Logical Empiricism and Pragmatism (Vienna Circle Institute Yearbook Vol
Total Page:16
File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb
Load more
Recommended publications
-
Discovery and the Rationality of Science
Loyola University Chicago Loyola eCommons Dissertations Theses and Dissertations 1985 Discovery and the Rationality of Science William S. Hill Loyola University Chicago Follow this and additional works at: https://ecommons.luc.edu/luc_diss Part of the Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Hill, William S., "Discovery and the Rationality of Science" (1985). Dissertations. 2434. https://ecommons.luc.edu/luc_diss/2434 This Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by the Theses and Dissertations at Loyola eCommons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Dissertations by an authorized administrator of Loyola eCommons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-Noncommercial-No Derivative Works 3.0 License. Copyright © 1985 William S. Hill DISCOVERY AND THE RATIONALITY OF SCIENCE by Wiliam S. Hill A Dissertation Submitted to the Faculty of the Graduate School of Loyola University of Chicago in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy August 1985 TABLE OF CONTENTS Page ACKNOWLEDGMENTS • . ii VITA • • • • • • • • • • • · • • • iii Chapter I. INTRODUCTION . 1 Discovery as a Direction for Philosophy of Science • • • • • • • . • . • . 1 The Justification Approach to Philosophy of Science . 2 The Discovery Alternative . • . • . • . • • 6 II. THE IMPLICATIONS OF THEORY-LADENNESS FOR THE HISTORY AND RATIONALITY OF SCIENCE. • • • • 10 Normal Science. • • . • . • . • . • • • • . • • 12 Revolutionary Science • • • • • • • . • • • 16 Kuhn's Historical Method. • . • . • . • . • . 20 The Success of Kuhn's Replacement • . • • . 22 III. THE IMPLICATIONS OF THEORY-LADENNESS FOR THE STABILITY OF EVIDENCE IN SCIENCE. • . • . • • • 29 Relative Stability of Observation Terms . • • . 32 The "Useh Criterion for the Theory-Observation Distinction • • • • . • . • . • . • . • • . 37 The Problem of Circularity. • . 43 IV. -
Joseph Fletcher the Father of Biomedical Ethics by Richard Taylor
L J Spring 1984 Vol. 4, No. 2 Joseph Fletcher The Father of Biomedical Ethics by Richard Taylor Special Features The Foundations of Religious liberty Carl Henry, Father Ernest Fortin, Paul Kurtz, and Lee Nisbet God and the New Physics Mario Bunge, Mendel Sachs, and Paul Davies Plus: Floyd Matson, Matthew Ies Spetter, Richard Kostelanetz, and Nicholas Capaldi SPRING 1984 ISSN 0272-0701 VOL. 4, NO. 2 Contents 3 LETTERS TO THE EDITOR SAVE OUR CHILDREN 4 Christian Science, Faith Healing,, and the Law Rita Swan 10 Ultrafundamentalist Sects and Child Abuse Lowell D. Streiker 17 Joseph Fletcher: The Father of Biomedical Ethics Richard Taylor THE FOUNDATIONS OF RELIGIOUS LIBERTY AND DEMOCRACY 20 Religious Liberty: Cornerstone of Human Rights Carl F. H. Henry 27 Democracy Without Theology Paul Kurtz 32 Is Liberal Democracy Really Christian? Ernest Fortin 35 Father Fortins Protestant Politics Lee Nisbet 38 Biblical Views of Sex: Blessing or Handicap? Jeffrey J. W. Baker 41 A Naturalistic Basis for Morality John Kekes BIBLICAL CRITICISM 44 On Miracles Randel Helms HUMANIST SELF-PORTRAITS 46 A Humanist Credo Matthew les Specter 47 The Distinctions of Humanism Richard Kosielanetz 48 Humane-ism Floyd Matson VIEWPOINTS 49 Moral Absolutes and Foreign Policy Nicholas Capaldi 50 The Vatican Ambassador Edd Doerr BOOKS 52 God and the Physicists Mario Bunge, Mendel Sachs, and Paul Davies 51 POETRY 60 ON THE BARRICADES 62 CLASSIFIED Cover art courtesy of the Buffalo and Erie County Public Library and AP/Wide World Edirur: Paul Kurtz -I ssueiare Editors: Gordon Stein, Lee Nisbet l s.sistartt Editors: Doris Doyle, Andrea Szalanski Ir, Director: Gregory Lyde Vigrass Contributing Editors: Lionel Abel, author, critic, SUNY at Buffalo; Paul Beattie, president, Fellowship of Religious Humanists; Jo-Ann Boydston, director, Dewey Center; Laurence Briskman, lecturer. -
John Dewey, Historiography, and the Practice of History. Seth J
East Tennessee State University Digital Commons @ East Tennessee State University Electronic Theses and Dissertations Student Works 5-2009 John Dewey, Historiography, and the Practice of History. Seth J. Bartee East Tennessee State University Follow this and additional works at: https://dc.etsu.edu/etd Part of the Other History Commons Recommended Citation Bartee, Seth J., "John Dewey, Historiography, and the Practice of History." (2009). Electronic Theses and Dissertations. Paper 1859. https://dc.etsu.edu/etd/1859 This Thesis - Open Access is brought to you for free and open access by the Student Works at Digital Commons @ East Tennessee State University. It has been accepted for inclusion in Electronic Theses and Dissertations by an authorized administrator of Digital Commons @ East Tennessee State University. For more information, please contact [email protected]. John Dewey, Historiography, and the Practice of History _____________________ A thesis presented to the faculty of the Department in History East Tennessee State University In partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree Masters of Arts in History _____________________ by Seth J. Bartee May 2009 _____________________ Dr. Melvin E. Page, Chair Dr. Daniel Newcomer Dr. William Burgess Dr. Stephen Fritz Keywords: John Dewey, Pragmatism, Historiography, Personhood, Instrumentalism ABSTRACT John Dewey, Historiography, and the Practice of History by Seth J. Bartee John Dewey was America‟s foremost authority on many of the critical issues in the twentieth century. Dewey dedicated his professional career as an expert on the major branches of philosophy. A neglected aspect of Dewey‟s philosophy is his writings on historiography, the philosophy of history, and his influence on American historians. -
Neoconservatism: Origins and Evolution, 1945 – 1980
Neoconservatism: Origins and Evolution, 1945 – 1980 Robert L. Richardson, Jr. A dissertation submitted to the faculty of the University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in the Department of History. Chapel Hill 2009 Approved by, Michael H. Hunt, Chair Richard Kohn Timothy McKeown Nancy Mitchell Roger Lotchin Abstract Robert L. Richardson, Jr. Neoconservatism: Origins and Evolution, 1945 – 1985 (Under the direction of Michael H. Hunt) This dissertation examines the origins and evolution of neoconservatism as a philosophical and political movement in America from 1945 to 1980. I maintain that as the exigencies and anxieties of the Cold War fostered new intellectual and professional connections between academia, government and business, three disparate intellectual currents were brought into contact: the German philosophical tradition of anti-modernism, the strategic-analytical tradition associated with the RAND Corporation, and the early Cold War anti-Communist tradition identified with figures such as Reinhold Niebuhr. Driven by similar aims and concerns, these three intellectual currents eventually coalesced into neoconservatism. As a political movement, neoconservatism sought, from the 1950s on, to re-orient American policy away from containment and coexistence and toward confrontation and rollback through activism in academia, bureaucratic and electoral politics. Although the neoconservatives were only partially successful in promoting their transformative project, their accomplishments are historically significant. More specifically, they managed to interject their views and ideas into American political and strategic thought, discredit détente and arms control, and shift U.S. foreign policy toward a more confrontational stance vis-à-vis the Soviet Union. -
The Pragmatic Turn in Philosophy
Introduction n recent years the classical authors of Anglo-Saxon pragmatism have gar- Inered a renewed importance in international philosophical circles. In the aftermath of the linguistic turn, philosophers such as Charles S. Peirce, William James, George H. Mead, Ferdinand C. S. Schiller, and John Dewey are being reread alongside, for example, recent postmodern and deconstructivist thought as alternatives to a traditional orientation toward the concerns of a represen- tationalist epistemology. In the context of contemporary continental thought, the work of Jacques Derrida, Jean-Francois Lyotard, and Gilles Deleuze comprises just a few examples of a culturewide assault on a metaphysical worldview premised on what Michel Foucault called the empirico-transcendental doublet, and presents a wealth of potential exchange with the pragmatist critique of representationalism. In both cases, aspects of pragmatist thought are being used to add flexibility to the conceptual tools of modern philoso- phy, in order to promote a style of philosophizing more apt to dealing with the problems of everyday life. The hope for a pragmatic “renewing of phi- losophy” (Putnam) evidenced in these trends has led to an analytic reexami- nation of some of the fundamental positions in modern continental thought as well, and to a recognition of previously unacknowledged or underappreciated pragmatic elements in thinkers like Kant, Hegel, Nietzsche, Heidegger, and Wittgenstein. Within the current analytic discussions, a wide spectrum of differing and at times completely heterogeneous forms of neopragmatism can be distinguished, which for heuristic purposes can be grouped into two general categories according to the type of discursive strategy employed. The first of these consists in a conscious inflation of the concept of pragmatism in order to establish it as widely as possible within the disciplinary discourse of philosophy. -
Medium-Term Strategic Plan of the Institute of Philosophy (2020–2023) 1A) Analysis of the External Environment the Situation
Medium-term Strategic Plan of the Institute of Philosophy (2020–2023) 1a) Analysis of the external environment The situation of the Institute has been determined by the fundamental science policy reform in the course of which the Research Centre for the Humanities changed its operational form. Instead of being a budgetary entity of the Public Body of the Hungarian Academy of Sciences (HAS), as of 1 September 2019, it continues to operate as a central budgetary entity directed by the Eötvös Loránd Research Network (ELRN). 1b) Review of the internal capacities The previous period (2016–2018) saw the creation of the first excellence research team within the Institute, which has had an important budget from funds, and which has studied the values underlying scientific research. We have published monographs about the philosophy of Kant, Hume, and Saint Augustine of Hippo, about quantum theory, logical empiricism, historical philosophy and other topics. In addition to the publication of Latin- and Hungarian-language sources, the Hungarian Philosophical Archives has also been launched, which contains documents and biographical data. The Institute is a founding member of the Artificial Intelligence Coalition. The Institute has increased its presence in international professional forums, as has been reflected – in addition to our publication activities – by the higher number of international conferences attended and organized in the recent period. In accordance with the broad interpretation of philosophy’s mission of usefulness for the community, the fellows of the Institute have been involved in public life extensively as well as in popular science and interdisciplinary activities, both through their lectures delivered in Hungary and abroad, and their media appearances and writings. -
26 Huttemann Love Reduction
View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by PhilPapers Reduction Andreas Hüttemann Alan C. Love Abstract Reduction and reductionism have been central philosophical topics in analytic philosophy of science for more than six decades. Together they encompass a diversity of issues from metaphysics and epistemology. This article provides an introduction to the topic that illuminates how contemporary epistemological discussions took their shape historically and limns the contours of concrete cases of reduction in specific natural sciences. The unity of science and the impulse to accomplish compositional reduction in accord with a layer-cake vision of the sciences, the seminal contributions of Ernest Nagel on theory reduction and how they strongly conditioned subsequent philosophical discussions, and the detailed issues pertaining to different accounts of reduction that arise in both physical and biological science (e.g., limit-case and part-whole reduction in physics, the difference-making principle in genetics, and mechanisms in molecular biology) are explored. The conclusion argues that the epistemological heterogeneity and patchwork organization of the natural sciences encourages a pluralist stance about reduction. Keywords composition, limit-case reduction, Ernest Nagel, mechanisms, part-whole reduction, theory reduction Reduction and reductionism have been central philosophical topics in analytic philosophy of science for more than six decades. Together they encompass a diversity of issues from metaphysics (e.g., physicalism and emergence) and epistemology (e.g., theory structure, 1 causal explanation, and methodology). “Reduction” usually refers to an asymmetrical relationship between two items (e.g., theories, explanations, properties, etc.) where one item is reduced to another. -
ABSTRACT Made in God's Image: a Multidisciplinary Study of Personhood and Faith Sarah C. Heady Director: Junius Johnson, Phd T
ABSTRACT Made in God’s Image: A Multidisciplinary Study of Personhood and Faith Sarah C. Heady Director: Junius Johnson, PhD The question "what is a person?" haunts countless disciplines and debates, from theology to neuroscience, abortion to artificial intelligence. For Christians to engage meaningfully in such areas in a way consistent with their religious ideals, they must have a carefully considered perspective on personhood. In this project, I present a model of how to consider such a challenging topic. I first establish a biblical anthropology consisting of twelve principles of personhood derived from Scripture. I next present three different perspectives on personhood – traditional theological, emergent, and reductionist – which originate from the disciplines of theology, sociology, and neuroscience, respectively. I analyze the compatibility of these three perspectives with the established biblical principles of personhood. From this, I conclude that the traditional theological perspective is most compatible with Scripture. However, I more significantly argue that one should adopt the perspective on personhood that bears the greatest consilience with both Scripture and other forms of knowledge, while giving priority to Scripture. I ultimately conclude that the traditional theological perspective is the most consilient of the three perspectives with Scripture and the wider body of knowledge. APPROVED BY DIRECTOR OF HONORS THESIS: __________________________________________________ Dr. Junius Johnson, Department of Great Texts APPROVED -
5. Mormann FINAL-2
From Cautious Enthusiasm to Profound Disenchantment Ernest Nagel and Carnapian Logical Empiricism Thomas Mormann Department of Logic and Philosophy Science University of the Basque Country UPV/EHU Donostia-San Sebastian, Spain [email protected] Abstract: In this paper I’d like to study the complex relation between logical empiricism and American pragmatism examining the case of Ernest Nagel. More precisely, I want to explore some aspects of Nagel’s changing attitude towards the “new” logical-empiricist philosophy that arrived in the US in the 1930s. In the beginning, Nagel welcomed logical empiricism almost wholeheartedly. This early enthusiasm did not last. Nagel’s growing dissatisfaction with the Carnapian version of logical empiricist philosophy was clearly expressed in his criticism of Carnap’s inductive logic and more generally in his last book, Teleology Revisited and Other Essays in the History and Philosophy of Science, where he criticizes Carnap’s philosophy of science in general as ahistoric and non-pragmatist. It is argued that Carnap and Nagel represented opposed possibilities for how the profession of a philosopher of science could be understood: Carnap, as a “conceptual engineer”, was engaged in the task of inventing conceptual tools for a better theoretical understanding of science, while Nagel is better characterized as a “public intellectual” engaged in the more general practical project of realizing a more rational and enlightened society. Keywords: Logical Empiricism; American Pragmatism; History of Science; Rudolf Carnap; Ernest Nagel 5.1. Introduction The relation between logical empiricism and American pragmatism is one of the more difficult problems in the history of philosophy.1 This relation cannot be described as a point- like event; rather, it was a process that evolved for various decades. -
The Challenge of Morton White and the Politics of Antiformalism
Morton White. Social Thought in America: The Revolt Against Formalism. New York: Viking, 1949. viii + 260 pp. $6.95, cloth, ISBN 978-0-19-519837-9. Reviewed by Robert Genter Published on H-Ideas (July, 2000) [Note: This review is part of the H-Ideas Ret‐ of French existentialism than the optimism of rospective Reviews series. This series reviews American pragmatism. It was an era in which books published during the twentieth century "Dewey's views [were] being replaced by which have been deemed to be among the most Kierkegaard's" (p. 3). In this regard, White's con‐ important contributions to the feld of intellectual tribution to the feld of intellectual history in this history.] period lay not only in his particular interpretation The publication in 1949 of Morton White's of the antiformalists but in his willingness to con‐ study of late nineteenth-century antiformalism in sider their contribution to the philosophical en‐ American thought occurred at a very peculiar terprise at all. time in the history of American philosophy. the White's demarcation of the major American post-World War II transformation of American thinkers of the late nineteenth century, including philosophy departments into centers for analytic John Dewey, Charles Beard, Oliver Wendell philosophy succeeded in marginalizing the main Holmes, James Harvey Robinson, and Thorstein currents of antiformalism, including pragmatism Veblen, as antiformalists marked the frst work of and naturalism. The theoretical shift ushered in intellectual history dedicated to a broad theoriza‐ by the emigration to America of the famous Vien‐ tion of this period. He was the frst to treat these na Circle, including Rudolf Carnap, Herbert Feigl, individual critiques of historical analysis, philo‐ and Albert Blumberg, and the turn to logical posi‐ sophical speculation, and economic discourse as tivism vanquished questions of experience and part of a shared intellectual project. -
Language Is a Form of Experience: Reconciling Classical Pragmatism
Abstract The revival of philosophical pragmatism has generated a wealth of intramural debates between neopragmatists like Richard Rorty and contemporary scholars devoted to expli- cating the classical pragmatism of John Dewey and William James. Of all these Language is a internecine conflicts, the most divisive con- cerns the status of language and experience Form of in pragmatist philosophy. Contemporary scholars of classical pragmatism defend expe- Experience: rience as the heart of pragmatism while neo- pragmatists drop the concept of experience Reconciling in favor of a thoroughly linguistic pragma- tism. I argue that both positions engender Classical formidable risks. After discussing the present impasse, I describe a third version of prag- Pragmatism matism which involves a reconstruction of the classical pragmatist concept of experience and in light of the criticisms of foundationalism crucial to the neopragmatist linguistic turn. Neopragmatism This third version of pragmatism does justice to both Rorty and Dewey by focusing on colin koopman experience as a temporal field. Keywords: Richard Rorty, John Dewey, William James, Classical Pragmatism, Neopragmatism, Foundationalism, Myth of the Given, Linguistic Turn Experience and Language in Contemporary Pragmatism The revival of pragmatism by contempo- rary philosophers such as Richard Rorty, Hilary Putnam, and Robert Brandom has generated a wealth of intramural debates between these upstart neopragmatists and contemporary scholars of classical pragma- tism devoted to the work of Charles Peirce, William James, and John Dewey. Of all the internecine conflicts which continue to rage, perhaps the most ink has been spilled TRANSACTIONS OF THE CHARLES S. PEIRCE SOCIETY Vol. 43, No. 4 ©2007 694 over issues concerning the relative priority of language and experience of Experience Language is a Form in pragmatism. -
Passmore, J. (1967). Logical Positivism. in P. Edwards (Ed.). the Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Vol. 5, 52- 57). New York: Macmillan
Passmore, J. (1967). Logical Positivism. In P. Edwards (Ed.). The Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Vol. 5, 52- 57). New York: Macmillan. LOGICAL POSITIVISM is the name given in 1931 by A. E. Blumberg and Herbert Feigl to a set of philosophical ideas put forward by the Vienna circle. Synonymous expressions include "consistent empiricism," "logical empiricism," "scientific empiricism," and "logical neo-positivism." The name logical positivism is often, but misleadingly, used more broadly to include the "analytical" or "ordinary language philosophies developed at Cambridge and Oxford. HISTORICAL BACKGROUND The logical positivists thought of themselves as continuing a nineteenth-century Viennese empirical tradition, closely linked with British empiricism and culminating in the antimetaphysical, scientifically oriented teaching of Ernst Mach. In 1907 the mathematician Hans Hahn, the economist Otto Neurath, and the physicist Philipp Frank, all of whom were later to be prominent members of the Vienna circle, came together as an informal group to discuss the philosophy of science. They hoped to give an account of science which would do justice -as, they thought, Mach did not- to the central importance of mathematics, logic, and theoretical physics, without abandoning Mach's general doctrine that science is, fundamentally, the description of experience. As a solution to their problems, they looked to the "new positivism" of Poincare; in attempting to reconcile Mach and Poincare; they anticipated the main themes of logical positivism. In 1922, at the instigation of members of the "Vienna group," Moritz Schlick was invited to Vienna as professor, like Mach before him (1895-1901), in the philosophy of the inductive sciences. Schlick had been trained as a scientist under Max Planck and had won a name for himself as an interpreter of Einstein's theory of relativity.