Secularism/Atheism/ Agnosticism

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Secularism/Atheism/ Agnosticism CHAPTER THIRTY-FOUR SECULARISM/ATHEISM/ AGNOSTICISM Vincent P. Pecora ecularism, atheism, and agnosticism belong to what Ludwig Wittgenstein called Sa “family” of ideas, yet are etymologically distinct. Two of the terms—agnosticism and secularism—are coinages of later nineteenth-century Britain, though their linguistic roots are much older. At least in Western Europe and Russia, the fi n de siècle produced a questioning of theism unlike anything that had come before. The dominant religious attitude among late seventeenth- and eighteenth-century intellectuals had been deism, the assumption that God existed but was absent from human affairs. Some deists could have been called atheists or agnostics, had the latter term been available. But deism covered, as it were, a multitude of sins between theism and atheism, and provided a useful way of avoiding deeper theological controversy. It was a perspective inspired by Galileo’s astronomy, Isaac Newton’s mechanics, the Reformation’s rejection of miracles and the papacy, and the acknowledgment after the voyages of discovery of a larger and less savage array of religious practices than anyone had previously imagined. Deism was the shared theology of the Enlightenment, from the Scottish sentimental moralists and French encyclopédistes to the American founders and the German Romantic philosophers. By contrast, the European nineteenth century unfolded in the idealistic but threatening shadow of the French Revolution, which was nothing if not virulently anti-clerical. Whether one celebrated its humanist, republican ideals with nationalist revolutionaries, or feared its anarchic violence, as did supporters of the old regimes, the French Revolution and Napoleon’s attempt at a new European order presaged a liberated and Promethean but also unregulated and disorderly future. Percy Bysshe Shelley updated Aeschylus in his Prometheus Unbound: A Lyrical Drama in Four Acts (1818–19), in which the phantasm of Jupiter invoked by the chained Prometheus rehearses Prometheus’s curse against his God. But thou who art the God and Lord—O thou Who fi llest with thy soul this world of woe, To whom all things of Earth and Heaven do bow In fear and worship—all-prevailing foe! I curse thee! Let a sufferer’s curse 537 — Vincent P. Pecora — Clasp thee, his torturer, like remorse, Till thine Infi nity shall be A robe of envenomed agony And thine Omnipotence a crown of pain To cling like burning gold round thy dissolving brain. (Prometheus Unbound, Act 1, ll. 282–91) Under the guise of pagan verse-theater, Shelley did not mince words. But the promise of Promethean revolution was its ability to overcome the limitations of fi ne art, social class, and political power in the pursuit of a world unfettered by Gods and monarchs alike. It is this Napoleonic/Promethean vision of a heroically anti- theistic and anti-authoritarian humanity that the nineteenth century inherited, and that gave its debates about divine authority the frisson of a struggle over social authority as well. ATHEISM Atheism today seems straightforward: evolution, atoms, DNA, but no God or supernatural realm. But this is too simplistic. The word in English dates back at least to the late sixteenth century, where it tended to mean “godless” or Epicurean. Mere fragments of the writings of Epicurus (341–270 bce) survive, but his name has long been associated with atomistic materialism. Yet his religious beliefs seem closer to that of eighteenth-century deists: Epicurus held that freedom from fear and pain was life’s goal, and that the gods did not interfere in mortal existence. In Paradise Lost (1667), John Milton refers to “the atheist crew” following Satan into battle against God’s angelic legions (Book VI, line 370), but Milton means something closer to impious or rebellious here. Satan obviously does not deny the existence of God; he wants to dethrone him. Atheism throughout the centuries actually pointed to a number of different epistemological and moral positions—neither Epicurus nor Milton’s Satan aligns neatly with, say, the seventeenth-century materialism of Thomas Hobbes or the libertinism of John Wilmot, 2nd Earl of Rochester, though all four have been labeled atheists, and Rochester was quite vocal about his disbelief (despite his deathbed conversion). Like later nineteenth-century agnosticism, atheism implied both an epistemological position—there is neither evidence for a divinity nor any reason to assume one—and a moral position, summed up by several characters in Fyodor Dostoevsky’s The Brothers Karamazov (1880): without God and immortality, Miusov observes, “everything would be permitted, even anthro- pophagy” (Dostoevsky 69). The nineteenth-century arguments about secularism, atheism, and agnosticism are often about the relation between belief and morality. Does the epistemological position necessarily entail the moral one (as Rochester’s death at 33, probably from venereal and kidney disease, implied to many) and as Dostoevsky assumed, or can one ignore the deity and still lead a virtuous, even admirable, life, a view held by Hobbes, most of the deists, and the majority of nineteenth-century atheists and agnostics? Three signifi cant versions of later nineteenth-century atheism deserve attention. Throughout the fl urry of debate and discussion over religion, two fi gures—one solidly on the political left, and one roughly on the political right—stand out as 538 — Secularism/atheism/agnosticism — exemplary atheists: Karl Marx and Friedrich Nietzsche. Marx’s claim that religion was nothing more than the “opium of the people” resounds to this day, but his more far-reaching critique of religion appears in “On the Jewish Question” (1843) (see Marx, Critique 131). The latter essay responds to Bruno Bauer’s argument that neither Prussia nor any other Christian state could politically emancipate the Jews and survive. Bauer demanded the abolition of religion as a prerequisite to true political freedom. What is remarkable today is that neither Bauer nor Marx demonstrated any confi dence in what modern democracies call religious pluralism. Religion for Marx and Bauer was so identifi ed with a single national identity that neither believed a nation harboring competing religions could cohere. Bauer insisted that only the renunciation of religious belief could produce equality of political rights—an extension of French republicanism and of the Young Hegelian argument, elaborated by Ludwig Feuerbach, that religion was nothing more than human love mistakenly displaced into a non-human realm. Once the mistake was recognized, Feuerbach argued, religion as such would disappear and true human emancipation would occur. Against Bauer, Marx argued that religion would wither away of its own accord. Economic oppression and inequity drove individuals into the arms of religion searching for cosmic solace—the justice denied on earth was to be guaranteed in heaven—so that ending injustice would destroy the need for religion. Marx and Engels devoted a large part of The German Ideology (completed in 1846, though not published until 1932) toward illustrating how Feuerbach had put the cart before the horse. By making emancipation depend on the abandonment of religious belief, Feuerbach granted religion a causality it did not possess. “Feuerbach, consequently, does not see that the ‘religious sentiment’ is itself a social product” rather than an element of some “human essence” (“Theses on Feuerbach,” nos. VII and VI; see Marx and Engels, German 122). With capitalism’s collapse, a new egalitarian society would no longer have any need for religious explanations or expectations. Marx did not assume that atheism itself had any social or epistemo- logical effects; theism was simply an illusion that would evaporate when material inequality disappeared. Whatever one thinks of Marx’s economic program, it is certain that his arguments against religion have had a larger effect on the way intellectuals have approached belief after him than those of any other nineteenth-century thinker. Many liberals after Max Weber, and especially after the Great Depression, embraced Marx’s central point that religious belief and economic wellbeing were inversely proportional, no matter how skeptical they remained about communism. Christ’s “blessed are the meek” became sociological axiom, though not in the way Christ intended. For the sociologists, the meek had more need of faith. The mid-1960s brought the fl ourishing of the “secularization thesis”: the rise of economic, political, and social modernity, including nationalism and rationally administered capitalism, guaranteed the fall of religion, a conclusion borne out by empirical data at the time. Only in recent decades has the long association between the rise of economic modernity and the fall of religion come to be seriously questioned. Nietzsche’s critique of religion was more aggressive, if more ambitious and ambiguous, than Marx’s. But Nietzsche may be more representative of the decadence- cum-regeneration spirit of fi n-de-siècle culture. Nietzsche mounted a wholesale 539 — Vincent P. Pecora — attack not only on European Christianity and the Judaism from which it arose, but also on non-Western religions such as Hinduism and Buddhism, all of which exemplifi ed “ascetic ideals”—that is, selfl essness, a hatred of the body and its desires, and a longing for release from the physical world (see Nietzsche, Genealogy, Third Essay). Priestly Christianity promoted this ascetic ideal to the wretched of the earth, convincing them of what was in their interest: the meek would one day inherit the earth and be avenged by divine triumph over their tormentors. Nietzsche claimed that this ascetic ideal led to Europe’s nineteenth-century nihilism and the catastrophe of egalitarian democracy and socialism. But the demise of European civilization was for him also a harbinger of cultural rebirth, with other forms of enchantment arising out of Europe’s destruction. Where Marx understood the birth and death of religion as necessary consequences of economic development, Nietzsche saw the emergence of Judaism and Christianity in antiquity as a grand historical detour, the growing implications of which had become intolerable in fi n-de-siècle Europe.
Recommended publications
  • A Contextual Examination of Three Historical Stages of Atheism and the Legality of an American Freedom from Religion
    ABSTRACT Rejecting the Definitive: A Contextual Examination of Three Historical Stages of Atheism and the Legality of an American Freedom from Religion Ethan Gjerset Quillen, B.A., M.A., M.A. Mentor: T. Michael Parrish, Ph.D. The trouble with “definitions” is they leave no room for evolution. When a word is concretely defined, it is done so in a particular time and place. Contextual interpretations permit a better understanding of certain heavy words; Atheism as a prime example. In the post-modern world Atheism has become more accepted and popular, especially as a reaction to global terrorism. However, the current definition of Atheism is terribly inaccurate. It cannot be stated properly that pagan Atheism is the same as New Atheism. By interpreting the Atheisms from four stages in the term‟s history a clearer picture of its meaning will come out, hopefully alleviating the stereotypical biases weighed upon it. In the interpretation of the Atheisms from Pagan Antiquity, the Enlightenment, the New Atheist Movement, and the American Judicial and Civil Religious system, a defense of the theory of elastic contextual interpretations, rather than concrete definitions, shall be made. Rejecting the Definitive: A Contextual Examination of Three Historical Stages of Atheism and the Legality of an American Freedom from Religion by Ethan Gjerset Quillen, B.A., M.A. A Thesis Approved by the J.M. Dawson Institute of Church-State Studies ___________________________________ Robyn L. Driskell, Ph.D., Interim Chairperson Submitted to the Graduate Faculty of Baylor University in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of Master of Arts Approved by the Thesis Committee ___________________________________ T.
    [Show full text]
  • David Hume, "The Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion," and Religious Tolerance
    University of Tennessee, Knoxville TRACE: Tennessee Research and Creative Exchange Supervised Undergraduate Student Research Chancellor’s Honors Program Projects and Creative Work 5-2020 David Hume, "The Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion," and Religious Tolerance Jarrett Delozier [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://trace.tennessee.edu/utk_chanhonoproj Part of the History of Philosophy Commons, History of Religion Commons, Intellectual History Commons, and the Religious Thought, Theology and Philosophy of Religion Commons Recommended Citation Delozier, Jarrett, "David Hume, "The Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion," and Religious Tolerance" (2020). Chancellor’s Honors Program Projects. https://trace.tennessee.edu/utk_chanhonoproj/2382 This Dissertation/Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Supervised Undergraduate Student Research and Creative Work at TRACE: Tennessee Research and Creative Exchange. It has been accepted for inclusion in Chancellor’s Honors Program Projects by an authorized administrator of TRACE: Tennessee Research and Creative Exchange. For more information, please contact [email protected]. DeLozier 1 Introduction In the history of philosophy of religion and natural theology, David Hume is an immensely influential contributor. One of his most important works in the field is his Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion, which contains his greatest treatment of natural theology, specifically the design argument. However, there’s a big problem which the Dialogues present to understanding Hume. Eleven of the twelve parts of the Dialogues contain Hume’s sharp criticisms and attacks on the Design argument. But in the final part, in what is often called “Philo’s Reversal,” he seems to completely reverse course by renouncing his skepticism and endorsing the Design argument.
    [Show full text]
  • The Problem of God's Existence
    THE PROBLEM OF GOD’S EXISTENCE: IN DEFENCE OF SCEPTICISM IRENEUSZ ZIEMIŃSKI University of Szczecin Abstract. There are four main positions in the argument about whether God exists: atheism (God does not exist), theism (God exists), agnosticism (it is impossible to know whether God exists or not), and scepticism (at the moment we do not know whether God exists or not). From an epistemological standpoint, scepticism is the most rational; even if a decisive argument which would settle the debate has not been discovered yet, one cannot exclude the possibility of finding it eventually. Agnosticism is too radical (and even incoherent), but theism and atheism exceed the available data. However, from a practical standpoint, choosing theism or atheism seems to be more rational than scepticism (not to mention agnosticism); one of them is bound to be right, because there are only two possibilities, one of which has to be true: either God exists or not. The main thesis I am going to defend1 is that currently the question of whether God exists remains unanswered because the available data does not enable us to settle it. It does not mean that there is no possible evidence which could settle the dispute about the existence of God or that we will never be able to discover it; still, even if such evidence exists, we do not know it at the moment. In other words, this will be an attempt to justify the thesis that the most adequate standpoint on the matter of whether God exists is scepticism. First I will present my main assumptions, mainly concerning the concept of God (point 1), next I will outline the main standpoints on the matter and show the difficulties of 1 A shorter version of this paper was presented during the international conference ‘Epistemology of Atheism’, organized by Professor Roger Pouivet in Nancy (France) in June 2013.
    [Show full text]
  • Agnost-A-What?
    Soc (2015) 52:201–202 DOI 10.1007/s12115-015-9887-1 COMMENTARY: CALDERWOOD PRIZE ESSAY IN PUBLIC WRITING Agnost-a-What? Emma van den Terrell1 Published online: 14 April 2015 # Springer Science+Business Media New York 2015 What religion are you? It is likely that every adult has been really considered the BGod question.^ I have come to my asked some permutation of this socially loaded question and beliefs as a matter of personal discovery informed by can acknowledge the difficulty in answering it. Personally, critical reading and discussion throughout my studies as I’m a perfectly content agnostic. The many blank looks and a religion major. I then realized that Saul’s question questions I’ve received on my agnosticism reinforce my belief revealed a complete misconception of the basic premise of that being agnostic in America is little understood and often agnosticism. By accusing agnostics of not knowing due to conflated with atheism. I, like other agnostics, have Bneither laziness or lack of thought, he misses the point: true faith nor disbelief in God,^ and, to quote Saint John of agnostics are okay with not knowing and never trying to Damascus, believe that any God Bin his essence and nature figure out the BGod dilemma.^ Agnosticism is belief, like is absolutely incomprehensible and totally unknowable.^ Catholicism or Judaism—it’s just that instead of believing in Agnostics believe that humans can never truly know if there God, agnostics believe in a limited human capacity to know if is a God, unlike many religious observers. But agnostics also there is a God or absence of a God.
    [Show full text]
  • 1 Remembering Marx's Secularism* Scholars Engaged in the Critique Of
    Remembering Marx’s Secularism* Scholars engaged in the critique of secularism have struggled with the numerous meanings of the secular and its cognates, such as secularism, secularization, and secularity. Seeking coherence in the secular’s semantic excess, they have often elided distinctions between these meanings or sought a more basic concept of the secular that can contain all of its senses (Asad 2003; Taylor 2007; see Weir 2015). Numerous scholars have observed strong similarities between secularism and Protestantism (Fessenden 2007; Modern 2011; Yelle 2013; see McCrary and Wheatley 2017), at times echoing a Christian theological tradition that has long been anti-secular (Taylor 2007; Gregory 2012; see Reynolds 2016). Unlike this anti-secular tradition, the strongest version of the critique of secularism is a critique of the conditions that produce a distinction between secular and religious and a critique of the ways that empire benefits from this distinction. Overcoming a tidy separation between secularism and religion requires fracturing both and reassembling them in new ways that allow messy life to exceed governance (Hurd 2015, 122- 27). Remembering Karl Marx’s secularism provides an opportunity to recover the differences within secularism and its difference from Christianity, but also its odd similarities with religion. This recovery can help refine the critique of secularism and preserve some important tools for improving material conditions. * Joseph Blankholm, Department of Religious Studies, University of California, Santa Barbara, CA 93106, USA. E-mail: [email protected]. I owe thanks to several PhD students at the University of California, Santa Barbara for their valuable insights and feedback, including Matthew Harris, as well as the students in my seminar on materialism: Timothy Snediker, Lucas McCracken, Courtney Applewhite, and Damian Lanahan-Kalish.
    [Show full text]
  • Deism and Agnosticism
    UNIT 2 DEISM AND AGNOSTICISM Contents 2.0 Objectives 2.1 Introduction 2.2 Deism – Its Origin and Definition 2.3 Deism – Various Facets 2.4 Agnosticism – Its origin and Defintion 2.5 Agnosticism – Various Dimensions 2.6 Let Us Sum Up 2.7 Key Words 2.8 Further Readings and References 2.0 OBJECTIVES The main objective of this Unit is to introduce, Deism and Agnosticism, two key concepts from the world of philosophy of Religion. Since it is not possible to give a complete and exhaustive account of these two concepts within such a limited space, the chapter aims at laying a foundation of the concepts which can be built up later by further reading. The chapter looks not only at the Historical aspect of the two concepts but also examines their meaning and significance in the realm of Religion and further dives deep into the Philosophical implications of the same. Apart from looking into the two concepts separately there will be an attempt to see them in the light of each other. Deism and Agnosticism fall into many of the theories which have tried to explain the relation of the Creator and His creation. Agnosticism is concerned with the possibility of the knowledge of the Creator if any such exists at all. Therefore an examination of these concepts in the light of the other theories, in the larger philosophical canvas, is another objective of the study. The chapter ends with a reflection on the relevance of the concepts in the present context and their implications in the other domains of Philosophy of Religion.
    [Show full text]
  • The Faith of a Heretic
    THE FAITH OF A HERETIC Beginning a Series on Modern Religious Beliefs in America to become a Jew. Having never heard of Uni- One of America's most brilliant young philos- tarianism, I assumed that the religion for people ophers tells why-after' trying two of them-he who believed in God, but not in Christ or the cannot believe in any of the worLd's great re- Holy Ghost, was Judaism. ligions. He argues that acute, rational criti- A few months after my conversation with my cism of religious beliefs can, and should, exist father, but before 1 left the church, Hitler came along with deep feeling for man's religious quest. to power. 'Warned of the persecution that my But for him traditional religious teachings are decision might entail, I replied that one certainly only one amung many sources which can inspire men "to live and, if possible, die with some could not change one's mind for a reason like measure of nobility." / that. I did not realize until a little later that all In the following articles in this series, out- four of my grandparents had been Jewish; and standing young Catholic, Jewish, and Protestant none of us knew that this, and not one's own thinkers-none of them professional clergymen- religion, would be decisive from the Nazis' point will describe their personal faiths and tell how of view. My decision had been made inde- they arrived at them. pendently of my descent and of Nazism, on re- ligious grounds. I took my new religion very seriously, explored WALTER KAUFMANN it with enormous curiosity and growing love, and gradually became more and more orthodox.
    [Show full text]
  • Analogical Inference in Hume's Philosophy of Religion
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Asbury Theological Seminary Faith and Philosophy: Journal of the Society of Christian Philosophers Volume 2 Issue 3 Article 6 7-1-1985 Analogical Inference in Hume's Philosophy of Religion Dale Jacquette Follow this and additional works at: https://place.asburyseminary.edu/faithandphilosophy Recommended Citation Jacquette, Dale (1985) "Analogical Inference in Hume's Philosophy of Religion," Faith and Philosophy: Journal of the Society of Christian Philosophers: Vol. 2 : Iss. 3 , Article 6. Available at: https://place.asburyseminary.edu/faithandphilosophy/vol2/iss3/6 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Journals at ePLACE: preserving, learning, and creative exchange. It has been accepted for inclusion in Faith and Philosophy: Journal of the Society of Christian Philosophers by an authorized editor of ePLACE: preserving, learning, and creative exchange. ANALOGICAL INFERENCE IN HUME'S PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION Dale lacquette The whole earth, believe me, Philo, is cursed and polluted. -Demea David Hume, in his philosophical writings on religion, is often guarded and ambiguous about his own religious beliefs. There is dispute over which if any of the characters in the Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion speaks for Hume.' To further complicate things, Hume' s published remarks about religion sometimes directly contradict his recorded pronouncements in private conversations with some of his contemporaries. 2 But whether Hume was a deist, fideist, atheist, or agnostic, it is generally agreed that his empiricist philosophy of religion precludes the probability that an intelligent designer or designers of the universe could have human-like moral qualities.
    [Show full text]
  • Comparison Between Atheism, Agnosticism and Humanism
    http://www.inosr.net/inosr-applied-sciences/ Tallulah and Mishka INOSR APPLIED SCIENCES 1(1): 14-20, 2015 ©INOSR PUBLICATIONS International Network Organization for Scientific Research ISSN: 2705-165X Comparison between Atheism, Agnosticism and Humanism Tallulah Rebecca and Mishka Joshua Department of religious studies, Faculty of Theology and Religion University of Pretoria, South Africa Email: [email protected] ABSTRACT This article reviews the Comparison thinking and evidence (rationalism and between Atheism, Agnosticism and empiricism) over acceptance of dogma or Humanism. Atheism is, in the broadest superstition. The words atheist and sense, an absence of belief in the existence agnostic conjure up a number of different of deities. Less broadly, atheism is a perceptions and meanings. When it comes rejection of the belief that any deities exist. to questioning the existence of gods, the Agnosticism is the view that the existence subject is a tricky one that is often of God, of the divine or the supernatural is misunderstood. No matter what their unknown or unknowable. Humanism is a reasons or how they approach the philosophical and ethical stance that question, agnostics and atheists are emphasizes the value and agency of fundamentally different, but also non- human beings, individually and exclusive. collectively, and generally prefers critical Keywords: Comparison, Atheism, Agnosticism Humanism INTRODUCTION Atheism is, in the broadest sense, an application of the term narrowed in absence of belief in the existence of scope. The first individuals to identify deities. Less broadly, atheism is a themselves using the word atheist lived in rejection of the belief that any deities the 18th century during the Age of exist.
    [Show full text]
  • Contemporary Reviews of Middlemarch
    C-BACK-1 10/01/2015 9:29 AM Page 678 Review Copy Appendix B: Contemporary Reviews of Middlemarch 1. From Edward Dowden, “George Eliot,” Contemporary Review 20 (August 1872): 403-22 [In this appreciative essay by a leading Shakespeare scholar of the day, the main interest in GE’s novels is not her vivid characters but, rather, the remarkable nar- rative voice in her fiction, what Dowden calls her “second self.” The dominating presence of the German philosopher Arthur Schopenhauer (1788-1860) sug- gests where her contemporaries thought GE belonged in the context of European ideas. The contemporary reception of the novel, as represented by this and the reviews that follow, tells us a great deal about the Victorian world of ideas and the intellectual, aesthetic, and ethical investments of GE’s critics.] When we have passed in review the works of that great writer who calls herself George Eliot, and given for a time our use of sight to her portraitures of men and women, what form, as we move away, persists on the field of vision, and remains the chief centre of interest for the imagination? The form not of Tito, or Maggie, or Dinah, or Silas, but of one who, if not the real George Eliot, is that “second self” who writes her books, and lives and speaks through them. Such a second self of an author is perhaps more substantial than any mere human per- sonality encumbered with the accidents of flesh and blood and daily living. It stands at some distance from the primary self, and differs considerably from its fellow.
    [Show full text]
  • Dalrev Vol44 Iss4 Pp418 427.Pdf (5.195Mb)
    Robert H. Tener THE IMPORTANCE OF BEING HUTTON ANYONE WHO DEVOTES considerable time to the study of a minor literary figure prob­ ably feels the need to justify his work. I would certainly not except myself, for I have often observed a response of blank unrecognition when I inform scholars that I am engaged in research on Richard Holt Hutton. And since this response is fre­ quently enough exhibited by specialists in Victorian literature, I feel that I owe them some information, if not an explanation. More positively, I am convinced that Hutton has been undeservedly neglected, and that an indication of his importance is therefore overdue. One method of suggesting the significance of a critic is to show how he has been regarded by those whose opinions we can respect. It is this method that I employ here. I consider two main bodies of opinion on Hutton's dual functions of editor and critic: the views of his contemporaries, and then the attitudes of more recent writers. For thirty-six years from 1861 to 1897 Hutton was co-proprietor and literary editor of the weekly Spectator. When his colleague, Meredith Townsend, purchased the paper early in 1861 he acquired a depressed property. But though the Spectator's championship of the North during the American Civil War further jeopardized circulation, by the end of the war the paper had recovered its ground, and thereafter moved from strength to strength.1 The stages of its growing readership and influ­ ence can be traced in contemporary opinion. William Cory, for instance, in a letter to a friend on February 1, 1863, wrote: ..
    [Show full text]
  • 1934 Unitarian Movement.Pdf
    fi * " >, -,$a a ri 7 'I * as- h1in-g & t!estP; ton BrLLnch," LONDON t,. GEORGE ALLEN &' UNWIN- LID v- ' MUSEUM STREET FIRST PUBLISHED IN 1934 ACE * i& ITwas by invitation of The Hibbert Trustees, to whom all interested in "Christianity in its most simple and intel- indebted, that what follows lieibleV form" have long been was written. For the opinions expressed the writer alone is responsible. His aim has been to give some account of the work during two centuries of a small group of religious thinkers, who, for the most part, have been overlooked in the records of English religious life, and so rescue from obscurity a few names that deserve to be remembered amongst pioneers and pathfinders in more fields than one. Obligations are gratefully acknowledged to the Rev. V. D. Davis. B.A., and the Rev. W. H. Burgess, M.A., for a few fruitful suggestions, and to the Rev. W. Whitaker, I M.A., for his labours in correcting proofs. MANCHESTER October 14, 1933 At1 yigifs ~ese~vcd 1L' PRENTED IN GREAT BRITAIN BY UNWIN BROTHERS LTD., WOKING CON TENTS A 7.. I. BIBLICAL SCHOLARSHIP' PAGE BIBLICAL SCHOLARSHIP 1 3 iI. EDUCATION CONFORMIST ACADEMIES 111. THE MODERN UNIVERSITIES 111. JOURNALS AND WRIODICAL LITERATURE . THE UNITARIAN CONTRIBUTI:ON TO PERIODICAL . LITERATURE ?aEz . AND BIOGR AND BELLES-LETTRES 11. PHILOSOPHY 111. HISTORY AND BIOGRAPHY I IV. LITERATURE ....:'. INDEX OF PERIODICALS "INDEX OF PERSONS p - INDEX OF PLACES :>$ ';: GENERAL INDEX C. A* - CHAPTER l BIBLICAL SCHOLARSHIP 9L * KING of the origin of Unitarian Christianity in this country,
    [Show full text]