“There Are Only Two Ways in Which Humankind Can Produce Knowledge: Through Passive Observation Or Through Active Experiment. T

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

“There Are Only Two Ways in Which Humankind Can Produce Knowledge: Through Passive Observation Or Through Active Experiment. T “There are only two ways in which humankind can produce knowledge: through passive observation or through active experiment.” This statement raises important knowledge questions that have to do with the production of knowledge itself. The first is: How do we produce new knowledge? The second: Is the production of knowledge limited to certain methodologies? When I use the word “production,” I do not mean the acquisition of knowledge; I mean the discovery of new knowledge previously unknown to humanity. With this definition in mind, I agree with the statement. Passive observation and active experiment form the basis for the production of new knowledge, whether it is produced through the senses, trial and error, or the scientific method. Some would argue that knowledge is produced from ways of knowing (WOKs), while observation and experimentation are merely methods of checking whether that knowledge is true. I believe that WOKs can serve as catalysts for the production of knowledge – that they can produce ideas and theories – and, as such, are closely tied to and dependent on observation and experimentation. Ultimately, however, the actual discovery of new knowledge relies on passive observation and/or active experiment. To demonstrate this, I will examine several WOKs and analyze how each can be traced back to what I believe are the only two methods of producing knowledge. The first WOK that can be connected to the statement is sense perception - the use of our senses to examine the world around us. Passive observation is a method of noticing and understanding what our senses tell us without interfering or making judgments. It allows us to witness events and the existence of things in order to gather the information necessary for any discovery. Observation is also the first step in the scientific method. For example, when Charles Darwin visited the Galapagos Islands, he noticed that the beaks of the several species of finches were different according to their environment and diet. This observation later formed the basis for his Theory of Evolution. The second way of knowing that can be connected back to the statement is reason. Reason, the use of logic to make inferences about or deduce something, is involved with passive observation and active experiment. Active experiment is manipulating our surroundings to determine what the result will be. When we observe something, we can then use reason to determine a probable explanation. Observing the same thing multiple times can lead to the formation of a hypothesis – if a, then b. Once a hypothesis is formed, there are two ways that hypothesis can be tested. The first method is through trial and error, a primitive form of experimentation. When humans still lived as hunter-gatherers, before the scientific method had been developed, they did not always know which plants were safe to eat. Reason was essential to survival. For example, certain types of almonds contained cyanide, a poison, while others did not. Over time, humans learned through observation and experience which trees produced almonds that were deadly and which ones were safe. Then, they made sure to only eat from those that were safe. The second method is through designing an experiment specifically to test the hypothesis. Thanks to modern technology, we can now explore topics that go beyond simple survival skills and are far more complex, such as quantum theory. We still cannot completely escape trial and error, as we often have to test, for example, whether or not some product is safe. However, we have learned to run tests on animals to minimize the risk of humans being harmed. This shows that over time, reason has not only helped mankind in the production of knowledge, but has also been useful in helping to improve the safety and accuracy of our methods for producing knowledge. Again, however, while WOKs and methodologies are inextricably linked, the production of new knowledge and discovery is dependent on passive observation and active experiment. In my own experience, I used active experimentation in a science project. I burned several types of vegetable oils and compared their energy outputs to that of petroleum. While petroleum produced the most energy, some of the vegetable oils came very close to petroleum’s energy levels. Had this been an original experiment, it would have become new knowledge, although I would have had to run more verification trials. Even though my experiment had already been performed before, it further confirmed the previous experiment’s results. Not everyone would agree that observation and experimentation are the only ways to produce knowledge. As such a statement is a knowledge claim rather than a fact, it is open to debate. Some would argue that WOKs produce knowledge, while observation and experimentation are only used to check whether that knowledge is reliable or true. A justification for this is that sense perception and reason, the two WOKs with which the methodologies of observation and experimentation are most closely connected, are subjective. Senses can be fooled – a notable example being optical illusions, in which our mind is tricked into seeing things that don’t actually exist, into not seeing things that do exist, or seeing more than one image. Observation is also selective. Our minds see what they want to see. Memories can be distorted according to our personal biases. For example, eyewitness accounts are notoriously unreliable. Often, they turn out to be false. People who witness the same thing can have different observations. Reason, too, can be subjective. Right now, there are two leading theories that describe how the universe works: Quantum Theory and the Theory of Relativity. The former works on the atomic level and the latter works on larger bodies of mass. Both have decades’ worth of research and evidence behind them, but they cannot both be correct. In response, I would say this: other WOKs can serve as catalysts for producing knowledge but cannot produce new knowledge or discovery without observation and/or experimentation. Imagination, for example, can stimulate curiosity and lead to discovery, but our imaginations are based on the present world we see. Intuition may give us a gut or instinctual sense, but our subconscious thinking, the ability to process information quickly without evidence, is based on past observations. Language is a method for communicating new knowledge, but does not produce knowledge on its own. It is true that we must have a word for something in order to express it, and that the presence or absence of a certain expression in a language can affect one’s thinking, but languages are also adaptable. Every year, numerous words are added to the dictionary to express new terms and concepts. As society and technology progresses, so, too, does language. WOKs can create ideas and theories, but we can’t produce new knowledge or discovery without passive observation and active experiment. It is only through passive observation and active experiment that those ideas and theories from the WOKs are transformed into new knowledge or discovery. If a knowledge claim is made that cannot be tested - for example, “The universe has a creator” - then it is more of a belief or faith rather than knowledge. With regard to sense perception and reason being subjective, it’s true that they can be, but there are explanations. Just because they’re not always right does not mean we should conclude that they can never be relied on. Senses can be fooled; that has been established. However, the cases in which they can be fooled are generally very specific or isolated. It’s doubtful that most people would say that we could never rely on our senses. If our senses are inaccurate, how could we as a species have survived for so long? Moving on to reason, again, it is true that two people can make two of the same observations and come to two different conclusions. Does this mean reason has failed us? No. It merely suggests that further research or evidence is needed. In the case of how the universe works, we still don’t have all the data necessary to make a proper conclusion. “There are only two ways in which humankind can produce knowledge: through passive observation or through active experiment.” I believe this statement to be true when the definition of the word “produce” is limited to discovery and the production of new knowledge. As it is somewhat ambiguous, I cannot completely prove that this statement is true, but I can interpret it. Producing knowledge or discovery means adding to the shared knowledge of mankind as a whole, and I conclude that we only can produce new knowledge by either passive observation by active experiment. Ways of Knowing provide us with ideas and theories; observation and experimentation determine whether they are added to the shared knowledge of humanity. Word Count: 1,434 Bibliography Diamond, Jared M. Guns, Germs, and Steel: The Fates of Human Societies. New York: W.W. Norton, 1998. Print. .
Recommended publications
  • Can Dolphins Plan Their Behavior?
    International Journal of Comparative Psychology, 2010, 23, 664-670. Copyright 2010 by the International Society for Comparative Psychology Can Dolphins Plan their Behavior? Stan A. Kuczaj II University of Southern Mississippi, U.S.A. Mark J. Xitco Jr. Space and Naval Warfare Systems Center Pacific, U.S.A. John D. Gory Disney’s Animal Programs, U.S.A. The ability to plan one’s behavior in novel and appropriate ways when confronted with new problems has been found in members of relatively few species. This ability provides significant evolutionary advantages in that the planner can mentally assess possible solutions prior to implementing one of them, and so need not risk life and limb by muddling though possible solutions to problems via trial and error learning. Although there are instances of wild dolphin behavior that suggest planning, it is difficult to determine if such behaviors were the result of planning, trial and error learning, or even some form of serendipitous discovery. Investigations of problem solving in bottlenose dolphins living in zoological settings can better assess the actual causes of apparent planning, and such controlled studies have demonstrated that dolphins can plan their behaviors in novel contexts. These settings facilitate the assessment of processes that underlie behaviors of interest, while observations from the wild provide invaluable information about apparent planning behavior in various contexts. Integrating findings from both settings is necessary if we hope to fully understand the dolphin capacity for planning. Recent years have witnessed the discovery of a myriad array of cognitive abilities in a variety of species (see Wasserman & Zentall, 2006).
    [Show full text]
  • Beyond Trial-And-Error in a Selectionist Psychology
    Behavior and Philosophy, 30, 73-99 (2002). © 2002 Cambridge Center for Behavioral Studies BEYOND TRIAL-AND-ERROR IN A SELECTIONIST PSYCHOLOGY J.M. Cleaveland Universität Konstanz ABSTRACT: A common criticism of a selectionist psychology is that the mechanism of overt behavioral variability and environmental selection cannot account for instances of seemingly novel, intelligent behavior. However, behavioral novelty is quite easily accounted for in much the same manner as it is in phylogenetic selection—through an appreciation of historicity. Nonetheless, the issue of novelty is closely related to another issue that is problematic for a selectionist psychology, namely the issue of what constitutes an ontogenetic adaptation. Ontogenetic adaptations simply cannot be defined purely by reference to behavioral units. A solution to this quandary emerges by considering how phylogenetic selection distinguishes between codical and material units. The former are inferred, relational, and persist; the latter are directly observed and temporary. A similar distinction in a selectionist psychology exists between associations and behaviors, and I argue that ontogenetic selection is for associations—not behaviors. Such a stance does not require a conceptual nervous system, although it does subsume operant and classical conditioning phenomena under a common conceptual umbrella. Throughout the paper, various analogies between phylogenetic and ontogenetic selection are considered: Codical units (e.g., genotypes, associations) vs. material units (e.g., phenotypes, behavior), preparedness vs. fitness, instinctive drift vs. allometry, associative drift vs. genetic drift, associants vs. alleles. The object of such comparisons is not to claim that they are accurate but rather to stretch and push the overall analogy between phylogenetic and ontogenetic selectionism so as to delineate the latter more accurately.
    [Show full text]
  • (1963). Science As Falsification by Karl R. Popper
    The following excerpt was originally published in Conjectures and Refutations (1963). Science as Falsification by Karl R. Popper When I received the list of participants in this course and realized that I had been asked to speak to philosophical colleagues I thought, after some hesitation and consolation, that you would probably prefer me to speak about those problems which interests me most, and about those developments with which I am most intimately acquainted. I therefore decided to do what I have never done before: to give you a report on my own work in the philosophy of science, since the autumn 1919 when I first begin to grapple with the problem, "When should a theory be ranked as scientific?" or "Is there a criterion for the scientific character or status of a theory?" The problem which troubled me at the time was neither, "When is a theory true?" nor "When is a theory acceptable?" my problem was different. I wished to distinguish between science and pseudo-science; knowing very well that science often errs, and that pseudoscience may happen to stumble on the truth. I knew, of course, the most widely accepted answer to my problem: that science is distinguished from pseudoscience—or from "metaphysics"—by its empirical method, which is essentially inductive, proceeding from observation or experiment. But this did not satisfy me. On the contrary, I often formulated my problem as one of distinguishing between a genuinely empirical method and a non-empirical or even pseudo-empirical method — that is to say, a method which, although it appeals to observation and experiment, nevertheless does not come up to scientific standards.
    [Show full text]
  • Federal Philosophy of Science: a Deconstruction— and a Reconstruction*
    FEDERAL PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE: A DECONSTRUCTION— AND A RECONSTRUCTION* Susan Haack† I. A TANGLED TALE When they feel the need to distinguish genuine science—the real thing—from pretenders, or to understand what is distinctive about the scientific method, U.S. courts have sometimes called on Karl Popper’s conception of falsifiability as the hallmark of the genuinely scientific, and his account of the method of science as conjecture and refutation. Sometimes the legal issue before the courts is the interpretation of the Establishment Clause in applica- tion to biology teaching in public high schools, and the question is whether “creation science” is really science, or only religion in dis- guise.1 Much more often, though, the legal issue is one of evidence * This paper is based on a (much shorter) presentation, first given at a conference on “Objective Knowledge: Popper and Beyond,” at the Max Weber Program, Euro- pean University Institute, Fiesole, in March 2009. My thanks to Pamela Lucken for research assistance, and to Mark Migotti and Stephen Urice for helpful comments on draft versions. † Distinguished Professor in the Humanities, Cooper Senior Scholar in Arts and Sciences, Professor of Philosophy and Professor of Law, University of Miami. 1 In McLean v. Arkansas, for example, the court reasoned that, unlike the theory of evolu- tion, creation “science” is unfalsifiable, and so is not really science at all, but rather a reli- gious doctrine; hence a statute mandating equal time for evolution and creation science in public high-school biology classes was unconstitutional—in violation of the Establishment 394 2010] Federal Philosophy of Science 395 law, and the question is whether this or that scientific expert testi- mony is reliable enough to be admissible.
    [Show full text]
  • 1 SCIENCE: CONJECTURES and REFUTATIONS Karl R
    1/22 Conjectures and Refutations: The Growth of Scientific Knowledge Book by Karl R. Popper; Basic Books, 1962 1 SCIENCE: CONJECTURES AND REFUTATIONS Karl R. Popper Mr. Turnbull had predicted evil consequences, . and was now doing the best in his power to bring about the verification of his own prophecies. ANTHONY TROLLOPE I WHEN I received the list of participants in this course and realized that I had been asked to speak to philosophical colleagues I thought, after some hesitation and consultation, that you would probably prefer me to speak about those problems which interest me most, and about those developments with which I am most intimately acquainted. I therefore decided to do what I have never done before: to give you a report on my own work in the philosophy of science, since the autumn of 1919 when I first began to grapple with the problem, 'When should a theory be ranked as scientific?' or 'Is there a criterion for the scientific character or status of a theory?' The problem which troubled me at the time was neither, 'When is a theory true?' nor, 'When is a theory acceptable?' My problem was different. I wished to distinguish between science and pseudo- science; knowing very well that science often errs, and that pseudo-science may happen to stumble on the truth. I knew, of course, the most widely accepted answer to my problem: that science is distinguished from pseudo-science--or from 'metaphysics'--by its empirical method, which is essentially inductive, proceeding from observation or experiment. But this did not satisfy me.
    [Show full text]
  • Learning and Teaching : Theories, Approaches and Models
    LEARNING AND TEACHING : THEORIES, APPROACHES AND MODELS CHAPTER 2: BEHAVIORIST APPROACH Prof. Dr. Hasan Bacanlı Üskudar University, Faculty of Humanities and Social Sciences (Translated by Sakine Koca Sincer) Behaviorist Approach First of all, behaviour is composed of reactions and movements that an organism gives and does in a certain situation. The term, behaviour is mostly used for actions that can be observed from outside. Behaviorist learning approach mostly focuses on how behaviours are acquired. Behaviorist approach claims that learning can develop by means of establishing a connection between stimulus and behaviour, and that any behaviour can be changed through reinforcement. Behaviorists address learning as a mechanic process and give particular importance to objectivity. According to behaviorists, people are not good or bad from birth. Experiences and environment constitute a human’s personality. According to them, human brain can be compared to a black box. Neither can we know what is going on in this black box nor do we need to know it. What is important is not what is happening in this black box, but what is important is what goes in this black box (input) and what comes out of it (output). Outputs are objective, observable and measurable. Inputs and outputs can be adjusted, arranged and controlled. What is important is not the senses of a person, but the reflection of them.7 The pioneers of behaviorist approach are I. Pavlov, J.B. Watson, E.L. Thorndike, E.R. Guthrie and B.F. Skinner. History of Behaviorist Approach By the early 20th century, the science of psychology has had important turnouts, 20-30 years after Wundt established the first psychology laboratory.
    [Show full text]
  • 7 Classical Conditioning VI
    Instrumental Conditioning I: Control learning PSY/NEU338: Animal learning and decision making: Psychological, computational and neural perspectives a “simple” decision making task prediction helps decisions 2 predictions are for control If we can predict what situations are associated with rewards we can try to bring those about through our actions 3 outline • Thorndike: S-R learning • Basic properties of instrumental conditioning • Skinner: behaviorism, schedules of reinforcement 4 Edward Thorndike (1874-1949) • Background: Darwin, attempts to show that animals are intelligent • Thorndike was the first to show this systematically (not just anecdotes) • Age 23: submitted PhD thesis on “Animal intelligence: an experimental study of the associative processes in animals” • Tested hungry cats (also chicks, dogs) in “puzzle boxes” • operational definition for learning: time to escape • gradual learning curves, did not look like ‘insight’ but rather trial and error 5 THORNDIKE’S PUZZLE BOXES AND THE ORIGINS OF THE EXPERIMENTAL ANALYSIS OF BEHAVIOR - Paul Chance, JEAB (1999) There were 15 of these boxes, and they were constructed mainly of wooden slats and hardware cloth. Each box contained a door that the cat could open by manipulating some device. Cats opened the door to Box I by pressing a lever (The cat that first escaped from Box I may well deserve a place in history for being the first in a long line of lever-pressing animals.) Box K, the only box depicted graphically in the dissertation, required the performance of three distinct responses: The cat had to depress a treadle, pull on a string, and push a bar up or down before the door would finally fall open.
    [Show full text]
  • Federal Philosophy of Science: a Deconstruction- and a Reconstruction Susan Haack University of Miami School of Law, [email protected]
    University of Miami Law School University of Miami School of Law Institutional Repository Articles Faculty and Deans 2010 Federal Philosophy of Science: a Deconstruction- and a Reconstruction Susan Haack University of Miami School of Law, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://repository.law.miami.edu/fac_articles Part of the Evidence Commons, Law and Philosophy Commons, and the Legal History Commons Recommended Citation Susan Haack, Federal Philosophy of Science: a Deconstruction- and a Reconstruction, 5 N.Y.U. J.L. & Liberty 394 (2010). This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Faculty and Deans at University of Miami School of Law Institutional Repository. It has been accepted for inclusion in Articles by an authorized administrator of University of Miami School of Law Institutional Repository. For more information, please contact [email protected]. NEW YORK UNIVERSITY JOURNAL OF LAW & LIBERTY FEDERAL PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE: A DECONSTRUCTION- AND A RECONSTRUCTION* Susan Haackt I. A TANGLED TALE When they feel the need to distinguish genuine science - the real thing-from pretenders, or to understand what is distinctive about the scientific method, U.S. courts have sometimes called on Karl Popper's conception of falsifiability as the hallmark of the genuinely scientific, and his account of the method of science as conjecture and refutation. Sometimes the legal issue before the courts is the interpretation of the Establishment Clause in applica- tion to biology teaching in public high schools, and the question is whether "creation science" is really science, or only religion in dis- guise.' Much more often, though, the legal issue is one of evidence * This paper is based on a (much shorter) presentation, first given at a conference on "Objective Knowledge: Popper and Beyond," at the Max Weber Program, Euro- pean University Institute, Fiesole, in March 2009.
    [Show full text]
  • Irreconcilable Differences? the Troubled Marriage of Science and Law*
    02_HAACK_CONTRACT PROOF.DOC IRRECONCILABLE DIFFERENCES? THE TROUBLED MARRIAGE OF SCIENCE AND LAW* SUSAN HAACK** In many respects [the scientific expert] seems to be a positive annoyance to lawyers, and even to judges at times, a sort of intractable, incompatible, inharmonious factor, disturbing the otherwise smooth current of legal procedure; too important or necessary to be ruled out, too intelligent and disciplined mentally to yield without reason to ordinary rules and regulations of the court, . and, at the same time[,] possessing an undoubted influence with the jury, that it is difficult to restrict by the established rules and maxims of legal procedure.1 It is often said, with good cause, that . the goal of a trial and the goal of science are . at odds. [A]s a general rule, . courts don’t do science very well.2 I GETTING STARTED There was not a lot to be said for the miserable weeks after Hurricanes Katrina and Wilma—except, in retrospect, that all those hours spent sweating in the dark prompted some vivid thoughts about what life must have been like before electric light and power were available at the flick of a switch, and renewed my appreciation of the countless ways in which science now permeates just about every aspect of modern life. “Every aspect of modern life” including, of course, the legal system. Legal proceedings now often rely significantly on scientific testimony, and scientific advisors contribute significantly to regulatory decisionmaking.3 Moreover, the Copyright © 2009 by Susan Haack. This Article is also available at http://law.duke.edu/journals/lcp.
    [Show full text]
  • Karl Popper and the Social Sciences
    2 Karl Popper and the Social Sciences Sylvain K. Cibangu Regis University, Denver, University of Washington, Seattle, USA 1. Introduction The social sciences have a rich tradition, as shown by its various authors and theories found throughout written history. In the 1st century BC, for example, Seneca the younger stated that “human beings are social animals” (Cl.1.3.2). Not long before, in the 4th century BC, Aristotle insisted that “man is by nature [emphasis mine] a political animal” (Pol. 1.1.9). This chapter focuses on Karl Popper, a contemporary social thinker. Popper represented one of, if not, the most prolific authors that articulated the status of the social sciences. While Popper (1950/1971a, 1950/1971b, 1959/1992, 1963, 1972, 1982, 1983, 1991, 1996a) produced an extensive body of literature devoted to the social sciences, he has been given too little attention in modern social science historiography. Even though he “concentrated mainly on practical problems of the methodology of the social sciences” (Popper, 2008, p. 87), textbooks of social science methodology rarely include Popper’s writings. Consequently, his works on the social sciences and/or psychology, including his dissertation, remain largely unknown. This chapter explores the heretofore unexplored social themes that arise and recur in Popper’s writings. To begin to redress this gap in the Popperian scholarship, Popper’s (2008) recently published posthumous work is of particular interest to our discussion. I pay close attention to parts IV and V of this milestone book, which contains several of Popper’s unpublished materials concerned with social issues. These materials were collected from various archives preserved respectively at Stanford University (USA), University of Canterbury (New Zealand), and Klagenfurt University (Austria).
    [Show full text]
  • Against Morgan's Canonweb
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by PhilPapers This is a penultimate draft of a chapter to appear in K. Andrews and J. Beck (eds.), The Routledge Handbook of Philosophy of Animal Minds (Routledge). Please cite the published version. Against Morgan’s Canon Simon Fitzpatrick Department of Philosophy John Carroll University Introduction Despite a variety of critiques (e.g., de Waal 1999; Sober 1998, 2005; Fitzpatrick 2008; Andrews and Huss 2014; Meketa 2014; Starzak forthcoming), the principle known as Morgan’s Canon retains a significant hold on modern scientific and philosophical discussions of non-human animal (henceforth, “animal”) cognition and behavior. Proposed by the late nineteenth century British philosopher-psychologist, Conwy Lloyd Morgan—generally regarded as the “father” of modern comparative psychology—it states that: In no case may we interpret an action as the outcome of the exercise of a higher psychical faculty, if it can be interpreted as the outcome of the exercise of one which stands lower in the psychological scale. (Morgan 1894: 53) Morgan saw this principle as necessary for scientifically rigorous investigation into the minds of animals. It went on to exert enormous influence on the subsequent development of comparative psychology, though not always in ways consistent with Morgan’s original intent (Costall 1993; Thomas 1998; Fitzpatrick and Goodrich forthcoming). My focus will be on how Morgan’s Canon has been interpreted and applied by psychologists and philosophers since Morgan’s day, particularly over the last few decades, and whether or not it should continue to be accepted as a fundamental guiding principle for the study of animal cognition and behavior—to which the answer will be an emphatic “no”.
    [Show full text]
  • INTRODUCTION to ANIMAL BEHAVIOR the Word ' Ethology'
    INTRODUCTION TO ANIMAL BEHAVIOR The word ‘ethology’ is derived from two Greek word ‘ethos’ meaning culture and ‘logos’, meaning study. Behavior can be defined as observable activities an animal performs in response to the various stimuli in order to survive and reproduce. A behavioral act is a response to a stimulus which is the basic and universal concept of behavior. A stimulus is always a change in the internal or external environment of organisms. A stimulus may be in the form of signs/symbols or releases. Signs can be visual, auditory, chemical or other types of sensory models. A releaser stimulus releases certain programmed stereotyped activities or fixed action pattern (FAP) of behavior. A stimulus always elicits a response which is an attempt to adapt to the change. Thus behavior is generally stimulus- response oriented. The behavior of an organism is essentially an expression of the capabilities of its nervous system. While the environment determines the nature of the stimulus, the response involves the body, especially the nervous system of the organism which is genetically determined. AIMS AND OBJECTIVES OF ETHOLOGY 1. To understand why animals behave the way they do. 2. Understand the cause f behavior 3. The physiological mechanism that generates the action 4. To understand how behavior develops 5. To study the evolutionary history of behavior 6. To analyze the potentials of the nervous system 7. To study the range of behavior prevalent in the animal kingdom starting from innate to learned behavior, from fighting to cooperating etc 8. For effective management of game animals 9. The farmer must be aware of habits of his animals to get maximum benefit 10.
    [Show full text]