophy? In this report, we present an overview of our activities in challenging 2020. Members of the MCMP are in charge of the “What’s Hot in Mathematical Philosophy?” series, which appears regularly in the (I) We continue to use different media in order to reach out to the online gazette The Reasoner. public: 6. Publication Management 1. The MCMP website In collaboration with LMU's library and the central internet After a relaunch and facelift, the MCMP website continues to be the department, we introduced our very own publication management place to go to for everything MCMP.
    [Show full text]
  • Arxiv:1803.01386V4 [Math.HO] 25 Jun 2021
    2009 SEKI http://wirth.bplaced.net/seki.html ISSN 1860-5931 arXiv:1803.01386v4 [math.HO] 25 Jun 2021 A Most Interesting Draft for Hilbert and Bernays’ “Grundlagen der Mathematik” that never found its way into any publi- Working-Paper cation, and 2 CVof Gisbert Hasenjaeger Claus-Peter Wirth Dept. of Computer Sci., Saarland Univ., 66123 Saarbrücken, Germany [email protected] SEKI Working-Paper SWP–2017–01 SEKI SEKI is published by the following institutions: German Research Center for Artificial Intelligence (DFKI GmbH), Germany • Robert Hooke Str.5, D–28359 Bremen • Trippstadter Str. 122, D–67663 Kaiserslautern • Campus D 3 2, D–66123 Saarbrücken Jacobs University Bremen, School of Engineering & Science, Campus Ring 1, D–28759 Bremen, Germany Universität des Saarlandes, FR 6.2 Informatik, Campus, D–66123 Saarbrücken, Germany SEKI Editor: Claus-Peter Wirth E-mail: [email protected] WWW: http://wirth.bplaced.net Please send surface mail exclusively to: DFKI Bremen GmbH Safe and Secure Cognitive Systems Cartesium Enrique Schmidt Str. 5 D–28359 Bremen Germany This SEKI Working-Paper was internally reviewed by: Wilfried Sieg, Carnegie Mellon Univ., Dept. of Philosophy Baker Hall 161, 5000 Forbes Avenue Pittsburgh, PA 15213 E-mail: [email protected] WWW: https://www.cmu.edu/dietrich/philosophy/people/faculty/sieg.html A Most Interesting Draft for Hilbert and Bernays’ “Grundlagen der Mathematik” that never found its way into any publication, and two CV of Gisbert Hasenjaeger Claus-Peter Wirth Dept. of Computer Sci., Saarland Univ., 66123 Saarbrücken, Germany [email protected] First Published: March 4, 2018 Thoroughly rev. & largely extd. (title, §§ 2, 3, and 4, CV, Bibliography, &c.): Jan.
    [Show full text]
  • (0) 625307185 Home A
    Work address: University College Groningen, Hoendiepskade 23/24, NL-9718 BG Groningen, The Netherlands, +31 (0) 625307185 Home address: ‘t Olde Hof 43, NL-9951JX Winsum, The Netherlands Dr. Dr. Simon Friederich born 30/08/1981 in Heidelberg, Germany http://simonfriederich.eu Email: s.m.friederich @ rug.nl AREAS OF RESEARCH General philosophy of science, philosophy of physics Philosophy of mathematics Epistemology AREAS OF COMPETENCE Philosophy of mind; effective altruism EDUCATION 2019 Habilitation (German qualification for full professorship) in philosophy, Ludwig-Maximilians-Universität München, Germany 2014 PhD in philosophy, Institute for Philosophy, University of Bonn, Germany; grade: “summa cum laude” 2010 PhD in physics, Institute for Theoretical Physics, University of Heidelberg, Germany; grade: “magna cum laude” 2008 Magister in philosophy Philosophisches Seminar, University of Göttingen, Germany; grade: “with distinction” 2007 Diploma in physics Institute for Theoretical Physics, University of Göttingen, Germany; grade: “very good” CURRENT POSITION Since September 2019 Associate professor of philosophy of science, University of Groningen, University College Groningen (UCG) and Faculty of Philosophy, The Netherlands, Interim Academic Director of Humanities at UCG October 2014 – August 2018, Assistant professor of philosophy of science, University of Groningen, University College Groningen and Faculty of Philosophy, The Netherlands In addition, since August 2015, external member of the Munich Center for Mathematical Philosophy (MCMP) PREVIOUS POSITIONS 2012 – 2014 substituting for a full professorship in theoretical philosophy, University of Göttingen 2011 – 2012 PostDoc at University of Wuppertal University, research collaboration “Epistemology of the Large Hadron Collider”, funded by the German Academic Foundation (DFG) RESEARCH VISITS July 2019 visiting scholar at the Rotman Institute of Philosophy, University of Western Ontario (Canada) Host: Prof.
    [Show full text]
  • EVERT WILLEM BETH's SCIENTIFIC PHILOSOPHY 1. Introduction
    EVERT WILLEM BETH'S SCIENTIFIC PHILOSOPHY Miriam FRANCHELLA Universita degli Studi, Milano 1. Introduction The Dutch man Evert Willem Beth (1908-1964) is famous for his contributions to logic. It is also known that he was a philosopher and became interested in logic quite late in his life. Still, the aspects of his philosophical reflections and the details of its development are almost unknown. He himself gave some hints for ordering his pro­ duction. 1 He divided it into four periods: the neo-kantian, the antikantian, the antiirrationalist, the logical one. Within this frame­ work, it is possible to individuate a core around which Beth devel­ oped his reflections: it is the interplay betwe~n philosophy and the sciences. In effect, his philosophical reflections were always linked to the sciences in two ways: firstly, because he steadily checked his philosophical ideas against the current situation in foundational re­ search; second, because he occupied himself with the general ques­ tion of the relationships between philosophy and the sciences. We are going to analyse these aspects in detail. 2. The role of intuition: thinking ofKant At the very beginning of his work Beth was convinced that intuitionism was the only acceptable foundational school. He con­ sidered logicism as "out" at that period. The other two positions - formalism and intuitionism - appealed both to intuition: 1. "Een terugblik" ("A retrospective view"), De Gids 123 (1960), 320-330; also in E.W. Beth, Door wetenshap tot wijsheid (Assen, van Gorcum 1964), 112-113. 222 intuitionism directly, in the construction of mathematics, while for­ malism only in the metamathematical analysis.
    [Show full text]
  • Formal, Informal Or Anti-Logical? the Philosophy of the Logician Evert Willem Beth (1908-1964)
    INFORMAL LOGIC XII. 1, Winter 1990 In the Service of Human Society: Formal, Informal or Anti-Logical? The Philosophy of the Logician Evert Willem Beth (1908-1964) E. M. BARTH Groningen University Introduction 1. Where does European argumentation theory come from? Proof as a social act The topic on which I have been asked to speak is, as far as I understood it, the Where does the highly amorphous field formal-informal divide in logic. Having called argumentation theory derive from? pondered about that task for a long time I There is, I believe, a certain difference be­ decided that concerning a weighing of the tween the United States on the one hand and pro's and con's of the two approaches I Europe and Canada on the other in this want to cut it short and to simply say: respect. Whereas in the United States the There ought to be formal logic, attuned departments of speech communication seem to human affairs; to have been very influential indeed, in There ought to be informal logic, attuned Europe argumentation theory derives from to human affairs; philosophy, and to a very large extent from logic-as in Canada. and once upon a time the twain shall meet. This fact is of considerable importance I do not accept the formal-informal for an understanding of the possibilities of, divide as a divide. That distinction ought and in, the field, as I shall try to show. Five to be played down. It is merely a question European philosophers at least from the of method-an interesting question, but not generation before us must be mentioned, at all a threatening one.
    [Show full text]
  • E.W. Beth and the Logical Empiricists Philosophia Scientiæ, Tome 3, No 4 (1998-1999), P
    PHILOSOPHIA SCIENTIÆ HENK VISSER E.W. Beth and the logical empiricists Philosophia Scientiæ, tome 3, no 4 (1998-1999), p. 49-76 <http://www.numdam.org/item?id=PHSC_1998-1999__3_4_49_0> © Éditions Kimé, 1998-1999, tous droits réservés. L’accès aux archives de la revue « Philosophia Scientiæ » (http://poincare.univ-nancy2.fr/PhilosophiaScientiae/) implique l’accord avec les conditions générales d’utilisation (http://www. numdam.org/conditions). Toute utilisation commerciale ou im- pression systématique est constitutive d’une infraction pénale. Toute copie ou impression de ce fichier doit contenir la pré- sente mention de copyright. Article numérisé dans le cadre du programme Numérisation de documents anciens mathématiques http://www.numdam.org/ E.W. Beth and the Logical Empiricists Henk Visser The E. W. Beth Foundation Abstract. This paper is concerned with Beth's reactions to logical empiricist doctrines, mainly during the period that logical empiricism did not yet belong to the past, beginning with Beth's first publication, and ending at the time that Beth formulated his own conception of scientific philosophy. In Beth's development, three phases are distinguished ; in the fïrst period, which runs frorn 1933 to 1940, Beth's appeal to "évidences" is seen as a fondamental différence with the views of the logical empiricits, though Beth stood sympathetic toward their rejection of metaphysics. During a short second period, from 1940 to 1942, Beth tried to establish a form of "modem metaphysics", which he believed to account for the logical empiricist objections against traditional metaphysics, but after 1942, in his third period, Beth propagated a "scientific philosophy" in which ail results are open to revision.
    [Show full text]
  • Mechanizing Induction
    MECHANIZING INDUCTION Ronald Ortner and Hannes Leitgeb In this chapter we will deal with “mechanizing” induction, i.e. with ways in which theoretical computer science approaches inductive generalization. In the field of Machine Learning , algorithms for induction are developed. De- pending on the form of the available data, the nature of these algorithms may be very different. Some of them combine geometric and statistical ideas, while others use classical reasoning based on logical formalism. However, we are not so much interested in the algorithms themselves, but more on the philosophical and theoretical foundations they share. Thus in the first of two parts, we will examine different approaches and inductive assumptions in two particular learning settings. While many machine learning algorithms work well on a lot of tasks, the inter- pretation of the learned hypothesis is often difficult. Thus, while e.g. an algorithm surprisingly is able to determine the gender of the author of a given text with about 80 percent accuracy [Argamon and Shimoni, 2003 ], for a human it takes some extra effort to understand on the basis of which criteria the algorithm is able to do so. With that respect the advantage of approaches using logic are obvious: If the output hypothesis is a formula of predicate logic, it is easy to interpret. How- ever, if decision trees or algorithms from the area of inductive logic programming are based purely on classical logic, they suffer from the fact that most universal statements do not hold for exceptional cases, and classical logic does not offer any convenient way of representing statements which are meant to hold in the “normal case”.
    [Show full text]
  • Possible-Worlds Semantics for Modal Notions Conceived As Predicates
    POSSIBLE-WORLDS SEMANTICS FOR MODAL NOTIONS CONCEIVED AS PREDICATES VOLKER HALBACH, HANNES LEITGEB, AND PHILIP WELCH Abstract. If is conceived as an operator, i.e., an expression that gives applied to a formula another formula, the expressive power of the language is severely re- stricted when compared to a language where is conceived as a predicate, i.e., an expression that yields a formula if it is applied to a term. This consideration favours the predicate approach. The predicate view, however, is threatened mainly by two problems: Some obvious predicate systems are inconsistent, and possible-worlds se- mantics for predicates of sentences has not been developed very far. By introducing possible-worlds semantics for the language of arithmetic plus the unary predicate , we tackle both problems. Given a frame hW, Ri consisting of a set W of worlds and a binary relation R on W, we investigate whether we can interpret at every world in such a way that pAq holds at a world w ∈ W if and only if A holds at every world v ∈ W such that wRv. The arithmetical vocabulary is interpreted by the standard model at every world. Several ‘paradoxes’ (like Montague’s Theorem, G¨odel’s Second Incompleteness Theorem, McGee’s Theorem on the ω-inconsistency of certain truth theories etc.) show that many frames, e.g., reflexive frames, do not allow for such an interpretation. We present sufficient and necessary conditions for the existence of a suitable interpretation of at any world. Sound and complete semi-formal systems, corresponding to the modal systems K and K4, for the class of all possible-worlds models for predicates and all transitive possible-worlds models are presented.
    [Show full text]
  • Reducing Belief Simpliciter to Degrees of Belief
    Reducing Belief Simpliciter to Degrees of Belief Hannes Leitgeb March 2010 Abstract We prove that given reasonable assumptions, it is possible to give an explicit defini- tion of belief simpliciter in terms of subjective probability, such that it is neither the case that belief is stripped of any of its usual logical properties, nor is it the case that believed propositions are bound to have probability 1. Belief simpliciter is not to be eliminated in favour of degrees of belief, rather, by reducing it to assignments of con- sistently high degrees of belief, both quantitative and qualitative belief turn out to be governed by one unified theory. Turning to possible applications and extensions of the theory, we suggest that this will allow us to see: how the Bayesian approach in general philosophy of science can be reconciled with the deductive or semantic conception of scientific theories and theory change; how primitive conditional probability functions (Popper functions) arise from conditionalizing absolute probability measures on max- imally strong believed propositions with respect to different cautiousness thresholds; how the assertability of conditionals can become an all-or-nothing affair in the face of non-trivial subjective conditional probabilities; how knowledge entails a high degree of belief but not necessarly certainty; and how high conditional chances may become the truthmakers of counterfactuals. 1 Introduction [THIS IS A PRELIMINARY AND INCOMPLETE DRAFT OF JUST THE TECHNICAL DETAILS:::] Belief is said to come in a quantitative version—degrees of belief—and in a qualitative one—belief simpliciter. More particularly, rational belief is said to have such a quantita- tive and a qualitative side, and indeed we will only be interested in notions of belief here which satisfy some strong logical requirements.
    [Show full text]
  • Logic in Philosophy of Mathematics
    Logic in Philosophy of Mathematics Hannes Leitgeb 1 What is Philosophy of Mathematics? Philosophers have been fascinated by mathematics right from the beginning of philosophy, and it is easy to see why: The subject matter of mathematics| numbers, geometrical figures, calculation procedures, functions, sets, and so on|seems to be abstract, that is, not in space or time and not anything to which we could get access by any causal means. Still mathematicians seem to be able to justify theorems about numbers, geometrical figures, calcula- tion procedures, functions, and sets in the strictest possible sense, by giving mathematical proofs for these theorems. How is this possible? Can we actu- ally justify mathematics in this way? What exactly is a proof? What do we even mean when we say things like `The less-than relation for natural num- bers (non-negative integers) is transitive' or `there exists a function on the real numbers which is continuous but nowhere differentiable'? Under what conditions are such statements true or false? Are all statements that are formulated in some mathematical language true or false, and is every true mathematical statement necessarily true? Are there mathematical truths which mathematicians could not prove even if they had unlimited time and economical resources? What do mathematical entities have in common with everyday objects such as chairs or the moon, and how do they differ from them? Or do they exist at all? Do we need to commit ourselves to the existence of mathematical entities when we do mathematics? Which role does mathematics play in our modern scientific theories, and does the em- pirical support of scientific theories translate into empirical support of the mathematical parts of these theories? Questions like these are among the many fascinating questions that get asked by philosophers of mathematics, and as it turned out, much of the progress on these questions in the last century is due to the development of modern mathematical and philosophical logic.
    [Show full text]