Preface 1 Singer and the Practical Ethics Movement

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Preface 1 Singer and the Practical Ethics Movement 1 Preface Singer and the Practical Ethics Movement DALE JAMIESON This book is a celebration of the work of Peter· . honor people by criticizing them Sing.' .f Smger. Smce philosophers wn come in for analysis and appr~isal .el tShi mlgs on a Wide array of topics . III S vo ume Smger' t h· Peter Singer is one of the most influential philosophers of the twentieth VieWS, his normative theory , and h·IS su b stanttve. posif. s meh aet Ical as the moral status of animals th .t f h IOns on suc matters century. While other philosophers have been more important ill the devel­ are all subjected to scrutiny' Si e sa~cI yo. uman life, and famine relief opment of the discipline, none has changed more lives. Newsweek maga­ supplement what he h .. nger s rephes to his critics importantly "ille observed that "the modem [animal rights] movement may be dated to essential reading for an~~::~~~u:y ~r:tt;nllon these issues and will be the publication of Animal Liberation.,,1 For many years this book was Many people helped to make thea;r;se:t ~~uundersta?d his views. given away by People for the Ethical Treatment of Animals, one of the Lapore's enthusiastic invitation and St S· h~e pOSSible. It was Ernie organizations founded in the wake of Animal Liberation and now one of the project going and sustained it C e~~ m~ IS steady support that got the largest and most effective animal rights organizations in the world. On the Henry R. Luce Foundation· a~ e on 0 lege m conjunction with Paul McCartney's 1993 world tour copies of Animal Liberation were sold support and the E . I proVided funds for research and staff alongside T-shirts. Thus far Animal Liberation has sold more than 400,000 , nVlronmenta Impacts Grou f h N . for Atmospheric Research (NCAR) pot e atlOnal Center copies in nine languages. Altogether Singer is responsible ill whole or part being completed. Kelly Knutsen and ;:: my home while the book was for producing twenty-seven books, most of which sell significantly better Carleton, and Baat Enosh er£ d la Lackey proVided support at than books by other philosophers. Practical Ethics, for example, has sold NCAR. I am indebted to Ba~t f~~~th v:nous electronic miracles at over 100,000 copies ill ten languages. Singer has also authored a vast humor. I also thank John Taylor ~ hi er competence and her good number of articles and reviews that have appeared in journals ranging s Finally, Peter Singer was unfailingl~r hel ;~Od and pattent copy-editing. from The Philosophical Review to the New York Times. able and discussing his work with ihu m makmg hiS papers avail­ Peter Singer was born ill Melbourne, Australia, on July 6, 1946. His gratitude for their hospitality durin me. .e enttre Smger falll11y has my parents were Viennese Jews who escaped ill 1938, shortly after the S. g my VISit to Melbourne Anschluss incorporated Austria into the German Reich. They fled to mce most of us produce so few book . people to acknowledge I believe th t II s and there are so many worthy Australia because that was the only country that would accept them, This book is dedicated ;0 all those a a blioOks should have dedications. sponsored by a man whom Peter's mother had met only once through a . woeh b eve tliatphil h· . mutual acquaintance when he was a tourist ill Vienna. By the time Peter an acadenuc exercise or a way of k' . asop y 18 not Just for improving ourselves and mak~a ;~g a hvmg, but also an illstrument was born, his father was a successful importer of coffee and tea and his book is dedicated to those who loo:g t the world better. In parttcular this mother was practicillg medicine, a profession for which she had trailled in "Why not the best?" a emselves and others and wonder, Austria. Eager to integrate their children into Australian society, the Smgers spoke only English at home and sent Peter to a prestigious Dale Jamieson Protestant school. He went on to Melbourne University, where as an Northfield, Millnesota undergraduate he studied law, history, and philosophy. In 1969 he 2 JAMIESON SINGER AND THE PRACTICAL ETHICS MOVEMENT 3 receiv~~ an MA in philosophy, writing a thesis on "Why should I be moral. A scholarshIp allowed Singer to complete his graduate stud' . movement and the rebirth of feminism, the apparent consensus of the Oxford, where he received his BPhil in 1971 and served R dlelifs:," 1950s was shattered by student protests and black militancy. In the lecturer from 1971 to 1973. as a c .e United States there was a clear "disconnect" between what was going In 1972, Singer published "Famine, affluence and morality" in the fIrst on in the university and what was happening in the streets. This was volume of a new Journal, Philosophy and Public Affairs Thi f I symbolized by the disruption of John Searle's ethics classes at Berkeley. whICh has been reprinted more than two doze f .: s ar IC e, Searle wanted to lecture on deriving an "ought" from an "is," while several reasons. In style it was an unconventio:al1~, 18 l::;portant f~r students wanted to discuss the war in Vietnam. As an undergraduate at that it was written in simple, direct prose with fe~ r osop cal ess'J,y ill San Francisco State in the late 1960s, I was vividly aware of this split sophical texts. Rather than beginning from'Kant Ar' t e;~rences to ph!lo­ between philosophY and life. Ethics in the classroom was W. D. Ross and P. H. Nowell-Smith but it was Martin Luther King, Che Guevara, and the Ical moral question, it addressed events that wer~ oc~~~r~'g o:s as::;Peothet­ Wfltillg. The artJcle began with these words' "As I 't thi · N g r Was Black Panthers who dominated our conversations outside of class. In 1971 I '. Wfl e s, m ovember d.' ~eop e ,~~ dYillg ill East Bengal from lack of food shelter and 1968, the year in which student insurrections broke out all over the me lea care. mger went on to present his readers with ~ stark ~oral world, the biggest news in academic philosophy was the growing hege­ challenge. On the basis of some apparently simple I 'bl . mony of truth-conditional semantics. But the philosophers who made a a d th t ' P ausl e prennses· he r,;;;e a we ought to transfer our resources to those who are worsdoff difference to the events of 1968 were not Quine and Davidson but Marx u: we reach the point at which further transfers would hann and Marcuse. The frustration that many of us felt was not merely that re t an they w?uld benefIt others. Singer Was asking his readers to usi.:o Marx and Marcuse were not discussed in classes, but that the very con­ th:: opera tICkets, theIr Wille cellars, and private schools for their c~dr~~ cerns that motivated them seemed to have been banished from academic ~ ; accoutr~ments of the sophisticated, upper-middle class life favored philosophy. While there is a lot to be said for working in philosophy of language, even during wartime, in retrospect it seems inevitable that the a~outa~a:~ ::~sde=::,~:~ore, Singer Was completely nnapologetic concerns of real life could not forever be excluded from the academy, especially in a discipline that has a long history of concern with substant­ ive normative questions. ::: :~:~f~~: 1~:ll~~~ c~m~~~~~~~~:~' f~:~:~~e~~na~::e:~c~:ldy Wit~iit~ By the late 1960s, a group of elite East Coast philosophers, including CUSSlOn ... IS not enough Wh t' th·. s Thomas Nagel, John Rawls, and Judith Jarvis Thomson, had formed the (and personal) affairs if' a IS e pomt of relatIng philosophy to public . t t kin we do not take our conclusions seriously? In this Society for Ethical and Legal Philosophy and were discussing such topics illS anee, a g OUf conclusion seriously means acting upon it. 3 . as racism, abortion, affirmative action, and the morality of war. Soon Sin . h thereafter a group of philosophers at Rockefeller University launched ger was wfltillg t ese words at a new moment' h'l Philosophy and Public Affairs. The practical ethics movement soon ~:re ~an f~ee~ years before, in 1956, Peter Laslet~ h~dl ~:~~~~d ~!~~~ swept the country. in ~o osop y ead, and moral philosophy clearly was among the walk­ The philosophers who were turning their attention to matters of urgent "i~eolo:dedhl ~ 1960, ill The End of Ideology, Daniel Bell declared that public interest were not exclusively moral and political philosophers. In th U '. wd ~ once was a road to action, has come to be a dead end ,,4 Since the issues that they discussed were of broad interest, yet had largely chall:nge~~bou~a~~~h:eli::sa:~d~~:~ad atgrefement that fundamen;al been ignored by professional philosophers, they were fair game for who­ I I b sor 0 country to create had ever wanted to take them up. Ironically, just as Russell turned out to be arge y een resolved by the affluent society of the 1950s 5 Th . till the most politically active major philosopher of the century, so logicians problems of the future were in the basic science .' . ~ III e eclua and philosophers of science helped to bring practical ethics back into the solutio~s.
Recommended publications
  • Understandings of Genomic Research in Developing
    Traore et al. BMC Medical Ethics (2015) 16:42 DOI 10.1186/s12910-015-0035-7 RESEARCH ARTICLE Open Access Understandings of genomic research in developing countries: a qualitative study of the views of MalariaGEN participants in Mali Karim Traore1, Susan Bull2*, Alassane Niare1, Salimata Konate1, Mahamadou A. Thera1, Dominic Kwiatkowski3, Michael Parker2 and Ogobara K. Doumbo1 Abstract Background: Obtaining informed consent for participation in genomic research in low-income settings presents specific ethical issues requiring attention. These include the challenges that arise when providing information about unfamiliar and technical research methods, the implications of complicated infrastructure and data sharing requirements, and the potential consequences of future research with samples and data. This study investigated researchers’ and participants’ parents’ experiences of a consent process and understandings of a genome-wide association study of malaria involving children aged five and under in Mali. It aimed to inform best practices in recruiting participants into genomic research. Methods: A qualitative rapid ethical assessment was undertaken. Fifty-five semi-structured interviews were conducted with the parents of research participants. An additional nine semi-structured interviews were conducted with senior research scientists, research assistants and with a member of an ethics committee. A focus group with five parents of research participants and direct observations of four consent processes were also conducted. French and translated English transcripts were descriptively and thematically coded using OpenCode software. Results: Participants’ parents in the MalariaGEN study had differing understandings of the causes of malaria, the rationale for collecting blood samples, the purposes of the study and the kinds of information the study would generate.
    [Show full text]
  • Practical Ethics, Third Edition
    This page intentionally left blank Practical Ethics Third Edition For thirty years, Peter Singer’s Practical Ethics has been the classic introduction to applied ethics. For this third edition, the author has revised and updated all the chapters and added a new chapter addressing climate change, one of the most important ethical chal- lenges of our generation. Some of the questions discussed in this book concern our daily lives. Is it ethical to buy luxuries when others do not have enough to eat? Should we buy meat produced from intensively reared animals? Am I doing something wrong if my carbon footprint is above the global average? Other questions confront us as concerned citizens: equality and discrimination on the grounds of race or sex; abortion, the use of embryos for research, and euthanasia; political violence and terrorism; and the preservation of our planet’s environment. This book’s lucid style and provocative arguments make it an ideal text for university courses and for anyone willing to think about how she or he ought to live. Peter Singer is currently Ira W. DeCamp Professor of Bioethics at the University Center for Human Values at Princeton University and Laureate Professor at the Centre for Applied Philosophy and Public Ethics at the University of Melbourne. He is the author or editor of more than forty books, including Animal Liberation (1975), Rethinking Life and Death (1996) and, most recently, The Life You Can Save (2009). In 2005, he was named one of the 100 most influential people in the world by Time magazine. Practical Ethics Third Edition PETER SINGER Princeton University and the University of Melbourne cambridge university press Cambridge, New York, Melbourne, Madrid, Cape Town, Singapore, Sao˜ Paulo, Delhi, Dubai, Tokyo, Mexico City Cambridge University Press 32 Avenue of the Americas, New York, ny 10013-2473, usa www.cambridge.org Information on this title: www.cambridge.org/9780521707688 C Peter Singer 1980, 1993, 2011 This publication is in copyright.
    [Show full text]
  • A Confucian Defense of Shame: Morality, Self-Cultivation, and the Dangers of Shamelessness
    religions Article Article Article A ConfucianA Confucian Defense Defense of Shame: of Shame: Morality, Morality, Self-Cultivation, Self-Cultivation, A Confucian Defense of Shame: Morality, Self-Cultivation, and theand Dangers the Dangers of Shamelessness of Shamelessness and the Dangers of Shamelessness Mark BerksonMark Berkson Mark Berkson Department of Religion,Department Hamline of Religion, University, Hamline St. Paul, University, MN 55104, St. USA;Paul, [email protected] 55104, USA; [email protected] Department of Religion, Hamline University, St. Paul, MN 55104, USA; [email protected] Abstract: ManyAbstract: philosophers Many and philosophers scholars in and the scholars West have in the a negative West have view a negative of shame. view In muchof shame. In much of Abstract: Many philosophers and scholars in the West have a negative view of shame.of post-classical In much ofpost-classical Western ethical Western thought, ethical shame thought, is compared shame is negativelycompared negatively with guilt, with as shame guilt, isas shame is asso- post-classical Western ethical thought, shame is compared negatively with guilt, asassociated shame is asso- withciated the “outer”, with the how “outer”, one appears how one before appears others before (and othe thusrs is (and merely thus a is matter merely of a “face”), matter of “face”), and ciated with the “outer”, how one appears before others (and thus is merely a matterand of “face”), guilt is and associatedguilt is associated with the “inner”with the realm “inner” of therealm conscience of the conscience and soul. and Anthropologists soul. Anthropologists and and philoso- guilt is associated with the “inner” realm of the conscience and soul.
    [Show full text]
  • Consequentialism and Moral Responsibility
    Consequentialism and Moral Responsibility Draft of September 2015 Elinor Mason For Christian Seidel (ed.) Consequentialism: new directions, new problems? OUP, forthcoming. There are two different ways of thinking about the relationship between consequentialism and moral responsibility. First, we might think that consequentialism can give us an account of responsibility. I discuss this possibility briefly, and then set it aside. The other way of thinking about the relationship is the focus of this paper. The question that concerns me, is, to what extent is a normative theory, consequentialism in particular, constrained by requirements that stem from concerns about responsibility? 1. Consequentialist Accounts of Moral Responsibility J.J.C. Smart suggests that we can extend consequentialist reasoning about morality to reasoning about responsibility. One of the attractions of consequentialism is that it provides such a straightforward and attractive account of justification for our moral practices. Why do we pay our taxes, treat each other with respect, look after each other and so on? Because doing so has good consequences. However, this sort of justification, though very appealing when considering moral practice, becomes extremely counterintuitive in other sorts of case. For example, it seems obvious that justification for beliefs cannot be consequentialist. Beliefs must be justified in some way that relates to their truth, though of course there is disagreement about exactly what makes a belief justified. Similarly, so a familiar line of thought goes, whether or not someone is responsible for an act, or for anything else, cannot be determined by looking at the consequences of holding them responsible. The claim that 1 responsibility can be understood in a consequentialist way seems like a category mistake.1 Smart’s view might be correct that, insofar as praising and blaming are actions, consequentialists should take the value of the consequences of performing those acts as the relevant factor in deciding whether or not to perform them.
    [Show full text]
  • Rolston on Animals, Ethics, and the Factory Farm
    [Expositions 6.1 (2012) 29–40] Expositions (online) ISSN: 1747–5376 Unnaturally Cruel: Rolston on Animals, Ethics, and the Factory Farm CHRISTIAN DIEHM University of Wisconsin, Stevens Point In 2010, over nine billion animals were killed in the United States for human consumption. This included nearly 1 million calves, 2.5 million sheep and lambs, 34 million cattle, 110 million hogs, 242 million turkeys, and well over 8.7 billion chickens (USDA 2011a; 2011b). Though hundreds of slaughterhouses actively contributed to these totals, more than half of the cattle just mentioned were killed at just fourteen plants. A slightly greater percentage of hogs was killed at only twelve (USDA 2011a). Chickens were processed in a total of three hundred and ten federally inspected facilities (USDA 2011b), which means that if every facility operated at the same capacity, each would have slaughtered over fifty-three birds per minute (nearly one per second) in every minute of every day, adding up to more than twenty-eight million apiece over the course of twelve months.1 Incredible as these figures may seem, 2010 was an average year for agricultural animals. Indeed, for nearly a decade now the total number of birds and mammals killed annually in the US has come in at or above the nine billion mark, and such enormous totals are possible only by virtue of the existence of an equally enormous network of industrialized agricultural suppliers. These high-volume farming operations – dubbed “factory farms” by the general public, or “Concentrated Animal Feeding Operations (CAFOs)” by state and federal agencies – are defined by the ways in which they restrict animals’ movements and behaviors, locate more and more bodies in less and less space, and increasingly mechanize many aspects of traditional husbandry.
    [Show full text]
  • Whether and Where to Give1 (Forthcoming in Philosophy and Public Affairs)
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by St Andrews Research Repository 1 Whether and Where to Give1 (Forthcoming in Philosophy and Public Affairs) Theron Pummer University of St Andrews 1. The Ethics of Giving and Effective Altruism The ethics of giving has traditionally focused on whether, and how much, to give to charities helping people in extreme poverty.2 In more recent years, the discussion has increasingly focused on where to give, spurred by an appreciation of the substantial differences in cost- effectiveness between charities. According to a commonly cited example, $40,000 can be used either to help 1 blind person by training a seeing-eye dog in the United States or to help 2,000 blind people by providing surgeries reversing the effects of trachoma in Africa.3 Effective altruists recommend that we give large sums to charity, but by far their more central message is that we give effectively, i.e., to whatever charities would do the most good per dollar donated.4 In this paper, I’ll assume that it’s not wrong not to give bigger, but will explore to what extent it may well nonetheless be wrong not to give better. The main claim I’ll argue for here is that in many cases it would be wrong of you to give a sum of money to charities that do less good than others you could have given to instead, even if 1 I am extremely grateful to Derek Parfit, Roger Crisp, Jeff McMahan, and Peter Singer for extremely helpful feedback and encouragement.
    [Show full text]
  • Han Feizi's Criticism of Confucianism and Its Implications for Virtue Ethics
    JOURNAL OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY Journal of Moral Philosophy 5 (2008) 423–453 www.brill.nl/jmp Han Feizi’s Criticism of Confucianism and its Implications for Virtue Ethics * Eric L. Hutton Department of Philosophy, University of Utah, 215 S. Central Campus Drive, CTIHB, 4th fl oor, Salt Lake City, UT 84112, USA [email protected] Abstract Several scholars have recently proposed that Confucianism should be regarded as a form of virtue ethics. Th is view off ers new approaches to understanding not only Confucian thinkers, but also their critics within the Chinese tradition. For if Confucianism is a form of virtue ethics, we can then ask to what extent Chinese criticisms of it parallel criticisms launched against contemporary virtue ethics, and what lessons for virtue ethics in general might be gleaned from the challenges to Confucianism in particular. Th is paper undertakes such an exercise in examining Han Feizi, an early critic of Confucianism. Th e essay off ers a careful interpretation of the debate between Han Feizi and the Confucians and suggests that thinking through Han Feizi’s criticisms and the possible Confucian responses to them has a broader philosophical payoff , namely by highlighting a problem for current defenders of virtue ethics that has not been widely noticed, but deserves attention. Keywords Bernard Williams, Chinese philosophy, Confucianism, Han Feizi, Rosalind Hursthouse, virtue ethics Although Confucianism is now almost synonymous with Chinese culture, over the course of history it has also attracted many critics from among the Chinese themselves. Of these critics, one of the most interesting is Han Feizi (ca.
    [Show full text]
  • Understanding Bernard Williams's Criticism of Aristotelian Naturalism
    UNDERSTANDING BERNARD WILLIAMS’S CRITICISM OF ARISTOTELIAN NATURALISM Michael Addison A Thesis Submitted for the Degree of MPhil at the University of St Andrews 2015 Full metadata for this item is available in St Andrews Research Repository at: http://research-repository.st-andrews.ac.uk/ Please use this identifier to cite or link to this item: http://hdl.handle.net/10023/9315 This item is protected by original copyright Understanding Bernard Williams’s Criticism of Aristotelian Naturalism. Michael Addison This thesis is submitted in partial fulfilment for the degree of MPhil at the University of St Andrews 19th November 2015 Abstract: In Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy (henceforth ELP) Williams claims that holding a naturalistic Aristotelian ethical theory is no longer an option for us—we cannot believe what Aristotle believed about human beings. It is the purpose of this thesis to understand what Williams means by this claim and to evaluate whether or not it constitutes a pressing argument against Aristotelian naturalism. The modern Aristotelian (represented here by Martha Nussbaum, Philippa Foot and Rosalind Hursthouse) seems to be untouched by the claim as presented—they do not have to hold Aristotle’s view of human nature. The Aristotelian approaches human nature, not from an “outside” perspective, like the scientist, but from an “inside” perspective—from the point of view of an ethically engaged agent. The method does not seek to use a theory-independent notion of human nature to vindicate the Aristotelian claim that the properly functioning human being is virtuous. Rather, the Aristotelian is engaged in a project of using the notions of virtue that we already possess, to paint a picture of the kind of lives that we can all identify with, and endorse as properly functioning.
    [Show full text]
  • RICHARD HARE 07 Hare 1226 15/11/2004 10:29 Page 117
    07 Hare 1226 15/11/2004 10:29 Page 116 RICHARD HARE 07 Hare 1226 15/11/2004 10:29 Page 117 Richard Mervyn Hare 1919–2002 RICHARD HARE left behind at his death a long essay titled ‘APhilosophical Autobiography’, which has since been published.1 Its opening is striking: I had a strange dream, or half-waking vision, not long ago. I found myself at the top of a mountain in the mist, feeling very pleased with myself, not just for having climbed the mountain, but for having achieved my life’s ambition, to find a way of answering moral questions rationally. But as I was preening myself on this achievement, the mist began to clear, and I saw that I was surrounded on the mountain top by the graves of all those other philosophers, great and small, who had had the same ambition, and thought they had achieved it. And I have come to see, reflecting on my dream, that, ever since, the hard-working philo- sophical worms had been nibbling away at their systems and showing that the achievement was an illusion. Yet his imagination could also be less modest: a gaggle of moral philoso- phers is trapped beneath the earth in a smoke-filled chamber; they talk at cross purposes, and refuse to take the way out into the open air that he alone has discovered. It was his ambition to have united elements from Aristotle, Kant, and Mill in a logically cogent way that solved the funda- mental problems of ethics (though with unfinished business); and he usu- ally believed himself to have achieved this.
    [Show full text]
  • “Human Being” a Moral Concept?
    QQ version – Oct. 26, 2010 Is “Human Being” a Moral Concept? Douglas MacLean Is “human being” a moral concept? I believe it is, which makes me a speciesist. Speciesism violates a moral principle of equality. Peter Singer defines it as “a prejudice or attitude of bias toward the interests of members of one’s own species and against those of members of other species.” He compares it to racism. My goal in this essay is to defend a speciesist attitude or outlook on morality. This defense consists in little more than sympathetically describing certain intuitions and exploring some of their implications. I have no further argument to show that this view is true or correct; in fact, I don’t know what such an argument would look like. As I see it, each side in debates about speciesism reveals different assumptions or begs different questions about the foundation of ethics. Critics of speciesism see ethics as grounded in status-conferring individual properties that generate agent-neutral reasons. The outlook I will describe is based on a conviction that ethics is inextricably tied to practices that define what it is to live a human life. The most general reasons in this conception of morality are human reasons. They are norms for creatures like us, but not necessarily for gods, intelligent aliens, or other possible agents. They are not agent-neutral. By defending a speciesist outlook on morality I do not mean to suggest that animal suffering has no moral significance. A decent human life takes seriously things like cruelty, callousness, or indifference to the natural world.
    [Show full text]
  • Bernard Williams on Ethical Theory
    Bernard Williams on Ethical Theory A Study of Bernard Williams' Critique of Ethical Theory and its Implications for doing Moral Philosophy Ivo R. Kreft A thesis submitted to the Department of Philosophy in conformity with the requirements for the degree of Master of Arts Queen's University Kingston, Ontario, Canada January 1998 copyright 8 Ivo R. Kreft, 1998 National Library Bibliothey nationale d Canada du Cana a Acquisitions and Acquisitions et Bibliographie Services services bibliographiques 395 Wellkqton Street 395, rue Wellington ûttawaûN K1AOiU4 Onawa ON KIA ON4 Canada Canada The author has granted a non- L'auteur a accordé une licence non exclusive licence dowing the exclusive permettant a la National Library of Canada to Bibliothèque nationale du Canada de reproduce, loan, distriiute or seLi reproduire, prêter, distribuer ou copies of this thesis in microform, vendre des copies de cette thèse sous paper or electronic formats. la forme de microfiche/fïlm, de reproduction sur papier ou sur format électronique. The author retains ownership of the L'auteur conserve la propriété du copyright in this thesis. Neither the droit d'auteur qui protège cette thése. thesis nor substantial extracts fkom it Ni la thèse ni des extraits substantiels may be printed or otherwise de celle-ci ne doivent être imprimés reproduced without the author's ou autrement reproduits sans son permission. autorisation. Abstract This thesis will evaluate the effect Bernard Williams' critique of ethical theory has on moral philosophy, and defend the view that although Williams has shown the inadequacies of theory, moral philosophy cm still enquire into the nature of ethics and produce substantive results.
    [Show full text]
  • Public Health Ethics: Global Cases, Practice, and Context
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Springer - Publisher Connector Chapter 1 Public Health Ethics: Global Cases, Practice, and Context Leonard W. Ortmann , Drue H. Barrett , Carla Saenz , Ruth Gaare Bernheim , Angus Dawson , Jo A. Valentine , and Andreas Reis 1.1 Introduction Introducing public health ethics poses two special challenges. First, it is a relatively new fi eld that combines public health and practical ethics . Its unfamiliarity requires considerable explanation, yet its scope and emergent qualities make delineation dif- fi cult. Moreover, while the early development of public health ethics occurred in a Western context, its reach, like public health itself, has become global. A second challenge, then, is to articulate an approach specifi c enough to provide clear The opinions, fi ndings, and conclusions of the authors do not necessarily refl ect the offi cial posi- tion, views, or policies of the editors, the editors’ host institutions, or the authors’ host institutions. L. W. Ortmann , PhD (*) • D. H. Barrett , PhD Offi ce of Scientifi c Integrity, Offi ce of the Associate Director for Science, Offi ce of the Director , Centers for Disease Control and Prevention , Atlanta , GA , USA e-mail: [email protected] C. Saenz , PhD Regional Program on Bioethics, Offi ce of Knowledge Management, Bioethics, and Research , Pan American Health Organization , Washington , DC , USA R. G. Bernheim , JD, MPH Department of Public Health Sciences , University of Virginia , Charlottesville , VA , USA A. Dawson , PhD Center for Values, Ethics and the Law in Medicine, Sydney School of Public Health , The University of Sydney , Sydney , Australia J.
    [Show full text]