Boethius, the Consolation of Philosophy, Book 5 (Or, Reconciling Human Freedom and Divine Foreknowledge)
Total Page:16
File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb
Boethius, The Consolation of Philosophy, book 5 (or, reconciling human freedom and divine foreknowledge) More than a century after Augustine, Boethius offers a different solution to the problem of human freedom versus divine foreknowledge, which appeals to the nature of time and God’s eternity. He reaches this conclusion by way of an imaginary conversation with “Lady Philosophy” as he waits in his prison cell before his execution (in 524 AD). 1. No Chance, No Freedom? Boethius begins by asking if it is possible for an event to occur by mere chance—i.e., an event that is purely random (indeterministic). The answer is no. For, a truly random event would have to be one that has no cause at all. But, this is just to say that a random event comes from nothing. As the famous adage goes, nothing comes from nothing, however. So, a truly random event is impossible. Clarification: Sure, we often CALL events “random” or “chance” events. But, we’re speaking improperly when we do so. For instance, imagine a farmer who, by “chance”, finds some gold buried in his field. This event is not truly random. For, there IS a causal explanation (e.g., some thief was on the run and buried it there long ago, but was captured before he could retrieve it, etc.). In short, what we really mean when we say that this was a “random” event is that it was unexpected, or unforeseen, or unintended. [Imagine a pair of dice. Though the result of throwing them may SEEM random, strictly speaking, if we knew the angle and momentum of your throw, every detail about the table and the dice, the air current, and so on, we would be able to accurately calculate how the dice would land. When we say that the result is “random” we really mean “unforeseen”. Or consider the way that a computer generates a “random” number. It uses an algorithm that is SO complicated that we cannot predict the number generated. So, it SEEMS random to us—the generated number is always unexpected. Nevertheless, one could calculate that number with certainty if they knew the mechanism (algorithm) that determined it.] But, then, if there is no such thing as true chance, and everything is really subject to the stream of causation, are we really free? For, the gold in the field, the pair of dice, a stone that inevitably falls to the ground—indeed, all physical objects—seem to just be entirely caught up in an “inescapable interweaving of causes”? (Pr. 1) (governed by physical laws) So then, are we, like the rock that falls, ALSO caught up in this chain of causes? Boethius asks, “Is there any freedom of our independent judgment? Or does the chain of fate tie together the very motions of human minds as well?” (Prose 3) 1 Yes, We Are Free: Lady Philosophy assures Boethius that humans do have free will. Unlike rocks that simply fall with no choice in the matter, we humans by nature have the ability to reason; i.e., the ability to discriminate or distinguish between things. We can JUDGE things, and come to the conclusion that some things are better, or worse, than others. Then, we can SEEK the better things and AVOID the worse things.1 [Still, today, we might worry that the laws of physics dictate even our judgements and desires! When we compare things and weigh them up, one against the other, is it INEVITABLE that we come to the conclusion that we do about which one is better? For instance, imagine that you were trying to decide between W&M and UVA. If it is inevitable that you decided that W&M is better, then perhaps you did not make your choice freely. If it is NOT inevitable that you came to the conclusion that you did, then think for a moment about what that means: Given EXACTLY the same reasons and EXACTLY the same deliberation, you could have instead come to the conclusion that UVA was better, and then decided to go there. Was that outcome REALLY possible though?] 2. Freedom vs. Foreknowledge: Given that we do have free will, the question of how human freedom is compatible with divine foreknowledge arises once again (Pr. 3, 3-6). Recall that the idea is that there is no free will, since (because God knows everything we will do before we do it, and is never wrong) everything we do is necessary. Now Augustine said there is no problem, since the DIRECTION of the necessity is such that it does not jeopardize free will. The two possible directions of necessitation are: (1) God’s knowledge Human choice (2) Human Choice God’s Knowledge The FIRST option is the one that removes free will. Think of them like this: (1) If God knows that I will do X tomorrow, this knowledge causes me to do X. (2) If I will do X tomorrow, then this action causes God to know that I will do X. The solution is that (2) is true, but (1) is false. Boethius rejects this “solution”, writing: 1 [Lady Philosophy also goes on to say that freedom comes in degrees. The MOST free are those who align their desires with God; they are less free when moved toward Earthly things; and least free when “enslaved” by vices, or destructive passions. Yet, even these slaves are free in some sense, since they are “captives of their own liberty”. The implication seems to be that they are enslaved because they FREELY CHOSE to be (like addicts, who voluntarily begin taking a drug, but then cannot voluntarily quit).] 2 “Ha! As if the contention were which is the cause of which—whether foreknowledge of future things is the cause of the necessity, or whether the necessity of future things is the cause of the foreseeing.” (Pr. 3, 7-14) First, Boethius seems to think it somewhat blasphemous to think that we can somehow CAUSE God—an eternal, unchanging being—to know things: “How utterly backwards it is to say that the outcome of temporal events is the cause of eternal knowledge!” (ibid.) More importantly, Boethius thinks that the direction of causation is irrelevant, for EITHER WAY there is a necessitation that threatens free will. He writes, “even though the cause of truth proceeds from only one side, there is present all the same a common necessity on both sides.” (Pr. 3, 7-14) This is because, even if foreknowledge doesn’t GENERATE or CAUSE the necessity of future events, it “is nevertheless a sign that such things are necessarily going to occur.” (Pr. 4, 9-14) In short, even if my knowledge of what will happen does not CAUSE it to happen, nevertheless, it will NECESSARILY happen—otherwise, I wouldn’t have knowledge. The belief seems to be that I can only KNOW that something is going to happen if it is 100% CERTAIN to happen. He writes, “when I know that something will be, it is necessarily the case that that same thing will be. And so it happens that the outcome of a foreseen event cannot be avoided.” (Pr. 3, 15-18) For, “there can in no way be foreknowledge if necessity is absent; … nothing can be grasped by knowledge unless it is a definite thing. For if things that are characterized by indefinite outcomes are foreseen as if they were definite, that would be the darkness of opinion and not the truth of knowledge.” (Pr. 4, 21-15) In other words, if we are free, then there are multiple ways that the future could turn out; i.e., the future is indefinite. But, knowledge is by nature definite; it is SURE; it is CERTAIN. So, one simply cannot KNOW that something will happen unless it will DEFINITELY happen. In short, with respect to seeing the future, there are two options: (1) God knows the future (which entails that the future is definite; i.e., no free will). (2) The future is NOT definite (which entails God CANNOT have knowledge of it, since one cannot be certain of things that are themselves uncertain!). Or, in other words: How can one have knowledge (which is definite) of a future free choice (which, if it is truly free, is NOT definite)? 3 The hopeless result: There is no free will. In turn, punishments and rewards are always unjust (since no one is truly blameworthy or praiseworthy). The ideas of “virtues” and “vices” are meaningless. And it would be pointless to hope, or pray, for anything, since “hopes and prayers … have no force”. 3. Boethius’s Solution: Lady Philosophy disagrees. Boethius seems to think that: If X knows that P will occur, then P is “necessarily going to occur” (Pr. 4, 9-14). Knowledge of the Present: But, surely something similar does not apply when we see PRESENT things occurring. For instance, consider a case where you KNOW that a charioteer is presently driving a chariot. Isn’t that something you can know? There is no problem of having definite knowledge of something indefinite, since (a) you know that the driver is driving the chariot, and (b) he IS DEFINITELY driving it. Nevertheless, the fact that he is DEFINITELY, presently driving the chariot does not entail that he did not choose to do so freely.2 When you see present things, you are able to distinguish between “necessary” events (e.g., the Sun’s rising) and “voluntary” ones (e.g., human choices). Both are “necessary” or “certain” in that they are both DEFINITELY happening—however, there was only necessity in the event itself for ONE of those two events (namely, the Sun’s rising).