Knowledge and Belief: 'De Dicto' and 'De

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Knowledge and Belief: 'De Dicto' and 'De Knowledge and Belief: 'De Dicto' and 'De Re' Author(s): Roderick Chisholm Source: Philosophical Studies: An International Journal for Philosophy in the Analytic Tradition , Vol. 29, No. 1 (Jan., 1976), pp. 1-20 Published by: Springer Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/4319005 Accessed: 09-02-2016 18:18 UTC Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/page/ info/about/policies/terms.jsp JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. Springer is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Philosophical Studies: An International Journal for Philosophy in the Analytic Tradition. http://www.jstor.org This content downloaded from 128.103.149.52 on Tue, 09 Feb 2016 18:18:43 UTC All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions RODERICK CHISHOLM KNOWLEDGE AND BELIEF: 'DE DICTO' AND 'DE RE' 1. INTRODUCTION I will attemptto explicatethe conceptsof beliefde re, knowledgede dicto, and knowledgede re. The generalapproach to be developedhere may also be appliedto those otherintentional attitudes - for example,desire, hope, fear, and endeavor- which may be directedeither upon propositionsor upon things which are not propositions.It differsfrom other contem- porarytreatments of these topics in that it does not attemptto explicate belief and knowledgeby referenceto linguisticconcepts. I assumethat languageshould be explicatedby referenceto belief and knowledge,and that it is not enlighteningto attemptto explicatebelief and knowledge by referenceto language.2 The definitionsI will formulatepresuppose the followingphilosophical concepts:(i) that of beliefde dicto,or the acceptanceof a proposition,as expressedin the locution'h is acceptedby S'; (ii) that of epistemicprefer- ability,as expressedin 'p is epistemicallypreferable to q for S'; (iii) that of necessityde re, as expressedin 'x is necessarilysuch that it is F' (iv) that of a propertyor attribute,considered as an 'eternalobject', something existingin everypossible world; and (v) the conceptof a propositionbeing true. I will also make use of the expressionsof logic and allow myself certainschematic definitions. I believethat the systemof conceptsto be utilizedhere is muchsimpler than any of those presupposedby other discussionsof these topics. 2. DE DICTO BELIEF I proposethat, in what follows, we restrictthe schema S believesthat p, (wherep may be replacedby any Englishsentence) to its ordinaryde dicto sense.This will mean,for one thing,that we cannotexistentially generalize PhilosophicalStudies 29 (1976) 1-20. All Rights Reserved Copyright? 1976 by D. ReidelPublishing Company, Dordrecht-Holland This content downloaded from 128.103.149.52 on Tue, 09 Feb 2016 18:18:43 UTC All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 2 RODERICK CHISHOLM over any term within the sentencein the place of p. Thus if our de dicto belief sentenceis Jones believesthat the tallest man is wise we cannot take the propositionit expressesto entail Thereis an x such that Jones believesthat x is wise. Nor can we replaceany term withinthe sentenceoccupying the place of p by any other term havingthe same extension.Hence, even if we know both that(1) the tallestman is the fastestrunner and that (2) Jonesbelieves that the tallest man is wise, we cannot, on the basis of this information, drawthe inferenceto Jones believesthat the fastestrunner is wise. Anotherfeature of this de dicto use of 'Jones believesthat the tallest man is wise' is this: If we know that the sentenceis true, in this de dicto use, then we may say of Jonesthat, if he is asked'Is the tallestman wise?', if he understandsthe question, and if he intends to reply honestlyand correctly,then he will endeavorto replyin the affirmative. In suggestingthat we restrictthe locution 'S believes that p' to this de dictosense, I am not suggestingthat the locutionis in fact so restricted in ordinaryEnglish. Indeed, I believethat it is not so restricted.3 If we are sensitiveto what seem to be the ontologicalimplications of belief, the ontologicalimplications of the fact that people believethings, we will realizethat (1) Jones believesthat the tallest man is wise impliesthat (2) Thereis somethingthat Jones believes. If we do not see this at once, perhapsit will help us if we considersuch facts as the following.If we know, not only that (1) is true, but also that Smithbelieves that the tallestman is wise, then we may inferthat thereis somethingthat both Jones and Smith believe. But if there is something that both Jonesand Smithbelieve, then there is an answerto the question: And whatis that something?(Or there is an answerto the question:What is one thingthat they both believe?)In the case of our examplethe answer would be: That the tallestman is wise. This content downloaded from 128.103.149.52 on Tue, 09 Feb 2016 18:18:43 UTC All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions KNOWLEDGE AND BELIEF: 'DE DICTO' AND 'DE RE' 3 We may obviouslyinfer (2) above from 'Thereis somethingthat both Jones and Smithbelieve'. But the truth of (2) is hardlydependent upon the fact that Smithhappens to believethe samething Jones does. It would seem, therefore,that once we are clear about what is implied by (1), when (1) is taken in the way we have suggested,then we should see that (1) implies(2).4 Given, then, that (1) does imply (2), it is usefulfor philosophicalpur- poses to make (1) more explicit.The logical structureof (1) is more ade- quatelyexposed if we rewriteit as (3) Jones acceptsthe propositionthat the tallest man is wise. Statement(3) expressesa straightforwarddyadic relation between Jones and a certainproposition, enabling us to infer 'Thereexist an x and a y such that x acceptsy'. Thus our sentence(3) is an instanceof this generalschema: S acceptsthe propositionthat p. I proposewe take this locution as the paradigmaticexpression of belief de dictoand introducethe moreordinary locution, instanced by (1), as an abbreviation.Thus we will have (DI) S believesthat p = Df The propositionthat p is acceptedby S. The definitionis schematic;we may replacep by any Englishsentence. Let us say that, if a man thus acceptsa proposition,then the proposition is one of the objectsof his belief. It is essentialto note that,very often, the propositionswe say we believe (even when we are speakingsincerely) are not in fact the objectsof our belief. I might point to a certainformula in PrincipiaMathematica and say "I believe that proposition",when, in fact, the propositionI accept is the one I might expressby saying"The propositionexpressed by that formula is true". The latter propositioncould be said, in Brentano's terminology,to be a surrogatefor the former.5 3. DE RE BELIEF One may make analogous points about what has been called de re belief. This content downloaded from 128.103.149.52 on Tue, 09 Feb 2016 18:18:43 UTC All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 4 RODERICK CHISHOLM If we remainsensitive to what seem to be the ontologicalimplications of belief, we will realizethat (1) The tallest man is believedby Jones to be wise implies (2) There is somethingthat Jones attributesto the tallest man. (In the placeof 'attributesto the tallestman', we mightsay 'believesof the tallestman'.) If one does not see immediatelythat (1) implies(2), one has only to note that, if (2) is true, and if the tallest man is also believedby Smith to be wise, then we could say that there is somethingthat both Jones and Smithattribute to the tallestman. The logical structureof (1), then, is somewhatmore adequatelyexpressed if we rewriteit as (3) Jones attributesthe propertyof beingwise to the tallestman. Our sentenceis thus an instanceof this generalschema S attributesto x the propertyof being F wherethe letterF is replaceableby any predicate-expression(e.g., 'wise' or 'such that he is wise' or 'suchthat he is wise and all men are mortal'). I proposewe take this locutionas the paradigmaticexpression of belief de re and introducethe more ordinarylocution, instancedby (1), as an abbreviation.Thus we will have (D2) x is believedby S to be F=Df S attributesthe propertyof being F to x. But the definiensof (D2), 'S attributesthe propertyof being F to x', is not includedamong the philosophicalconcepts we allowed ourselves at the outset. One problem,then, is that of explicatingthe concept of attributinga propertyto a thing. 4. INTERRELATIONS BETWEEN BELIEF 'DE RE' AND 'DE DICTO' The followingsummary may now throw some light upon what has been said about the objectsof belief.The lettersF and G occupythe placesof predicateexpressions and 'the F' is short for 'the thing which is F'. (a) S believesthat the F is G. (b) The F is believedby S to be G. This content downloaded from 128.103.149.52 on Tue, 09 Feb 2016 18:18:43 UTC All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions KNOWLEDGE AND BELIEF: 'DE DICTO' AND 'DE RE' 5 (c) S believesthat the propositionthat the F is G is true. (d) The propositionthat the F is G is believedby S to be true. (e) The propositionthat the F is G is acceptedby S. (f) S believesthat the F has the propertyof being G. (g) The F is believedby S to be such that it has the propertyof being G. (h) S attributesthe propertyof being G to the F. These eight locutions are easily confused with each other and such confusionsometimes infects what has been writtenabout the philosophy of belief. Let us ask, with respectto each of these locutions,which ones of the othersit entails.6 If 'accepts'and 'attributes'are restrictedin the ways in which I have proposed,then we may assertthat the followingentailment relations hold: a entailse b entailsh c entailsa, d, and e e entails a f entails a and e g entailsb and h h entailsb But no additionalentailment relations hold among these locutions.
Recommended publications
  • Ernest Sosa and Virtuously Begging the Question
    University of Windsor Scholarship at UWindsor OSSA Conference Archive OSSA 9 May 18th, 9:00 AM - May 21st, 5:00 PM Ernest Sosa and virtuously begging the question Michael Walschots University of Windsor Scott F. Aikin Follow this and additional works at: https://scholar.uwindsor.ca/ossaarchive Part of the Philosophy Commons Walschots, Michael and Aikin, Scott F., "Ernest Sosa and virtuously begging the question" (2011). OSSA Conference Archive. 38. https://scholar.uwindsor.ca/ossaarchive/OSSA9/papersandcommentaries/38 This Paper is brought to you for free and open access by the Conferences and Conference Proceedings at Scholarship at UWindsor. It has been accepted for inclusion in OSSA Conference Archive by an authorized conference organizer of Scholarship at UWindsor. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Ernest Sosa and virtuously begging the question MICHAEL WALSCHOTS Department of Philosophy University of Windsor 401 Sunset Ave. Windsor, ON N9P 3B4 Canada [email protected] ABSTRACT: This paper discusses the notion of epistemic circularity, supposedly different from logical circu- larity, and evaluates Ernest Sosa’s claim that this specific kind of circular reasoning is virtuous rather than vicious. I attempt to determine whether or not the conditions said to make epistemic circularity a permissible instance of begging the question could make other instances of circular reasoning equally permissible. KEYWORDS: begging the question, circular reasoning, Ernest Sosa, epistemic circularity, petitio principii, reliabilism. 1. INTRODUCTION In 1986, William Alston introduced the idea of ‘epistemic circularity’, which involves assuming the reliability of a given source of belief during the process of proving the reli- ability of that same source.
    [Show full text]
  • Waldomiro José Silva Filho1 Marcos Antonio Alves2
    Presentation Editorial / Editorial PRESENTATION Waldomiro José Silva Filho 1 Marcos Antonio Alves 2 It is with great happiness and honor that we present this special issue of Trans/Form/Ação: Unesp journal of philosophy in honor of Ernest Sosa. One of the most influential voices in the contemporary philosophy, Ernest Sosa was born in Cárdenas, Cuba, on June 17, 1940. He earned his Bachelor of Arts (B.A.) and Master of Arts (M.A.) from the University of Miami and his Doctor of Philosophy (Ph.D.) from the University of Pittsburgh in 1964. Since 2007, he has been Board of Governors Professor of Philosophy at Rutgers University. There is no doubt that Sosa is responsible for one of the revolution in Epistemology that will mark the history of philosophy. However, he also opened new paths in several central issues of philosophy, such as Metaphysics, Philosophy of Language and Philosophy of Mind. In 2020, the world philosophical community on all continents joined with his close friends and family to celebrate Ernie’s 80th birthday. Dozens of publications, books, journals, and webinars were held, even amidst the humanitarian devastation of the pandemic. The journal Trans/Form/Ação 1 Full Professor at the Philosophy Department of Federal University of Bahia (UFBA), Salvador, BA – Brazil. Researcher of the CNPq, Brazil. https://orcid.org/0000-0002-0874-9599 E-mail: [email protected] 2 Editor da Trans/Form/Ação: Unesp journal of Philosophy. Professor at the Philosophy Department of and Coordinator of Post Graduation Program in Philosophy – São Paulo State University (UNESP), Marília, SP – Brazil.
    [Show full text]
  • Substance and the Concept of Personal Identity
    AN OPEN ACCESS Ergo JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY Substance and the Concept of Personal Identity JenS KIPPer University of Cologne In this paper, I identify and discuss the following feature of our judgments about hypothetical scenarios concerning the identity of persons: with respect to the vast majority of scenarios, both members of a pair of logically complementary proposi- tions about personal identity are conceivable. I consider a number of explanations of this feature that draw on the metaphysics and the epistemology of personal identity, none of which prove to be satisfactory. I then argue that in order to give an adequate explanation, one needs to recognize an important characteristic of our concept of personal identity: it is such that if there are mental substances (or the like), they constitute personal identity. At the same time, there can still be persons if there are no such substances. Since this finding casts doubts on the way that thought experi- ments about personal identity are usually set up, I end by outlining its potential consequences for the debate over the identity of persons. 1. Introduction The debate over the nature of personal identity is as replete with thought experi- ments as many other philosophical debates. But there is a nagging suspicion that thought experiments work differently when the identity of persons is concerned. For example, it is natural to think that our judgment that the person in Harry Frankfurt’s (1969) famous case is responsible for what he did is based on our conceptual competence. When John Locke argues, however, that the person in the body of a cobbler who has the memories of a prince is that prince (1694/1975: 340), he does not seem to be stating a conceptual truth.
    [Show full text]
  • Thomas Kelly
    Thomas Kelly Department of Philosophy [email protected] Princeton University https://www.princeton.edu/~tkelly/ 212 1879 Hall (617)308-9673 Princeton, NJ 08544 Employment Princeton University, 2004- Professor of Philosophy, 2012- Associated Faculty, University Center for Human Values, 2006- Associate Professor of Philosophy, 2007-2012 Assistant Professor of Philosophy, 2004-2007 Assistant Professor of Philosophy, University of Notre Dame, 2003-2004. Junior Fellow, Harvard Society of Fellows, 2000-2003. Education Ph.D. in Philosophy, Harvard University, 2001. Dissertation: Rationality and the Ethics of Belief Committee: Robert Nozick, Derek Parfit, James Pryor. B.A. in Philosophy, summa cum laude, University of Notre Dame, 1994. Areas of Specialization Epistemology, Rationality, Philosophical Methodology. Areas of Competence History of Analytic Philosophy, Philosophy of Science, Political Philosophy, Ethics, Philosophy of Religion. 2 Publications Papers (32) “Bias: Some Conceptual Geography.” To appear in Nathan Ballantyne and David Dunning (eds.) Reason, Bias, and Inquiry: New Perspectives from the Crossroads of Epistemology and Psychology. (31) “Evidence.” To appear in the Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. (30) “Are There Any Successful Philosophical Arguments?” (co-authored with Sarah McGrath). In John Keller (ed.) Being, Freedom, and Method: Themes from the Philosophy of Peter van Inwagen (Oxford University Press 2017): 324-339. With a reply by Peter van Inwagen. (29) “Religious Diversity and the Epistemology of Theology” (co-authored with Nathan King). In William Abraham and Fred Aquino (eds.) The Oxford Handbook to the Epistemology of Theology (Oxford University Press 2017): 309-324. (28) “Historical versus Current Time Slice Theories in Epistemology.” In Hilary Kornblith and Brian McLaughlin (eds.) Goldman and His Critics (Blackwell Publishers 2016): 43-65.
    [Show full text]
  • A Critique of Roderick Chisholm
    DOI: https://doi.org/10.26512/rfmc.v8i2.35865 Intentionality and the Logico-Linguistic Commitment: A Critique of Roderick Chisholm [Intencionalidade e Compromisso Lógico-Linguístico: Uma crítica a Roderick Chisholm] Luis Niel* Abstract: The aim of this article is to analyze and criticize Roderick Chisholm’s con- ception of intentionality, which has, historically, served as the point of departure for most accounts of intentionality in analytic philosophy. My goal is to highlight the problematic ’logico-linguistic commitment’ presupposed by Chisholm, according to which mental concepts should be interpreted by means of semantic concepts. After addressing Chisholm’s differentiation between the ontological thesis (the idea that the intentional object might not exist) and the psychological thesis (the conception that only mental phenomena are intentional), as well as his defining criteria for intentionality (non-existential implication, independency of truth-value, and indirect reference), I fo- cus on the manifold problems presented by his theory. First, the two initial criteria entail a conceptual confusion between the semantic concept of ’intensionality’ and the mental concept of ’intentionality’. Second, according to these criteria-and against Chisholm’s explicit intention-perception and other cognitive activities should not be considered intentional. Third, there are no grounds for the artificial conflation of intentionality and the concept of ’propositional attitudes’-an equation which is an explicit tenet of the logico-linguistic commitment. In general, I argue that an interpretation of intentionality based on this commitment obscures the true meaning of the concept of intentionality, as it is presented, for instance, by phenomenology. Keywords: Chisholm. Intentionality. Intensionality. Propositional Attitudes. Logico- linguistic Commitment.
    [Show full text]
  • Situations and Individuals
    Forthcoming with MIT Press Current Studies in Linguistics Summer 2005 Situations and Individuals Paul Elbourne To my father To the memory of my mother Preface This book deals with the semantics of the natural language expressions that have been taken to refer to individuals: pronouns, definite descriptions and proper names. It claims, contrary to previous theorizing, that they have a common syntax and semantics, roughly that which is currently associated by philosophers and linguists with definite descriptions as construed in the tradition of Frege. As well as advancing this proposal, I hope to achieve at least one other aim, that of urging linguists and philosophers dealing with pronoun interpretation, in particular donkey anaphora, to consider a wider range of theories at all times than is sometimes done at present. I am thinking particularly of the gulf that seems to have emerged between those who practice some version of dynamic semantics (including DRT) and those who eschew this approach and claim that the semantics of donkey pronouns crucially involves definite descriptions (if they consider donkey anaphora at all). In my opinion there is too little work directly comparing the claims of these two schools (for that is what they amount to) and testing them against the data in the way that any two rival theories might be tested. (Irene Heim’s 1990 article in Linguistics and Philosophy does this, and largely inspired my own project, but I know of no other attempts.) I have tried to remedy that in this book. I ultimately come down on the side of definite descriptions and against dynamic semantics; but that preference is really of secondary importance beside the attempt at a systematic comparative project.
    [Show full text]
  • Arxiv:1908.09658V1 [Cs.MA] 26 Aug 2019 Sdfrtescn Ups.I General, in Purpose
    Dynamic Term-Modal Logic for Epistemic Social Network Dynamics (Extended Version) Andrés Occhipinti Liberman1 and Rasmus K. Rendsvig2 1 DTU Compute [email protected] 2 Center for Information and Bubble Studies, University of Copenhagen [email protected] Abstract. Logics for social networks have been studied in recent liter- ature. This paper presents a framework based on dynamic term-modal logic (DTML), a quantified variant of dynamic epistemic logic (DEL). In contrast with DEL where it is commonly known to whom agent names refer, DTML can represent dynamics with uncertainty about agent iden- tity. We exemplify dynamics where such uncertainty and de re/de dicto distinctions are key to social network epistemics. Technically, we show that DTML semantics can represent a popular class of hybrid logic epis- temic social network models. We also show that DTML can encode pre- viously discussed dynamics for which finding a complete logic was left open. As complete reduction axioms systems exist for DTML, this yields a complete system for the dynamics in question. Keywords: social networks, term-modal logic, dynamic epistemic logic 1 Introduction Over recent years, several papers have been dedicated to logical studies of social networks, their epistemics and dynamics [2,10–14,18–22,24,25]. The purpose of this literature typically is to define and investigate some social dynamics with respect to e.g. long-term stabilization or other properties, or to introduce formal logics that capture some social dynamics, or both. This paper illustrates how dynamic term-modal logic (DTML, [1]) may be arXiv:1908.09658v1 [cs.MA] 26 Aug 2019 used for the second purpose.
    [Show full text]
  • Essence, Plenitude, and Paradox
    PHILOSOPHICAL PERSPECTIVES Philosophical Perspectives, 25, Metaphysics, 2011 ESSENCE, PLENITUDE, AND PARADOX Sarah-Jane Leslie Princeton University Essentialism in philosophy is the view that there are in principle two ways of having properties and including parts: the essential way and the accidental way (e.g, Fine, 1994, 1995; Johnston 1984, 2006; Kripke, 1980; Salmon 1986, 2005; Yablo 1987). As I understand the view, even an extreme essentialist — who takes every property and every part to be had essentially — should agree with the in-principle distinction while arguing that certain metaphysical considerations mean that the second way of having properties is not, and cannot be, exemplified. Such a view would contrast with the view of an anti-essentialist like Willard van Orman Quine who repudiates the very distinction between the two ways of having properties. Quine’s view is not that all properties are accidental, for that would be to use what he calls the “invidious distinction” (1953), rather than repudiate it. His view is that there is not even in principle these two ways of having properties (or satisfying predicates, as he would put it), about which we can ask “Which of these two ways do things have properties?” What then ostensibly distinguishes the essential way of having properties from the accidental way? An object’s essential properties are conditions on what it is to be that object, and this set of conditions fixes just which possibilities or possible worlds the object exists in, namely just those in which it satisfies those conditions. An object’s essential properties also fix how long it exists, namely only at those times at which it satisfies those conditions.
    [Show full text]
  • Concrete Possible Worlds (Final)
    CONCRETE POSSIBLE WORLDS Phillip Bricker 1. INTRODUCTION. Open a book or article of contemporary analytic philosophy, and you are likely to find talk of possible worlds therein. This applies not only to analytic metaphysics, but to areas as diverse as philosophy of language, philosophy of science, epistemology, and ethics. Philosophers agree, for the most part, that possible worlds talk is extremely useful for explicating concepts and formulating theories. They disagree, however, over its proper interpretation. In this chapter, I discuss the view, championed by David Lewis, that philosophers’ talk of possible worlds is the literal truth.1 There exists a plurality of worlds. One of these is our world, the actual world, the physical universe that contains us and all our surroundings. The others are merely possible worlds containing merely possible beings, such as flying pigs and talking donkeys. But the other worlds are no less real or concrete for being merely possible. Fantastic? Yes! What could motivate a philosopher to believe such a tale? I start, as is customary, with modality.2 Truths about the world divide into two sorts: categorical and modal. Categorical truths describe how things are, what is actually the case. Modal truths describe how things could or must be, what is possibly or 1 The fullest statement of Lewis’s theory of possible worlds is contained in his magnum opus, Lewis (1986), On the Plurality of Worlds. Lewis’s view is sometimes called “modal realism.” 2 Historically, it was the attempt to provide semantics for modal logic that catapulted possible worlds to the forefront of analytic philosophy.
    [Show full text]
  • INTENTIONALITY Past and Future VIBS
    INTENTIONALITY Past and Future VIBS Volume 173 Robert Ginsberg Founding Editor Peter A. Redpath Executive Editor Associate Editors G. John M. Abbarno Matti Häyry Mary-Rose Barral Steven V. Hicks Gerhold K. Becker Richard T. Hull Raymond Angelo Belliotti Mark Letteri Kenneth A. Bryson Vincent L. Luizzi C. Stephen Byrum Alan Milchman H. G. Callaway George David Miller Robert A. Delfino Alan Rosenberg Rem B. Edwards Arleen L. F. Salles Andrew Fitz-Gibbon John R. Shook Francesc Forn i Argimon Eddy Souffrant William Gay Tuija Takala Dane R. Gordon Anne Waters J. Everet Green John R. Welch Heta Aleksandra Gylling Thomas F. Woods a volume in Cognitive Science CS Francesc Forn i Argimon, Editor INTENTIONALITY Past and Future Edited by Gábor Forrai and George Kampis Amsterdam - New York, NY 2005 Cover Design: Studio Pollmann The paper on which this book is printed meets the requirements of “ISO 9706:1994, Information and documentation - Paper for documents - Requirements for permanence”. ISBN: 90-420-1817-8 ©Editions Rodopi B.V., Amsterdam - New York, NY 2005 Printed in the Netherlands CONTENTS Preface vii List of Abbreviations ix ONE The Necessity and Nature of Mental Content 1 LAIRD ADDIS TWO Reading Brentano on the Intentionality of the Mental 15 PHILIP J. BARTOK THREE Emotions, Moods, and Intentionality 25 WILLIAM FISH FOUR Lockean Ideas as Intentional Contents 37 GÁBOR FORRAI FIVE Normativity and Mental Content 51 JUSSI HAUKIOJA SIX The Ontological and Intentional Status of Fregean Senses: An Early Account of External Content 63 GREG JESSON
    [Show full text]
  • Kinds of Knowledge, Limits of Science De Ridder, Jeroen
    VU Research Portal Kinds of knowledge, limits of science de Ridder, Jeroen published in Scientism 2018 DOI (link to publisher) 10.1093/oso/9780190462758.003.0009 document version Publisher's PDF, also known as Version of record document license Article 25fa Dutch Copyright Act Link to publication in VU Research Portal citation for published version (APA) de Ridder, J. (2018). Kinds of knowledge, limits of science. In G. J. de Ridder, H. D. Peels, & R. van Woudenberg (Eds.), Scientism: Prospects and Problems (pp. 190-219). Oxford University press. https://doi.org/10.1093/oso/9780190462758.003.0009 General rights Copyright and moral rights for the publications made accessible in the public portal are retained by the authors and/or other copyright owners and it is a condition of accessing publications that users recognise and abide by the legal requirements associated with these rights. • Users may download and print one copy of any publication from the public portal for the purpose of private study or research. • You may not further distribute the material or use it for any profit-making activity or commercial gain • You may freely distribute the URL identifying the publication in the public portal ? Take down policy If you believe that this document breaches copyright please contact us providing details, and we will remove access to the work immediately and investigate your claim. E-mail address: [email protected] Download date: 27. Sep. 2021 Kinds of Knowledge, Limits of Science Scientism: Prospects and Problems Jeroen de Ridder, Rik Peels, and Rene van Woudenberg Print publication date: 2018 Print ISBN-13: 9780190462758 Published to Oxford Scholarship Online: August 2018 DOI: 10.1093/oso/9780190462758.001.0001 Kinds of Knowledge, Limits of Science Jeroen de Ridder DOI:10.1093/oso/9780190462758.003.0009 Abstract and Keywords Does scientific knowledge have limits? This chapter tries to answer this question by first investigating the distinct nature of scientific knowledge, as contrasted with other kinds of knowledge.
    [Show full text]
  • Analyticity, Necessity and Belief Aspects of Two-Dimensional Semantics
    !"# #$%"" &'( ( )#"% * +, %- ( * %. ( %/* %0 * ( +, %. % +, % %0 ( 1 2 % ( %/ %+ ( ( %/ ( %/ ( ( 1 ( ( ( % "# 344%%4 253333 #6#787 /0.' 9'# 86' 8" /0.' 9'# 86' (#"8'# Analyticity, Necessity and Belief Aspects of two-dimensional semantics Eric Johannesson c Eric Johannesson, Stockholm 2017 ISBN print 978-91-7649-776-0 ISBN PDF 978-91-7649-777-7 Printed by Universitetsservice US-AB, Stockholm 2017 Distributor: Department of Philosophy, Stockholm University Cover photo: the water at Petite Terre, Guadeloupe 2016 Contents Acknowledgments v 1 Introduction 1 2 Modal logic 7 2.1Introduction.......................... 7 2.2Basicmodallogic....................... 13 2.3Non-denotingterms..................... 21 2.4Chaptersummary...................... 23 3 Two-dimensionalism 25 3.1Introduction.......................... 25 3.2Basictemporallogic..................... 27 3.3 Adding the now operator.................. 29 3.4Addingtheactualityoperator................ 32 3.5 Descriptivism ......................... 34 3.6Theanalytic/syntheticdistinction............. 40 3.7 Descriptivist 2D-semantics .................. 42 3.8 Causal descriptivism ..................... 49 3.9Meta-semantictwo-dimensionalism............. 50 3.10Epistemictwo-dimensionalism................ 54
    [Show full text]