Full Four-Dimensional Diffeomorphism Invariants and Their Role in Quantum

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Full Four-Dimensional Diffeomorphism Invariants and Their Role in Quantum Intrinsic GR Full four-dimensional diffeomorphism invariants and their role in quantum theories of gravity Donald Salisbury Austin College, USA Balfest80 DIAS, Dublin, January 25, 2018 Intrinsic GR Collaborators Work performed in collaboration in part with Josep Pons, J¨urgen Renn, Larry Shepley, Kurt Sundermeyer See arXiv:1508.01277v5 Intrinsic GR Overview 1 Introduction 2 Brief history of Hamiltonian general covariance 3 Gauge conditions and associated invariants 4 Intrinsic gravitational Hamilton-Jacobi approach 5 Implications for loop quantum gravity? Intrinsic GR Introduction 1. INTRODUCTION Intrinsic GR Introduction Introduction Focus of this talk: What are some implications for an eventual quantum theory of gravity of the classical evolution of the metric with respect to temporal and spatial landmarks constructed with the use of Weyl curvature scalars. All variables are diffeomorphism invariants. Questions to be addressed: What is the status of the multiplicity of observer-based evolution in classical general relativity. How can the fully relational approach be applied to loop quantum gravity? Is there a meaningful quantum generalization to non-commuting intrinsic coordinate algebras in loop quantum gravity? Intrinsic GR Brief history of Hamiltonian general covariance 2. BRIEF HISTORY OF HAMILTONIAN GENERAL COVARIANCE Intrinsic GR Brief history of Hamiltonian general covariance Rosenfeld's 1930 tetrad gravitational Lagrangian \Zur Quantelung der Wellenfelder", Annalen der Physik 397, 113 (1930) Translation by Salisbury and Sundermeyer [Rosenfeld, 2017] 1 1 µ ν I LJ I LJ L = (−g) 2 E E ! ! − ! ! 2κ I J µ L ν ν L µ 1 −! +< (−g)1=2 i ¯γµ @ + Ω − m ¯ + L 2 µ µ em µ I Tetrads EI , Rotation coefficients !µ L, Fermion field , 1 I J spinor connection Ωµ = 4 γ γ !µIJ . Intrinsic GR Brief history of Hamiltonian general covariance Rosenfeld's 1930 tetrad Hamiltonian density Rosenfeld invented a systematic procedure for solving for the _ µ velocities EI in terms of the conjugate momenta given that the @2L Jacobian matrix _ µ _ ν is singular. Although he did not do this @EI EJ explicitly for this model, the result (see [Salisbury & Sundermeyer, 2017] ) is h ab a yi I [IJ] H = H0 gab; p ; Aa; p ; ; + λI F + λIJ F + λF I [IJ] where F , F and F are primary constraints and λI , λIJ and λ are arbitrary spacetime functions. Preceeding Bergmann and Dirac by twenty years! See [Salisbury, 2009]. Intrinsic GR Brief history of Hamiltonian general covariance Rosenfeld's infinitesimal phase space symmetry generator Rosenfeld proved that the vanishing Noether charge generated the correct variations of all of the phase space variables under all of the local symmetries. Most importantly for us is that the active variations under the infinitesimal coordinate transformations x0µ = xµ + ξµ(x) are correct. His conserved and vanishing generating density is I _0 I _a _0 aI ν a ν 0 a −F e0I ξ − F eaI ξ − FA0ξ − p eνI ξ;a − p Aνξ;a − HA0ξ − Gaξ e e _ a y IJ −Fξ + p ξ;a + i p ξ − i p y ξ + F[IJ]ξ = 0 ~c ~c Intrinsic GR Brief history of Hamiltonian general covariance Peter Bergmann and Paul Dirac We leap two decades forward to the contributions to constrained Hamiltonian dynamics of Peter Bergmann and Paul Dirac - beginning in 1949. Dirac never concerned himself with the phase space realization of the full general covariance group. See his Vancouver lectures, [Dirac, 1950] [Dirac, 1951] [Bergmann, 1949], later with Jim Anderson [Anderson & Bergmann, 1951] and numerous collaborators including [Goldberg, 1953] did concern themselves with this symmetry. In particular a joint publication with Ralph Schiller [Bergmann & Schiller, 1953] explicitly employed the vanishing Noether charge. Intrinsic GR Brief history of Hamiltonian general covariance Non-realizability of the diffeomorphism Lie algebra But there is an obstacle to the realization of finite diffeomorphisms, explicitly recognized by Bergmann. One can see this in the Lie algebra µ µ ν µ ν µ 0 µ 0 ξ3 = ξ1,νξ2 − ξ2,νξ1 = ξ1;0ξ2 − ξ2;0ξ1 + ::: Repeated commutators lead to higher and higher order time derivatives. Intrinsic GR Brief history of Hamiltonian general covariance Dirac's resolution Dirac's solution was probably inspired by his student Paul Weiss: write the infinitesimal variations as a sum of perpendicular and tangent increments, µ µ 0 µ a ξ = n + δa This results in the familiar metric dependent Dirac algebra. Intrinsic GR Brief history of Hamiltonian general covariance The Bergmann - Komar group [Bergmann & Komar, 1972] interpreted this algebra as representing a compulsory metric-dependent transformation group Intrinsic GR Gauge conditions and associated invariants 3. GAUGE CONDITIONS AND ASSOCIATED INVARIANTS Intrinsic GR Gauge conditions and associated invariants The Legendre projectability requirement We have an mathematical justification for the Dirac decomposition. It is required in order that configuration-velocity variations be projectable under the Legendre transformation to phase space, [Pons et al. , 1997] Intrinsic GR Gauge conditions and associated invariants Ashtekar-Barbero-Immirzi Lagrangian [Pons et al. , 2000], [Pons & Salisbury, 2002] The connection is α i i −1 i α i i −1 i a a Aa := !a − α Ka; A0 := Ω0 − α KaN + αTi N;a The Lagrangian is ∼_ ∼ ≈ ∼ L = α−1αAi T a + NaH + NαH + αAi αH ; ABI a i c ∼ 0 0 i where the secondary constraints are α ∼ α ∼a α ∼ ∼bα i Hi := −α DaT i = 0; Ha := αT i Fba = 0 and ≈ 1 ∼ ∼ αH := − T aT b(−α2αF ij + (1 + α2)3Rij ) = 0: 0 2 i j ab ab Intrinsic GR Gauge conditions and associated invariants Legendre-projectable infinitesimal symmetries It is noteworthy that when gauge symmetries are present in addition to diffeomorphism symmetry, the transformations of some of the additional gauge variables under the change of coordinates 0µ µ µ 0 µ a x = x − n ξ − δa ξ ; are no longer projectable. See [Pons et al. , 2000]. In this case the α i a variation of A0 acquires unprojectable time derivatives of N, N , α i and A0. But these can be removed by adding to the variation an µα i −1 bi SO(3) rotation with descriptor −n Aµ + αN T N;b ≈ α This is in fact the variation generated by H0. Intrinsic GR Gauge conditions and associated invariants The complete generator of infinitesimal symmetry transformations The primary constraints are the variables canonically conjugate to the lapse, shift, and time component of the connection. Combination of primary and secondary constraints, all first class, allows one to construct the full set of gauge generators 0 00 _A B C A Gξ = PAξ + (HA + PC 00 N CAB0 )ξ ; C 00 where CAB0 are the structure functions associated with the Poisson brackets of the secondary constraints and the descriptors ξ are infinitesimal arbitrary functions of spacetime coordinates appearing in the projectable infinitesimal coordinate transformations 0µ µ µ 0 µ a x = x − n ξ + δa ξ ; ∼ i α and local SO(3) gauge rotations - generated by ξ Hi . Intrinsic GR Gauge conditions and associated invariants Time evolution versus diffeomorphisms The evolution in time is generated by Z Z ∼ ∼ ≈ d3xH = d3x −αAi αH + NaαH + NαH + λ PA : ABI 0 i a ∼ 0 A R 3 But the finite diffeomorphism generator exp s d x Gξ(t) transforms solutions into new solutions. Intrinsic GR Gauge conditions and associated invariants Enlargement of phase space Note that the lapse function N, the shift Na and the nought α i component of the connection A0 must be retained as canonical variables. Note also that contrary to popular belief, the Hamiltonian formulation does not fix a time foliation. New foliations result in new multipliers λA and new Hamiltonians as a consequence of the time dependence of the Hamiltonian. Intrinsic GR Intrinsic gravitational Hamilton-Jacobi approach 4. INTRINSIC GRAVITATIONAL HAMILTON-JACOBI APPROACH Intrinsic GR Intrinsic gravitational Hamilton-Jacobi approach An implementation of Rovelli's partial variable program Now that we have the full diffeomorphism group at our disposal, we can employ it to establish correlations between partial variables. One possible implementation, in principle, is to locate temporal and spatial landmarks by referring to curvature even in the vacuum case. There are of course many more possibilities when matter is present. We will employ these landmarks as \intrinsic" coordinates. Such coordinates must be formed from spacetime ∼ µ α i b scalars. Thus we choose X [ Aa; T j ]. In the vacuum case we propose the use of the four Weyl curvature scalars, as originally suggested by [Komar, 1958]. They are quadratic and cubic in the Weyl tensor. [Bergmann & Komar, 1960] showed that they are expressible solely in terms of the three metric and its conjugate momenta. The same ∼ α i b logic demonstrates dependence only on Aa and T j Intrinsic GR Intrinsic gravitational Hamilton-Jacobi approach Weyl scalars in the Ashtekar program In fact, we have for the complex connections that the Newman-Penrose scalars are 1 (i abc j) ij = t a F : 4 ∼ bc (See [Salisbury et al. , 1994], summarizing results originally due to [Capovilla et al. , 1991]). The Weyl scalars are in turn expressible j i j k i as I = i j and J = i j k . (See [Penrose & Rindler, 1988]) Intrinsic GR Intrinsic gravitational Hamilton-Jacobi approach Proof of principle Weyl scalars can always serve as coordinates in a local Riemann normal coordinate system. Overlapping patches can then cover the entire manifold. 1 Expand the metric in the neighborhood of any spacetime event to third order. See, for example, [Brewin, 2009] 1 1 g (x) = g − xρxσR − xρxσxκ@ R + O(4) µν µν 3 µνρσ 6 κ µνρσ 2 Keep only the linear in xµ contributions to I and J and solve for the xµ in terms of the I and J.
Recommended publications
  • Group Theory
    Appendix A Group Theory This appendix is a survey of only those topics in group theory that are needed to understand the composition of symmetry transformations and its consequences for fundamental physics. It is intended to be self-contained and covers those topics that are needed to follow the main text. Although in the end this appendix became quite long, a thorough understanding of group theory is possible only by consulting the appropriate literature in addition to this appendix. In order that this book not become too lengthy, proofs of theorems were largely omitted; again I refer to other monographs. From its very title, the book by H. Georgi [211] is the most appropriate if particle physics is the primary focus of interest. The book by G. Costa and G. Fogli [102] is written in the same spirit. Both books also cover the necessary group theory for grand unification ideas. A very comprehensive but also rather dense treatment is given by [428]. Still a classic is [254]; it contains more about the treatment of dynamical symmetries in quantum mechanics. A.1 Basics A.1.1 Definitions: Algebraic Structures From the structureless notion of a set, one can successively generate more and more algebraic structures. Those that play a prominent role in physics are defined in the following. Group A group G is a set with elements gi and an operation ◦ (called group multiplication) with the properties that (i) the operation is closed: gi ◦ g j ∈ G, (ii) a neutral element g0 ∈ G exists such that gi ◦ g0 = g0 ◦ gi = gi , (iii) for every gi exists an −1 ∈ ◦ −1 = = −1 ◦ inverse element gi G such that gi gi g0 gi gi , (iv) the operation is associative: gi ◦ (g j ◦ gk) = (gi ◦ g j ) ◦ gk.
    [Show full text]
  • Council for Innovative Research Peer Review Research Publishing System
    ISSN 2347-3487 Einstein's gravitation is Einstein-Grossmann's equations Alfonso Leon Guillen Gomez Independent scientific researcher, Bogota, Colombia E-mail: [email protected] Abstract While the philosophers of science discuss the General Relativity, the mathematical physicists do not question it. Therefore, there is a conflict. From the theoretical point view “the question of precisely what Einstein discovered remains unanswered, for we have no consensus over the exact nature of the theory's foundations. Is this the theory that extends the relativity of motion from inertial motion to accelerated motion, as Einstein contended? Or is it just a theory that treats gravitation geometrically in the spacetime setting?”. “The voices of dissent proclaim that Einstein was mistaken over the fundamental ideas of his own theory and that their basic principles are simply incompatible with this theory. Many newer texts make no mention of the principles Einstein listed as fundamental to his theory; they appear as neither axiom nor theorem. At best, they are recalled as ideas of purely historical importance in the theory's formation. The very name General Relativity is now routinely condemned as a misnomer and its use often zealously avoided in favour of, say, Einstein's theory of gravitation What has complicated an easy resolution of the debate are the alterations of Einstein's own position on the foundations of his theory”, (Norton, 1993) [1]. Of other hand from the mathematical point view the “General Relativity had been formulated as a messy set of partial differential equations in a single coordinate system. People were so pleased when they found a solution that they didn't care that it probably had no physical significance” (Hawking and Penrose, 1996) [2].
    [Show full text]
  • [Physics.Hist-Ph] 14 Dec 2011 Poincaré and Special Relativity
    Poincar´eand Special Relativity Emily Adlam Department of Philosophy, The University of Oxford Abstract Henri Poincar´e’s work on mathematical features of the Lorentz transfor- mations was an important precursor to the development of special relativity. In this paper I compare the approaches taken by Poincar´eand Einstein, aim- ing to come to an understanding of the philosophical ideas underlying their methods. In section (1) I assess Poincar´e’s contribution, concluding that al- though he inspired much of the mathematical formalism of special relativity, he cannot be credited with an overall conceptual grasp of the theory. In section (2) I investigate the origins of the two approaches, tracing differences to a disagreement about the appropriate direction for explanation in physics; I also discuss implications for modern controversies regarding explanation in the philosophy of special relativity. Finally, in section (3) I consider the links between Poincar´e’s philosophy and his science, arguing that apparent inconsistencies in his attitude to special relativity can be traced back to his acceptance of a ‘convenience thesis’ regarding conventions. Keywords Poincare; Einstein; special relativity; explanation; conventionalism; Lorentz transformations arXiv:1112.3175v1 [physics.hist-ph] 14 Dec 2011 1 1 Did Poincar´eDiscover Special Relativity? Poincar´e’s work introduced many ideas that subsequently became impor- tant in special relativity, and on a cursory inspection it may seem that his 1905 and 1906 papers (written before Einstein’s landmark paper was pub- lished) already contain most of the major features of the theory: he had the correct equations for the Lorentz transformations, articulated the relativity principle, derived the correct relativistic transformations for force and charge density, and found the rule for relativistic composition of velocities.
    [Show full text]
  • Einstein's Equations for Spin 2 Mass 0 from Noether's Converse Hilbertian
    Einstein’s Equations for Spin 2 Mass 0 from Noether’s Converse Hilbertian Assertion October 4, 2016 J. Brian Pitts Faculty of Philosophy, University of Cambridge [email protected] forthcoming in Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics Abstract An overlap between the general relativist and particle physicist views of Einstein gravity is uncovered. Noether’s 1918 paper developed Hilbert’s and Klein’s reflections on the conservation laws. Energy-momentum is just a term proportional to the field equations and a “curl” term with identically zero divergence. Noether proved a converse “Hilbertian assertion”: such “improper” conservation laws imply a generally covariant action. Later and independently, particle physicists derived the nonlinear Einstein equations as- suming the absence of negative-energy degrees of freedom (“ghosts”) for stability, along with universal coupling: all energy-momentum including gravity’s serves as a source for gravity. Those assumptions (all but) imply (for 0 graviton mass) that the energy-momentum is only a term proportional to the field equations and a symmetric curl, which implies the coalescence of the flat background geometry and the gravitational potential into an effective curved geometry. The flat metric, though useful in Rosenfeld’s stress-energy definition, disappears from the field equations. Thus the particle physics derivation uses a reinvented Noetherian converse Hilbertian assertion in Rosenfeld-tinged form. The Rosenfeld stress-energy is identically the canonical stress-energy plus a Belinfante curl and terms proportional to the field equations, so the flat metric is only a convenient mathematical trick without ontological commitment. Neither generalized relativity of motion, nor the identity of gravity and inertia, nor substantive general covariance is assumed.
    [Show full text]
  • Ngit `500&2-256
    NGiT `500&2-256 Foundations for a Theory of Gravitation Theories* 9 KIP S. THORNE, DAVID L. LEE,t and ALAN P. LIGHTMAN$ California Institute of Technology, Pasadena, California 91109 ABSTRACT A foundation is laid for future analyses of gravitation theories. This foundation is applicable to any theory formulated in terms of geometric objects defined on a 4-dimensional spacetime manifold. The foundation consists of (i) a glossary of fundamental concepts; (ii) a theorem that delineates the overlap between Lagrangian-based theories and metric theories; (iii) a conjecture (due to Schiff) that the Weak Equivalence Principle implies the Einstein Equivalence Principle; and (iv) a plausibility argument supporting this conjecture for the special case of relativistic, Lagrangian-based theories. Reproduced by NATIONAL TECHNICAL INFORMATION SERVICE US Department of Commerce Springfield, VA. 22151 Supported in part by the National Aeronautics and Space Administration [NGR 05-002-256] and the National Science Foundation [GP-27304, GP-28027]. t Imperial Oil Predoctoral Fellow. NSF Predoctoral Fellow during part of the period of this research. , (NASA-CR-130753) FOUNDATIONS FOR A N73-17499 I THEORY OF GRAVITATION THEORIES (California Inst. of Tech.) 45 p HC. $4.25 CSCL 08N Unclas V_._ __ _ ~ ___ __ _-G3/13 172 52 -' / I. INTRODUCTION Several years ago our group initiatedl a project of constructing theo- retical foundations for experimental tests of gravitation theories. The results of that project to date (largely due to Clifford M. Will and Wei-Tou Ni), and the results of a similar project being carried out by the group of Kenneth Nordtvedt at Montana State University, are summarized in several 2-4 recent review articles.
    [Show full text]
  • Generally Covariant Quantum Mechanics
    Proceedings of Institute of Mathematics of NAS of Ukraine 2004, Vol. 50, Part 2, 993–998 Generally Covariant Quantum Mechanics Jaroslaw WAWRZYCKI Institute of Nuclear Physics, ul. Radzikowskiego 152, 31-342 Krak´ow, Poland E-mail: [email protected], [email protected] We present a complete theory, which is a generalization of Bargmann’s theory of factors for ray representations. We apply the theory to the generally covariant formulation of the Quantum Mechanics. 1 Problem In the standard Quantum Mechanics (QM) and the Quantum Field Theory (QFT) the space- time coordinates are pretty classical variables. Therefore the question about the general cova- riance of QM and QFT emerges naturally just like in the classical theory: what is the effect of a change in space-time coordinates in QM and QFT when the change does not form any symmetry transformation? It is a commonly accepted belief that there are no substantial difficulties if we refer the question to the wave equation. We simply treat the wave equation, and do not say why, in such a manner as if it was a classical equation. The only problem arising is to find the transformation rule ψ → Trψ for the wave function ψ. This procedure, which on the other hand can be seriously objected, does not solve the above-stated problem. The heart of the problem as well as that of QM and QFT, lies in the Hilbert space of states, and specifically in finding the representation Tr of the covariance group in question. The trouble gets its source in the fact that the covariance transformation changes the form of the wave equation such that ψ and Trψ do not belong to the same Hilbert space, which means that Tr does not act in the ordinary Hilbert space.
    [Show full text]
  • Untying the Knot: How Einstein Found His Way Back to Field Equations Discarded in the Zurich Notebook
    MAX-PLANCK-INSTITUT FÜR WISSENSCHAFTSGESCHICHTE Max Planck Institute for the History of Science 2004 PREPRINT 264 Michel Janssen and Jürgen Renn Untying the Knot: How Einstein Found His Way Back to Field Equations Discarded in the Zurich Notebook MICHEL JANSSEN AND JÜRGEN RENN UNTYING THE KNOT: HOW EINSTEIN FOUND HIS WAY BACK TO FIELD EQUATIONS DISCARDED IN THE ZURICH NOTEBOOK “She bent down to tie the laces of my shoes. Tangled up in blue.” —Bob Dylan 1. INTRODUCTION: NEW ANSWERS TO OLD QUESTIONS Sometimes the most obvious questions are the most fruitful ones. The Zurich Note- book is a case in point. The notebook shows that Einstein already considered the field equations of general relativity about three years before he published them in Novem- ber 1915. In the spring of 1913 he settled on different equations, known as the “Entwurf” field equations after the title of the paper in which they were first pub- lished (Einstein and Grossmann 1913). By Einstein’s own lights, this move compro- mised one of the fundamental principles of his theory, the extension of the principle of relativity from uniform to arbitrary motion. Einstein had sought to implement this principle by constructing field equations out of generally-covariant expressions.1 The “Entwurf” field equations are not generally covariant. When Einstein published the equations, only their covariance under general linear transformations was assured. This raises two obvious questions. Why did Einstein reject equations of much broader covariance in 1912-1913? And why did he return to them in November 1915? A new answer to the first question has emerged from the analysis of the Zurich Notebook presented in this volume.
    [Show full text]
  • Are Neutrinos Spinorial Tachyons?
    Are neutrinos spinorial tachyons? Jakub Rembieli´nski∗ Katedra Fizyki Teoretycznej, UniwersytetL´odzki ul. Pomorska 149/153, 90–236L´od´z, Poland† Abstract Quantum field theory of space-like particles is investigated in the framework of absolute causality scheme preserving Lorentz symmetry. It is shown that tachyons are associated with unitary orbits of Poincar´emap- pings induced from SO(2) little group instead of SO(2, 1) one. Therefore the corresponding elementary states are labelled by helicity. A particular ± 1 case of the helicity λ = 2 is investigated in detail and a correspond- ing consistent field theory is proposed. In particular, it is shown that the Dirac-like equation proposed by Chodos et al. [1], inconsistent in the standard formulation of QFT, can be consistently quantized in the presented framework. This allows us to treat more seriously possibility that neutrinos can be fermionic tachyons as it is suggested by the present experimental data about neutrino masses [2]. 1 Introduction Almost all recent experiments, measuring directly or indirectly the electron and muon neutrino masses, have yielded negative values for the mass square [2, 1]. It suggests that these particles might be fermionic tachyons. This intriguing arXiv:hep-ph/9509220v2 15 Sep 1995 possibility was written down some years ago by Chodos et al. [1] and Recami et al. [3]. In the light of the mentioned experimental data we observe a return of interest in tachyons [4, 5]. On the other hand, in the current opinion, there is no satisfactory theory of superluminal particles. This persuasion creates a psychological barrier to take such possibility seriously.
    [Show full text]
  • Some Remarks on the Notions of General Covariance And
    Some remarks on the notions of general covariance and background independence Domenico Giulini University of Freiburg Department of Physics Hermann-Herder-Strasse 3 D-79104 Freiburg, Germany Abstract The notion of ‘general covariance’is intimately related to the notion of ‘back- ground independence’. Sometimes these notions are even identified. Such an identification was made long ago by James Anderson, who suggested to de- fine ‘general covariance’ as absence of what he calls ‘absolute structures’, a term here taken to define the even less concrete notion of ‘background’. We discuss some of the well known difficulties that occur when one tries to give a precise definition of the notion of ‘absolute structure’. As a result, there still seem to be fundamental difficulties in defining ‘general covariance’ or ‘background independence’ so as to become a non-trivial selection principle for fundamental physical theories. In the second part of this contribution we make some historical remarks concerning the 1913 ‘Entwurf’-Theoryby Einstein and Grossmann, in which general covariance was first put to the fore, and in which Einstein presented an argument why Poincar´e-invariant theories for a zero-mass scalar gravita- tional field necessarily suffer from severe inconsistencies concerning energy conservation. This argument is instructive, even though—or because—it ap- pears to be incorrect, as we will argue below. arXiv:gr-qc/0603087v1 22 Mar 2006 This paper is a contribution to “An assessment of current paradigms in the physics of fundamentalinteractions”, edited by I.O. Stamatescu (Springer Verlag, to appear). 1 Contents 1 Introduction 3 2 Attempts to define general covariance and/or background independence 4 2.1 Laws of motion: covariance versus invariance .
    [Show full text]
  • "ENTWURF" FIELD EQUATIONS to the EINSTEIN TENSOR II: November 1915 Until March 1916
    1 FROM THE BERLIN "ENTWURF" FIELD EQUATIONS TO THE EINSTEIN TENSOR II: November 1915 until March 1916 Galina Weinstein Visitor Scholar, Center for Einstein Studies, Philosophy Department, Boston University January 25, 2012 I discuss Einstein's path-breaking November 1915 General Relativity papers. I show that Einstein's field equations of November 25, 1915 with an additional term on the right hand side involving the trace of the energy-momentum tensor appear to have sprung from his first November 1915 paper: the November 4, 1915 equations. Second paper among three papers. 1 Introduction: David Hilbert Enters the Game, the priority dispute in a nutshell According to Stachel Einstein's Odyssey to general covariance during November 1915 went through two stages:1 1) Sometime in October 1915 Einstein dropped the Einstein-Grossman "Entwurf" theory. During October 1915 Einstein realized that the key to the solution lays in equations (14) and (17) of page 1041 of his 1914 review article "The Formal Foundation of the General Theory of Relativity", and adopted the determinant in equation (14), 1 as a postulate.2 This led him to general covariance. Starting on November 4 Einstein gradually expanded the range of the covariance of his field equations. 2) Between November 4 and November 11 Einstein realized that he did not need this postulate and he adopted it as a coordinate condition to simplify the field equations. Einstein was able to write the field equations of gravitation in a general covariant form. In the November 11 field equations the trace of the energy-momentum tensor vanishes. Between November 18 and November 25 Einstein found that he could write the field equations with an additional term on the right hand side of the field equations involving the trace of the energy-momentum tensor, which now need not vanish.
    [Show full text]
  • Introduction Can Only Be Influenced by Its Immediate Sur- Roundings
    1 note1 : November 4, 2014 Introduction can only be influenced by its immediate sur- roundings. In the context of particle physics, Quantum Field Theory is a theory of elementary particles and their From this principle follows the finite speed of interactions. The Standard Model of elementary information transmission. particles is a quantum field theory. Principle of covariance By definition, elementary particles are the most The principle of covariance emphasizes formu- fundamental — structureless — particles (like elec- lation of physical laws using only those phys- trons and photons) which exist in our universe. Ele- ical quantities the measurements of which the mentary particles exhibit wave-particle duality: on observers in different frames of reference could the one hand they diffract and interfere as waves unambiguously correlate. (or fields), on the other hand they appear and dis- appear as whole entities (called quanta). Hence the Mathematically speaking, the physical quanti- name of the theory. ties must transform covariantly, that is, un- A quantum field theory seeks to explain certain der a certain representation of the group of fundamental experimental observations — like the coordinate transformations between admissi- existence of antiparticles; the spin-statistics rela- ble frames of reference of the physical theory. tion; the CPT symmetry — as well as to predict This group of coordinate transformations is re- the results of any given experiment, like the cross- ferred to as the covariance group of the theory. section for the Compton scattering, or the value of The principle of covariance does not require the anomalous magnetic moment of the electron. invariance of physical laws under the group of There are two popular approaches to deal with admissible transformations although in most quantum fields.
    [Show full text]
  • General-Relativistic Covariance
    General-Relativistic Covariance April 25, 2019 Author information Neil Dewar (ORCID 0000-0001-6623-4529) Munich Center for Mathematical Philosophy LMU Munich Fakultät Für Philosophie, Wissenschaftstheorie und Religionswissenschaft Geschwister-Scholl-Platz 1 Munich 80539 Germany Contact information E: [email protected] T: 00447799762727 Abstract This is an essay about general covariance, and what it says (or doesn’t say) about spacetime structure. After outlining a version of the dynamical approach to spacetime theories, and how it struggles to deal with generally covariant theories, I argue that we should think about the symmetry structure of spacetime rather differently in generally- covariant theories compared to non-generally-covariant theories: namely, as a form of internal rather than external symmetry structure. 1 General-Relativistic Covariance April 25, 2019 1. Introduction This essay is about the feature of general relativity from which the hole argument springs: namely, general covariance. Famously, Einstein took the general covariance of the theory to express its commitment to a notion of “general relativity”, i.e., of the equivalence of all states of motion (just as the special covariance of special relativity expressed the equivalence of all inertial motion). In general, philosophers have been unpersuaded by Einstein’s claim, pointing to two problems in particular: the fact that general-relativistic spacetimes have a covariant derivative operator, and hence the re- sources to distinguish between inertial and non-inertial motion; and the fact that other theories (e.g. special relativity) can also be given a generally covariant formulation, which suggests that general covariance per se cannot be a physically significant feature of a theory.
    [Show full text]