Evolutionary Biology: a Basic Science for Psychiatry?

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Evolutionary Biology: a Basic Science for Psychiatry? Review article Evolutionary biology: a basic science for psychiatry? McGuire MT, Marks I, Nesse RM, Troisi A. Evolutionary biology: a M. T. McGuire’, I, Marks’, R. M. Nesse3, basic science for psychiatry? A. Troisi4 Acta Psychiatr Scand 1992: 86: 89-96. ’ Department of Psychiatry-Biobehavioral Sciences, School of Medicine, University of California at Los Angeles, USA, Institute of Psychiatry, DeCrispigny Park, London, United Kingdom, Department of Psychiatry, School of Medicine, University of Michigan, Ann Arbor, Michigan, USA, Clinica Psychiatrica, Universita di Roma, Italy Evolutionary biology has much to offer psychiatry. It distinguishes between Key words: evolutionary biology: psfchiatric ultimate and proximate explanations of behavior and addresses the theory; psychiatric research functional significance of behavior. Subtheories, frequently voiced Michael T. McGuire, Department of misconceptions, specific applications, testable hypotheses and limitations Psychiatry-Biobehavioral Sciences, School of of evolutionary theory are reviewed. An evolutionary perspective is likely to Medicine, University of California at Los Angeles, improve understanding of psychopathology, refocus some clinical 760 Westwood Plaza, Los Angeles, CA research, influence treatment and help integrate seemingly unrelated 90024, USA findings and theoretical explanations. Accepted for publication February 29, 1992 ory can be found in Williams (l), Wilson (2) and Introduction Alexander (3). Recent advances in evolutionary biology have im- plications for psychiatric theory, research and clin- Overview of the evolutionary approach to psychiatry ical practice. Evolutionary theory introduces a broad Behavior and much needed deductive framework; it facilitates the functional analysis of behavior; it identifies im- Consider behaviors such as acquiring a mate, sexual portant differences between ultimate causes and intercourse, having offspring, parent-offspring bond- proximate mechanisms; it promotes a reassessment ing, stranger anxiety, infant and juvenile play, sibling of current views about etiology and pathogenesis; rivalry, competition over resources, preferential in- and it alters treatment strategies and options. Evo- vestment of resources in kin, reciprocal exchanges lutionists acknowledge that much human behavior is among nonkin, competition for social status, recog- a product of personal and cultural experience, but nition and rejection of cheaters, deception of others argue that mind and culture themselves are products and self-deception. Natural selection has shaped of evolution and are better understood when ana- predispositions (strong biases) to engage in such be- lyzed within the evolutionary framework. haviors. Predispositions range from strong (such as Our assessment of the contributions that an evo- withdrawal from a painful stimulus) to weak (such lutionary point of view can make to psychiatry be- as preference for particular styles of music). gins with an analysis of its theoretical contributions The strengths of predispositions vary across indi- followed by a discussion of common misconcep- viduals. Experience and learning, which is also an tions. Possible applications to psychiatry are then evolved capacity, modify predispositions. Environ- evaluated. Finally, the limitations of the theory are mental options and constraints interact with evolved reviewed. and prioritized behavior strategies to affect the prob- Only selected parts of evolutionary theory are dis- ability of immediate and long-term behavior. Psy- cussed. More comprehensive discussion of the the- chological mechanisms (such as cognitive and psy- 89 McGuire et al. chodynamic ones) filter, modify, organize and focus responsible for that predisposition. Kin-selection information that influences behavior. Behaviors to theory explains how altruistic behavior among kin which most persons are not predisposed (such as facilitates the replication of genes shared by kin. The playing the piano) can be mastered, but usually after theory predicts, for example: that parents will invest considerable effort. Nonetheless, the general behav- more in their orspring than vice versa; that such ior profiles and patterns of human behavior are set investment is greater with higher parental assess- by the species’ genome and, within limits, unfold in ment of the offspring’s reproductive potential; and predictable ways. that stepchildren are more likely to be abused that The above and other behaviors are of special in- biological offspring. These predictions are well sup- terest to psychiatry for several reasons: 1) mental ported by evidence (17-19). disorders are associated with detectable abnormal- ities in the expression of such behaviors, such as Reciprocal altruism. Although kin selection explains reduced frequency of reciprocation (4-6); 2) an ad- investment in kin, unrelated individuals also help equate understanding of some mental disorders (such each other (20). Such reciprocity exchanges are not as phobias, depression and somatoform disorders) confined to humans. Vampire bats, for example, requires an appreciation of the functional signifi- share their blood meals after returning to their roost cance of such behaviors and of the evolved mecha- at dawn (21). Such exchanges even occur between nisms that regulate them (7, 8); and 3) treatment species (22); alarm calls by one species alert mem- strategies may change (for example greater empha- bers of other species, and cleaner fish remove par- sis on functional outcomes and increased attention asites from inside the mouths and gills of larger fish to environmental variables) with increasing appre- who protect cleaners from predation (23). ciation of the evolutionary perspective. Reciprocal altruism theory predicts: 1) A will help Natural selection favors brain mechanisms that B (nonkin) if, in A’s view, the probability of recip- result in behaviors conferring a reproductive advan- rocation by B times the probable benefit of this re- tage. Generally, such behaviors are neither atypical ciprocation equals or exceeds the initial cost to A nor pathological. With few exceptions, however, (reciprocal behavior is distinguished for mutualism, mental disorders are atypical, pathological and mal- where both parties gain simultaneously); 2) failure to adaptive. Evolutionary theory provides a framework reciprocate evokes moralistic aggression; 3) nonre- for analyzing adaptive behavior, the mechanisms ciprocation will rise at the end of a period of asso- that regulate it and the circumstances interfering with ciation (24); and 4) nonreciprocators will have fewer its normal expression (9). Psychopathology can be allies. These predictions are also supported by avail- illuminated by insights into its normal adaptive pre- able evidence (25,26). cursors. Most phobias, for example, are exaggerated Evolutionary theory also explains why such emo- normal fears (10, 11); minor adaptive rituals such tions as pride, happiness, guilt and moralistic anger as perfectionism are precursors for obsessive-com- and such behaviors as guilt induction, intimidation pulsive disorder (10); normal mood swings can be and social ostracism have evolved. They facilitate viewed as precursors for manic-depressive illness reciprocal relationships (20, 25, 27, 28). Much of (12); and normal sadness and social withdrawal may development and learning deals with refining recip- be precursors to clinical depression (13-15). rocal behaviors, such as how to successfully manage reciprocity exchanges without being exploited or re- Subt heories jected - battles among children often focus on who owes what to whom (29). Deviations from expected Since the early 1960s, a number of testable subthe- patterns of early kin and non-kin social relationships ories have been developed to explain specific behav- may contribute to disordered reciprocity relation- iors. Examples include: inclusive fitness or kin se- ships later in life (30). lection, reciprocal altruism, parent-offspring conflict, and cognitive/feeling mechanisms. Parent-ofspring conyict and sibling rivilary. Although cooperation between parents, offspring and siblings Inclusive fitness. Preferential investment in kin is is promoted by the genes they share in common, prominent in humans, as it is in other species. The conflicts can be explained by the fact that many of tendency is to invest more in close than in distant their genes are not shared (31). Parental fitness (the kin, and for parents to invest more in offspring than number .of parental genes replicated among off- vice versa. Hamilton (16) postulated that certain spring) is enhanced by the reduction of investment kin-related behavior is selected because it favors in- in maturing offspring in order to sooner reproduce dividuals who share genes. A behavior costly to the again. Existing offspring try to counter this reduction self may nevertheless evolve if it increases the sur- and maximize their own fitness by delaying the birth vival and reproduction of kin who share the genes of new siblings and by extracting as much from par- 90 Evolutionary psychobiology ents as they can. The tendency in many species for such mechanisms may help to explain some anxiety offspring to object to weaning supports this view. disorders. In other disorders, deficits in mechanisms The conflict has a natural end-point when existing for reciprocity negotiation seem probable. Such def- offspring’s inclusive fitness is increased more by hav- icits may be a product of proximate mechanisms ing a sibling with
Recommended publications
  • Interim Report IR-05-079 Evolution of Indirect Reciprocity
    International Institute for Tel: +43 2236 807 342 Applied Systems Analysis Fax: +43 2236 71313 Schlossplatz 1 E-mail: [email protected] A-2361 Laxenburg, Austria Web: www.iiasa.ac.at Interim Report IR-05-079 Evolution of Indirect Reciprocity Martin A. Nowak ([email protected]) Karl Sigmund ([email protected]) Approved by Ulf Dieckmann Program Leader, ADN December 2005 Interim Reports on work of the International Institute for Applied Systems Analysis receive only limited review. Views or opinions expressed herein do not necessarily represent those of the Institute, its National Member Organizations, or other organizations supporting the work. IIASA STUDIES IN ADAPTIVE DYNAMICS NO. 111 The Adaptive Dynamics Network at IIASA fosters the develop- ment of new mathematical and conceptual techniques for under- standing the evolution of complex adaptive systems. Focusing on these long-term implications of adaptive processes in systems of limited growth, the Adaptive Dynamics Network brings together scientists and institutions from around the world with IIASA acting as the central node. Scientific progress within the network is collected in the IIASA ADN Studies in Adaptive Dynamics series. No. 1 Metz JAJ, Geritz SAH, Meszéna G, Jacobs FJA, van No. 11 Geritz SAH, Metz JAJ, Kisdi É, Meszéna G: The Dy- Heerwaarden JS: Adaptive Dynamics: A Geometrical Study namics of Adaptation and Evolutionary Branching. IIASA of the Consequences of Nearly Faithful Reproduction. IIASA Working Paper WP-96-077 (1996). Physical Review Letters Working Paper WP-95-099 (1995). van Strien SJ, Verduyn 78:2024-2027 (1997). Lunel SM (eds): Stochastic and Spatial Structures of Dynami- cal Systems, Proceedings of the Royal Dutch Academy of Sci- No.
    [Show full text]
  • Strong Reciprocity and the Roots of Human Morality
    Soc Just Res DOI 10.1007/s11211-008-0067-y Strong Reciprocity and the Roots of Human Morality Herbert Gintis Æ Joseph Henrich Æ Samuel Bowles Æ Robert Boyd Æ Ernst Fehr Ó Springer Science+Business Media, LLC 2008 Abstract Human morality is a key evolutionary adaptation on which human social behavior has been based since the Pleistocene era. Ethical behavior is constitutive of human nature, we argue, and human morality is as important an adaptation as human cognition and speech. Ethical behavior, we assert, need not be a means toward personal gain. Because of our nature as moral beings, humans take pleasure in acting ethically and are pained when acting unethically. From an evolutionary viewpoint, we argue that ethical behavior was fitness-enhancing in the years marking the emergence of Homo sapiens because human groups with many altruists fared better than groups of selfish individuals, and the fitness losses sustained by altruists were more than compensated by the superior performance of the groups in which they congregated. Keywords Morality Á Human nature Á Evolution Á Reciprocity Á Sociobiology Á Altruism H. Gintis (&) Santa Fe Institute, Santa Fe, New Mexico and, The Central European University, Budapest, Hungary e-mail: [email protected] J. Henrich University of British Columbia, Vancouver, Canada S. Bowles Santa Fe Institute, Santa Fe, NM, USA R. Boyd University of California, Los Angeles, CA, USA E. Fehr University of Zurich, Zurich, Switzerland 123 Soc Just Res The Nature of Human Morality The two volumes under review summarize a body of research suggesting that human morality is a key evolutionary adaptation on which human social behavior has been based since the Pleistocene era.
    [Show full text]
  • Evolution of Direct Reciprocity Under Uncertainty Can Explain Human Generosity in One-Shot Encounters
    Evolution of direct reciprocity under uncertainty can explain human generosity in one-shot encounters Andrew W. Deltona,b,1,2, Max M. Krasnowa,b,1,2, Leda Cosmidesa,b, and John Toobya,c aCenter for Evolutionary Psychology and Departments of bPsychology and cAnthropology, University of California, Santa Barbara, CA 93106 Edited by Kenneth Binmore, University College London, London WC1E 6BT, United Kingdom and accepted by the Editorial Board May 27, 2011 (received for review February 9, 2011) Are humans too generous? The discovery that subjects choose to proven equally challenging to biologists, because they seem to incur costs to allocate benefits to others in anonymous, one-shot violate the expectations of widely accepted models of fitness economic games has posed an unsolved challenge to models of maximization that predict selfishness in the absence of either economic and evolutionary rationality. Using agent-based simu- (i) genetic relatedness, (ii) conditions favoring reciprocity, or lations, we show that such generosity is the necessary byproduct (iii) reputation enhancement (22). of selection on decision systems for regulating dyadic reciprocity The most glaring anomaly stems from the fact that, according to under conditions of uncertainty. In deciding whether to engage in both evolutionary and economic theories of cooperation, whether dyadic reciprocity, these systems must balance (i) the costs of mis- an interaction is repeated or one-shot should make a crucial dif- taking a one-shot interaction for a repeated interaction (hence, ference in how agents act. The chance of repeated interactions risking a single chance of being exploited) with (ii) the far greater offers the only possibility of repayment for forgoing immediate costs of mistaking a repeated interaction for a one-shot interaction selfish gains when the interactants are not relatives and the situ- (thereby precluding benefits from multiple future cooperative ation precludes reputation enhancement in the eyes of third par- interactions).
    [Show full text]
  • Competition Among Cooperators: Altruism and Reciprocity
    Colloquium Competition among cooperators: Altruism and reciprocity Peter Danielson* Centre for Applied Ethics, University of British Columbia, Vancouver, BC, Canada V6T 1Z2 Levine argues that neither self-interest nor altruism explains ex- quite widely, to include sometimes counterintuitive possibilities. perimental results in bargaining and public goods games. Subjects’ [This is the critical justification for Binmore’s (6) harsh criticism preferences appear also to be sensitive to their opponents’ per- of Axelrod (2, 7).] In particular, when we specify the mechanisms ceived altruism. Sethi and Somanathan provide a general account of reciprocity, we shall see that they have surprises in store for of reciprocal preferences that survive under evolutionary pressure. us (8). Although a wide variety of reciprocal strategies pass this evolu- The present paper runs a similar line of inquiry with a new tionary test, Sethi and Somanthan conjecture that fewer are likely starting point. We begin with Levine’s account of human coop- to survive when reciprocal strategies compete with each other. erative behavior in experiments using bargaining and public This paper develops evolutionary agent-based models to test their goods games. Although it is commonly agreed that self-interest conjecture in cases where reciprocal preferences can differ in a will not account for these experimental results, Levine goes variety of games. We confirm that reciprocity is necessary but not further and argues that simple altruism is also inadequate. A sufficient for optimal cooperation. We explore the theme of better fit is obtained from preferences that are sensitive to one’s competition among reciprocal cooperators and display three in- opponents’ perceived altruism.
    [Show full text]
  • The Reciprocity Controversy Gerald Carter1*
    Sciknow Publications Ltd. ABC 2014, 1(3):368-386 Animal Behavior and Cognition DOI: 10.12966/abc.08.11.2014 ©Attribution 3.0 Unported (CC BY 3.0) The Reciprocity Controversy Gerald Carter1* 1University of Maryland *Corresponding author (Email:[email protected]) Citation – Carter, G. (2014). The reciprocity controversy. Animal Behavior and Cognition, 1(3), 368-386. doi: 10.12966/abc.08.11.2014 Abstract - Reciprocity (or ―reciprocal altruism‖) was once considered an important and widespread evolutionary explanation for cooperation, yet many reviews now conclude that it is rare or absent outside of humans. Here, I show that nonhuman reciprocity seems rare mainly because its meaning has changed over time. The original broad concept of reciprocity is well supported by evidence, but subsequent divergent uses of the term have relied on various translations of the strategy ‗tit-for-tat‘ in the repeated Prisoner‘s Dilemma game. This model has resulted in four problematic approaches to defining and testing reciprocity. Authors that deny evidence of nonhuman reciprocity tend to (1) assume that it requires sophisticated cognition, (2) focus exclusively on short-term contingency with a single partner, (3) require paradoxical evidence for a temporary lifetime fitness cost, and (4) assume that responses to investments are fixed. While these restrictions basically define reciprocity out of existence, evidence shows that fungi, plants, fish, birds, rats, and primates enforce mutual benefit by contingently altering their cooperative investments based on the cooperative returns, just as predicted by the original reciprocity theory. Keywords – Cooperation, Prisoner‘s Dilemma, Pseudoreciprocity, Reciprocity, Reciprocal altruism Comparative psychologists, evolutionary psychologists, and behavioral ecologists often study cooperation using different theories and methods, asking questions at different levels of analysis.
    [Show full text]
  • The Psychology of Reciprocal Altruism Jeffrey R. Stevens and Juan F
    The psychology of reciprocal altruism Jeffrey R. Stevens and Juan F. Duque Author information Jeffrey R. Stevens University of Nebraska-Lincoln Lincoln, Nebraska, USA [email protected] Juan F. Duque University of Nebraska-Lincoln Lincoln, Nebraska, USA [email protected] Synonyms Reciprocity Definition Different forms of reciprocal altruism—taking turns offering altruistic help—require different psychological building blocks. Stevens, J.R. and Duque, J.F. (2016). The psychology of reciprocal altruism. In T.K. Shackelford & V.A. Weekes-Shackelford (Eds.), Encyclopedia of evolutionary psychological science. New York: Springer. doi:10.1007/978-3-319-16999-6_3051-1 1 Introduction A pair of pied flycatchers busily snatch insects to bring back to their nest and feed to their young. Suddenly, an owl appears close to the nest, posing a serious predation threat to their offspring. The pair fly straight to the owl, shrieking and dive bombing it to chase it away. A nearby pair of flycatchers detects the ruckus and also arrives to attack the predator. Another nearby pair, however, fails to help. An hour later, two owls appear, one at each of the neighboring nests. What should the original pair do? Krams, Krama, Igaune, and Mänd (2008) conducted this experiment and found that, out of 32 pairs of flycatchers, 2 stayed at the nest, 30 attacked the owl near the pair who helped them previously, and none attacked the owl near the pair who did not help them before. This willingness to pay a cost to cooperate or help another who has helped you before is called reciprocal altruism or reciprocity.
    [Show full text]
  • The Normative Source of Modern Tort Law
    HIDDEN IN PLAIN SIGHT: THE NORMATIVE SOURCE OF MODERN TORT LAW MARK A. GEISTFELD* According to conventional wisdom, the normative source of modern tort law is mysterious. The reasons trace back to the state of nature. In a world without cen- tralized government, individuals protected themselves by exacting talionic revenge—“an eye for an eye”—on their injurers. These customary norms of behavior were the source of the early common law, but tort scholars have assumed that they were merely a barbaric punitive practice without any relevance to the modern tort system. This field of the common law had to be normatively recreated, making it “modern.” The resultant body of tort law depends, as Oliver Wendell Holmes famously concluded, on “more or less definitely understood matters of policy.” The policies in question, however, have never been clearly identified. Courts and scholars continue to disagree about the norms that generate the behav- ioral obligations of modern tort law. The normative source of modern tort law has been hidden in plain sight because of this widely held but mistaken understanding of legal history. Contrary to conven- tional wisdom, the state of nature was governed by a reciprocity norm of equitable balance that has survived the evolving demands of the modern tort system. In cases of accidental harm, the reciprocity norm often took the form of a compensatory obligation requiring “the value of an eye for an eye.” This norm was initially adopted and then further developed by the early common law. Courts subsequently invoked the reciprocity norm in the late nineteenth and early twentieth centuries to justify rules of negligence and strict liability.
    [Show full text]
  • The Psychology of Revenge and Deterrence
    68 The Scholar “Blunt Not the Heart, Enrage It” The Psychology of Revenge and Deterrence Rose McDermott, PhD | Anthony C. Lopez, PhD | Peter K. Hatemi, PhD Texas National Security Review: Volume 1, Issue 1 (December 2017) Print: ISSN 2576-1021 Online: ISSN 2576-1153 69 Malcolm Dispute it like a man. Macduff I shall do so; But I must also feel it as a man: I cannot but remember such things were, That were most precious to me. — Did heaven look on, And would not take their part? Sinful Macduff, They were all struck for thee! naught that I am, Not for their own demerits, but for mine, Fell slaughter on their souls: heaven rest them now! Malcolm Be this the whetstone of your sword. Let grief Convert to anger; blunt not the heart, enrage it. - Macbeth, William Shakespeare Why is the instinct for vengeance so strong the threat of future exploitation. even when it is clear that widespread death and As long as humans have lived and competed destruction would be a much more likely outcome in groups, the question of deterring threats from than any kind of “victory”? In the event of a nuclear one’s adversaries has been of central importance. war, why is second-strike retaliation so certain Humanity’s progression from living in small hunter- when it may gain nothing of social or material value? gatherer tribes where everyone knew one another We believe these things because humans share a to nation-states with millions of people has, in universal thirst for retaliation in the face of threat many cases, magnified the stakes of the challenge and in the wake of loss, no matter what classical rather than altered its fundamental dynamics.
    [Show full text]