Herring: Criminal Law, Text, Cases, and Materials, 8Th Edition

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Herring: Criminal Law, Text, Cases, and Materials, 8Th Edition Herring: Criminal Law, Text, Cases, and Materials, 8th edition BIBLIOGRAPHY AND FURTHER READING ABBATE, F. (1992) ‘The Conspiracy Doctrine: A Critique’ in M. Gore and S. Harwood (eds) Controversies in Criminal Law (Boulder, CO: Westview). AINSWORTH, P. (2000) Psychology and Crime (Harlow: Longman). AKDENIZ, Y. (1996) ‘Section 3 of the Computer Misuse Act 1990—An Antidote for Computer Viruses’ Web Journal of Current Legal Issues. ALCOHOL CONCERN (2005) www.alcoholconcern.org.uk/. ALCOHOL CONCERN (2013) Statistics on alcohol (London: Alcohol Concern). ALEXANDER, L. (1996) ‘The Moral Magic of Consent (II)’ Legal Theory 2: 165. ALEXANDER, L. (1999) ‘Propter Honoris Respectum: A Unified Excuse of Pre- emptive Self-protection’ Notre Dame Law Review 74: 1475. ALEXANDER, L. (2000) ‘Insufficient Concern: A Unified Conception of Criminal Culpability’ California Law Review 88: 955. ALEXANDER, L. (2002) ‘Criminal Liability for Omissions’ in S. Shute and A. Simester (eds) Criminal Law Theory (Oxford: Oxford University Press). ALEXANDER, L. (2005) ‘Lesser Evils: A Closer Look at the Paradigmatic Justification’ Law and Philosophy 24: 611. ALEXANDER, L. (2013) ‘Causing the Conditions of One’s Defense: A Theoretical Non-problem’ Criminal Law and Philosophy 7: 623. ALEXANDER, L. AND KESSLER, K. (1997) ‘Mens Rea and Inchoate Crimes’ Journal of Law and Criminology 87: 1138. © Jonathan Herring, 2016. All rights reserved. Herring: Criminal Law, Text, Cases, and Materials, 8th edition ALEXANDER, L. AND KESSLER FERZAN, K. (2009) Crime and Culpability: A Theory of Criminal Law (Oxford: Oxford University Press). ALEXANDER, L. AND KESSLER FERZAN, K. (2011) ‘Beyond the Special Part’ in S. Green and R.A. Duff (eds) Philosophical Foundations of Criminal Law (Oxford: Oxford University Press). ALEXANDER, L., HURD, H. AND WESTEN, P. (2016) ‘Consent does not require communication: A Reply to Dougherty’ Law and Philosophy 35: 655 ALL PARTY PARLIAMENTARY INTERNET GROUP (2004) Revision of the Computer Misuse Act (London: APIG). ALLDRIDGE, P. (1983) ‘The Coherence of Defences’ Criminal Law Review 665. ALLDRIDGE, P. (1990) ‘The Doctrine of Innocent Agency’ Criminal Law Forum 2: 45. ALLDRIDGE, P. (1992) ‘Common Sense, Innocent Agency, and Causation’ Criminal Law Forum 4: 299. ALLDRIDGE, P. (1993a) ‘Sex, Lies and the Criminal Law’ Northern Ireland Law Quarterly 250. ALLDRIDGE, P. (1993b) ‘Attempted Murder of the Soul: Blackmail, Privacy and Secrets’ Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 13: 368. ALLDRIDGE, P. (2002) ‘Making Criminal Law Known’ in S. Shute and S. Simester (eds) Criminal Law Theory (Oxford: Oxford University Press). ALLEN, H. (1987) Justice Unbalanced (Milton Keynes: Open University Press). © Jonathan Herring, 2016. All rights reserved. Herring: Criminal Law, Text, Cases, and Materials, 8th edition ALLEN, M. (1995) ‘Consent and Assault’ Journal of Criminal Law 58: 183. ALLEN, M. (2007) Textbook on Criminal Law (Oxford: Oxford University Press). ALMOND, P. (2014) Corporate Manslaughter and Regulatory Reform (Palgrave) ALTMAN, S. (1993) ‘A Patchwork Theory of Blackmail’ University of Pennsylvania Law Review 141: 1639. AMNESTY INTERNATIONAL (2005) Sexual Assaults Research (London: Amnesty International). ANDERSON, J. (2008) ‘No Licence for Thuggery: Violence, Sport and the Criminal Law’ Criminal Law Review 751. ANDERSON, M. (2005) ‘Negotiating Sex’ Southern California Law Review 78: 1401. ANDERSON, M. (2010) ‘Diminishing The Legal Impact of Negative Social Attitudes Toward Acquaintance Rape Victims’ New Criminal Law Review 13: 644. ANON (1986) ‘The Cultural Defense in the Criminal Law’ Harvard Law Review 99: 1293. ARCHARD, D. (1998) Sexual Consent (Boulder, CO: Westview). ARCHARD, D. (2013) ‘Criminalising medical negligence’ in A. Alghrani, R. Bennett and S. Ost (eds) Bioethics, Medicine and the Criminal Law (Cambridge: CUP). ARENELLA, P. (1990) ‘Character, Choice and Moral Agency’ Social Philosophy and Policy 7: 67. © Jonathan Herring, 2016. All rights reserved. Herring: Criminal Law, Text, Cases, and Materials, 8th edition ARENELLA, P. (1992) ‘Convicting the Morally Blameless: Reassessing the Relationship between Legal and Moral Accountability’ University of California Los Angeles Law Review 39: 1511. ARENSON, K. (2014) ‘The Paradox of Disallowing Duress as a Defence to Murder’ Journal of Criminal Law 78: 65 ASHFORD, C. (2010) ‘Barebacking and the “Cult of Violence”: Queering the Criminal Law’ Journal of Criminal Law 74: 339. ASHWORTH, A. (1975) ‘Reason, Logic and Criminal Liability’ Law Quarterly Review 91: 102. ASHWORTH, A. (1976) ‘The Doctrine of Provocation’ Cambridge Law Journal 35: 292. ASHWORTH, A. (1978) ‘Transferred Malice and Punishment for Unforeseen Consequences’ in P. Glazebrook (ed.) Reshaping the Criminal Law (London: Stevens). ASHWORTH, A. (1980) ‘Intoxication and General Defences’ Criminal Law Review 556. ASHWORTH, A. (1987) ‘Defining Criminal Offences without Harm’ in P.F. Smith (ed.) Criminal Law: Essays in Honour of J.C. Smith (London: Butterworths). ASHWORTH, A. (1988) ‘Criminal Attempts and the Role of Resulting Harm under the Code, and in the Common Law’ Rutgers Law Journal 19: 725. ASHWORTH, A. (1989) ‘The Scope of Criminal Liability for Omissions’ Law Quarterly Review 105: 424. © Jonathan Herring, 2016. All rights reserved. Herring: Criminal Law, Text, Cases, and Materials, 8th edition ASHWORTH, A. (1996) ‘The Treatment of Good Intentions’ in A. Simester and A. Smith (eds) Harm and Culpability (Oxford: Oxford University Press). ASHWORTH, A. (2000a) ‘Victim’s Rights, Defendant’s Rights and Criminal Procedure’ in A. Crawford and J. Goodey (eds) Integrating a Victim Perspective within Criminal Justice (Aldershot: Ashgate Dartmouth). ASHWORTH, A. (2000b) ‘The Human Rights Act and the Substantive Criminal Law: A Non-minimalist View’ Criminal Law Review 564. ASHWORTH, A. (2000c) ‘Is Criminal Law a Lost Cause?’ Law Quarterly Review 116: 225. ASHWORTH, A. (2002a) Human Rights, Serious Crime and Criminal Procedure (London: Sweet & Maxwell). ASHWORTH, A. (2002b) ‘Re-drawing the Boundaries of Entrapment’ Criminal Law Review 161. ASHWORTH, A. (2002c) ‘Robbery Re-assessed’ Criminal Law Review 851. ASHWORTH, A. (2004) ‘Social Control and Anti-social Behaviour’ Law Quarterly Review 120: 263. ASHWORTH, A. (2005) Sentencing and Criminal Justice (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press). ASHWORTH, A. (2007) ‘Principles, Pragmatism and the Law Commission’s Recommendations on Homicide Law Reform’ Criminal Law Review 333. © Jonathan Herring, 2016. All rights reserved. Herring: Criminal Law, Text, Cases, and Materials, 8th edition ASHWORTH, A. (2008a) ‘Murder: Defence—Young Defendant—Intention to Kill— Defendant’s Father Instructing Him to Assist in Murder’ Criminal Law Review 138. ASHWORTH, A. (2008b) ‘A Change of Normative Position: Determining the Contours of Culpability in Criminal Law’ New Criminal Law Review 11: 232. ASHWORTH, A. (2009) Principles of Criminal Law (Oxford: Oxford University Press). ASHWORTH, A. (2010) ‘Child Defendants and the Doctrines of the Criminal Law’ in J. Chalmers, F. Leverick, and L. Farmer (eds) Essays in Criminal Law in Honour of Sir Gerald Gordon (Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press). ASHWORTH, A. (2011a) ‘Ignorance of the Criminal Law, and Duties to Avoid it’ Modern Law Review 74: 1. ASHWORTH, A. (2011b) ‘The Unfairness of Risk-Based Possession Offences’ Criminal Law and Philosophy 5: 237. ASHWORTH, A. (2011c) ‘Attempts’ in J. Deigh and D. Dolinko (eds) The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Criminal Law (Oxford: OUP). ASHWORTH, A. (2013) Positive Obligations in Criminal Law (Oxford: Hart). ASHWORTH, A. (2014) ‘A decade of human rights in criminal justice’ Criminal Law Review 325 ASHWORTH, A. (2015) ‘Manslaughter by omission and the rule of law’ Criminal Law Review 563 ASHWORTH, A. (2017) ‘Positive duties, regulation and the criminal sanction’ Law Quarterly Review 606 © Jonathan Herring, 2016. All rights reserved. Herring: Criminal Law, Text, Cases, and Materials, 8th edition ASHWORTH, A. AND BLAKE, M. (1996) ‘The Presumption of Innocence in English Criminal Law’ Criminal Law Review 306. ASHWORTH, A. AND HORDER, J. (2013) Principles of Criminal Law (7th edn, Oxford: Oxford University Press). ASHWORTH, A. AND MITCHELL, B. (2000) ‘Introduction’ in A. Ashworth and B. Mitchell (eds) Rethinking English Homicide Law (Oxford: Oxford University Press). ASHWORTH, A. AND REDMAYNE, M. (2010) The Criminal Process (4th edn, Oxford: Oxford University Press). ASHWORTH, A. AND STRANGE, M. (2003) ‘Criminal Law and Human Rights’ European Human Rights Law Review 2: 139. ASHWORTH, A., ZEDNER, L. AND TOMLIN, P. (eds) (2013) Prevention and the Limits of the Criminal Law (Oxford: Oxford University Press). ASSOCIATION OF CHIEF POLICE OFFICERS (2006) Results of Operation Matisse (London: ACPO). AUSTIN, J. (1956) ‘A Plea for Excuses’ Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 57: 1. AYYILDIZ, E. (1995) ‘When Battered Woman’s Syndrome Does Not Go Far Enough: Battered Woman as Vigilante’ Journal of Gender and Law 4: 148. BAKER, D. (2007) ‘The Moral Limits of Criminalizing Remote Harms’ New Criminal Law Review 10: 370. © Jonathan Herring, 2016. All rights reserved. Herring: Criminal Law, Text, Cases, and Materials, 8th edition BAKER, D. (2008a) ‘Constitutionalizing the Harm Principle’ Criminal Justice Ethics 27: 3. BAKER, D. (2008b) ‘The Moral Limits of Consent in Criminal Law’ New Criminal Law Review 12: 93. BAKER, D. (2009) ‘Collective Criminalization and the Constitutional Right to Endanger Others’, Criminal Justice Ethics 28: 168. BAKER, D.
Recommended publications
  • Criminal Law Exam Notes
    SUBJECT: CRIMINAL LAW Assault Common Assault • Assault is: • any act committed intentionally or recklessly • that causes another person • to apprehend immediate and unlawful violence → Fagan, Venna • Section 61 → sets out maximum punishment, 2 years imprisonment Actus Reus • Unlawful contact in applying force to another • Note → spitting at and contacting another with spit will constitute assault: Smith; DPP v JWH • The act of creating fear of immediate unlawful contact • Victim must actually be put in fear → Kuhl • The harm threatened must be sufficiently imminent → Zanker v Vartzokas; Knight • Assault can be committed by telephone if sufficiently imminent → Barton v Armstrong; Knight • It is unnecessary that force be accompanied by hostility → Boughey • Mere touching can amount to an assault → Collins v Wilcock • D may be relieved of liability on other grounds, such as: • Lack of mens rea • Implied consent, for example, contact during ordinary social intercourse → Boughey • Use of lawful force, such as self-defence • Victim’s state of mind: • Must actually fear → Kuhl • Must be aware → Pemble (rifle to the back) • Reasonable fear → Barton v Armstrong • Defendant aware of unusual timidity → unreasonableness of fear may not prevent conviction → MacPherson • Imminence: • Fear must be imminent although ‘immediate and continuing‘ can suffice → Zanker v Vartzokas • Threats of future violence not assault → Knight • Examples: • Where D was in another room → Lewis • Where D was on other side of locked door about to force entry → Beech • Where D
    [Show full text]
  • RE-VISITING the FRAUD ACT 2006 – a STEP TOO FAR? Hannah Willcocks
    RE-VISITING THE FRAUD ACT 2006 – A STEP TOO FAR? Hannah Willcocks Brought into force on 15th January 2007,1 the Fraud Act 2006 (‘the Act’) has now been part of the criminal law of England and Wales for over 12 years. Through the introduction of a new general offence of fraud, its aim was to improve the law by making it: a. more comprehensible to juries, especially in serious fraud trials; b. a useful tool in effective prosecutions; c. simpler and therefore fairer; and d. more flexible so able to encompass all forms of fraud 2 and “deal with developing technology”.3 Following the Act’s implementation, it has generally4 been accepted5 that the Act has managed to overcome the vast majority of the difficulties previously encountered with the old offences of deception.6 In 2012, in its Post-Legislative Assessment of the Fraud Act 2006, the Ministry of Justice (‘MoJ’) concluded that the aims and objectives of the 1 The Fraud Act 2006 (Commencement) Order 2006 (SI 2006/3200). 2 Law Commission, Fraud (Law Com No 276, Cm 5560, 2002), para 1.6. 3 Home Office, Fraud Law Reform: Consultation on Proposals for Legislation (2004) p. 5. 4 For a contrary view see Anthony Arlidge QC, Jonathan Fisher QC, Alexander Milne QC and Polly Sprenger, Arlidge and Parry on Fraud (5th edn, Sweet & Maxwell 2016) 44, para 3-005. 5 See e.g. Simester and Sullivan’s Criminal Law, Theory and Doctrine (5th edn, Hart Publishing Ltd 2013) 610; Andrew Ashworth & Jeremy Horder, Principles of Criminal Law (7th edn, Oxford University Press 2013) 405; Carol Withey ‘The Fraud Act 2006 – some early observations and comparisons with the former law’ (2007) 71(3) Journal of Criminal Law, 220 – 237, 228 – 236; Nicholas Yeo, ‘Bull’s-Eye’, 157 NLJ 212 & 418.
    [Show full text]
  • FATE MANAGEMENT: the Real Target of Modern Criminal Law
    FATE MANAGEMENT: The Real Target of Modern Criminal Law W.B. Kennedy Doctor of Juridical Studies 2004 University of Sydney © WB Kennedy, 2004 TABLE OF CONTENTS ABSTRACT vii PREFACE ix The Thesis History x ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS xiii TABLE OF CASES xv TABLE OF LEGISLATION xix New South Wales xix Other Australian jurisdictions xix Overseas municipal statute xx International instruments xx I INTRODUCTION 1 The Issue 1 The Doctrinal Background 4 The Chosen Paradigm 7 The Hypothesis 9 The Argument 13 Why is This Reform Useful? 21 Methodology 21 Structure ............................................................................24 II ANTICIPATORY OFFENCES 27 Introduction 27 Chapter Goal 28 Conspiracy and Complicity 29 Attempt 31 Arguments for a discount ......................................................33 The restitution argument 33 The prevention argument 34 Arguments for no discount .....................................................35 Punishment as retribution 35 Punishment as prevention 35 The objective argument: punish the violation 35 The subjective argument: punish the person 37 The anti-subjective argument 38 The problems created by the objective approach .......................39 The guilt threshold 39 Unlawful killing 40 Involuntary manslaughter 41 The problems with the subjective approach ..............................41 Impossibility 41 Mistake of fact 42 Mistake of law 43 Recklessness 45 Oppression 47 Conclusion 48 FATE MANAGEMENT III STRICT LIABILITY 51 Introduction 51 Chapter Goal 53 Origins 54 The Nature of Strict Liability
    [Show full text]
  • The Human Right of Self-Defense, 22 BYU J
    Brigham Young University Journal of Public Law Volume 22 | Issue 1 Article 3 7-1-2007 The umH an Right of Self-Defense David B. Kopel Paul Gallant Joanne D. Eisen Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.law.byu.edu/jpl Part of the Criminal Law Commons, Human Rights Law Commons, and the Second Amendment Commons Recommended Citation David B. Kopel, Paul Gallant, and Joanne D. Eisen, The Human Right of Self-Defense, 22 BYU J. Pub. L. 43 (2007). Available at: https://digitalcommons.law.byu.edu/jpl/vol22/iss1/3 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by BYU Law Digital Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Brigham Young University Journal of Public Law by an authorized editor of BYU Law Digital Commons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. The Human Right of Self-Defense David B. Kopel,1 Paul Gallant2 & Joanne D. Eisen3 I. INTRODUCTION “Any law, international or municipal, which prohibits recourse to force, is necessarily limited by the right of self-defense.”4 Is there a human right to defend oneself against a violent attacker? Is there an individual right to arms under international law? Conversely, are governments guilty of human rights violations if they do not enact strict gun control laws? The United Nations and some non-governmental organizations have declared that there is no human right to self-defense or to the possession of defensive arms.5 The UN and allied NGOs further declare that 1. Research Director, Independence Institute, Golden, Colorado; Associate Policy Analyst, Cato Institute, Washington, D.C., http://www.davekopel.org.
    [Show full text]
  • Principles of Criminal Liability
    Criminal Law G153 PPRINCIPLES OF CCRIMINAL LLIABILITY 22:: Mens Rea By the end of this unit, you will be able to: Explain what is meant by the term ‘mens rea’ and illustrate your explanation with cases Understand what is meant by the terms: o Direct intent, o Oblique intent, o Specific & basic intent. Explain the current legal test for recklessness, and understand how the test evolved. Explain the scope of the doctrine of transferred malice and how the courts have developed the concept of coincidence. You will also be able to evaluate: The development of the law on oblique intent and the proposals for reforming it. The limitations of the doctrines of coincidence and transferred malice. Homework During this unit, you will be set the following. In completing homework, you will be expected to do your own research and supplement your own notes. This is essential to show understanding. 1. Complete Homework Sheet (2) 2. Complete Case Cards for Actus Reus and Mens Rea. End of Unit Assessment As with AS, you will sit a DRAG test on elements, but this will be done at the end of this unit. You will also complete the following problem question (from Part B of the exam), which we will plan in lesson time, and you will then write up in timed circumstances as your termly assessment. Wayne belongs to a terrorist organisation. He telephones the police to say that he has placed a bomb in a van on Westminster Bridge and confirms that it is timed to explode in fifteen minutes. The police telephone operator mistakenly thinks that Wayne has said 'fifty minutes' and immediately communicates this information to his superior officer.
    [Show full text]
  • Dismantling the Purported Right to Kill in Defence of Property Kenneth Lambeth*
    Dismantling the Purported Right to Kill in Defence of Property Kenneth Lambeth* Two of the most fundamental western legal principles are the right to life and the right to own property. But what happens when life and property collide? Such a possibility exists within the realm of criminal law where a person may arguably be acquitted for killing in defence of property. Unlike life, property has never been a fundamental right,1 but a mere privilege2 based upon the power to exclude others. Killing in defence of property, without something more,3 can therefore never be justified. The right to life is now recognised internationally4 as a fundamental human right, that is, a basic right available to all human beings.5 Property is not, nor has it ever been, such a universal right. The common law has developed “without explicit reference to the primacy of the right to life”.6 However, the sanctity of human life, from which the right to life may be said to flow, predates the common law itself. This article examines two main sources to show that, wherever there is conflict between the right to life and the right to property, the right to life must prevail. The first such source is the historical, legal and social * Final year LLB student, Southern Cross University. A sincere and substantial debt of gratitude is owed to Professor Stanley Yeo for his support, guidance and inspiration. 1 The word ‘fundamental’ is defined in the Macquarie Dictionary to mean ‘essential; primary; original’. A ‘right’ is defined as ‘a just claim or title, whether legal, prescriptive or moral’: Delbridge, A et al (eds), The Macquarie Dictionary (3rd Ed), Macquarie Library, NSW, 1998, pp 859, 1830.
    [Show full text]
  • Criminal Code 2003.Pmd 273 11/27/2004, 12:35 PM 274 No
    273 No. 9 ] Criminal Code [2004. SAINT LUCIA ______ No. 9 of 2004 ARRANGEMENT OF SECTIONS CHAPTER ONE General Provisions PART I PRELIMINARY Section 1. Short title 2. Commencement 3. Application of Code 4. General construction of Code 5. Common law procedure to apply where necessary 6. Interpretation PART II JUSTIFICATIONS AND EXCUSES 7. Claim of right 8. Consent by deceit or duress void 9. Consent void by incapacity 10. Consent by mistake of fact 11. Consent by exercise of undue authority 12. Consent by person in authority not given in good faith 13. Exercise of authority 14. Explanation of authority 15. Invalid consent not prejudicial 16. Extent of justification 17. Consent to fight cannot justify harm 18. Consent to killing unjustifiable 19. Consent to harm or wound 20. Medical or surgical treatment must be proper 21. Medical or surgical or other force to minors or others in custody 22. Use of force, where person unable to consent 23. Revocation annuls consent 24. Ignorance or mistake of fact criminal code 2003.pmd 273 11/27/2004, 12:35 PM 274 No. 9 ] Criminal Code [2004. 25. Ignorance of law no excuse 26. Age of criminal responsibility 27. Presumption of mental disorder 28. Intoxication, when an excuse 29. Aider may justify same force as person aided 30. Arrest with or without process for crime 31. Arrest, etc., other than for indictable offence 32. Bona fide assistant and correctional officer 33. Bona fide execution of defective warrant or process 34. Reasonable use of force in self-defence 35. Defence of property, possession of right 36.
    [Show full text]
  • Albin Eser Grounds for Excluding Criminal Responsibility Article 31
    Sonderdrucke aus der Albert-Ludwigs-Universität Freiburg ALBIN ESER Grounds for excluding criminal responsibility [Article 31 of the Rome Statute] Originalbeitrag erschienen in: Otto Triffterer (Hrsg.): Commentary on the Rome Statute of the International Criminal Court. München [u.a.]: Beck [u.a.], 2008, S. 863-893 ALBIN ESER GROUNDS FOR EXCLUDING CRIMINAL RESPONSIBILITY [Article 31 of the Rome Statute] Reprint from: Otto Triffterer (ed.) Commentary on the Rome Statute of the International Criminal Court - Second Edition - C.H. Beck/Munchen • HartiVolkach • Nomos/Baden-Ba,den 2008 Article 31 Grounds for excluding criminal responsibility 1. In addition to other grounds for exc1udin4 criminal responsibility provided for in this Statute, a person shall not be criminally responsible if, at the time of that person's conduct: (a) The person suffers from a mental disease or defect that destroys that person's capacity to appreciate the unlawfulness or nature of his or her conduct, or capacity to control his or her conduct to conform to the requirements of law; (b) The person is in a state of intoxication that destroys that person's capacity to appreciate the unlawfulness or nature of his or her conduct, or capacity to control his or her conduct to conform to the requirements of law, unless the person has become voluntarily intoxicated under such circumstances that the person knew, or disregarded the risk, that, as a result of the intoxication, he or she was likely to engage in conduct constituting a crime within the jurisdiction of the Court; (c) The person acts reasonably to defend himself or herself or another person or, in the case of war crimes, property which Is essential for the survival of the person or another person or property which is essential for accomplishing a military mission, against an imminent and unlawful use of force in a manner proportionate to the degree of danger to the person or the other person or property protected.
    [Show full text]
  • Banksy at Disneyland: Generic Participation in Culture Jamming Joshua Carlisle Harzman University of the Pacific, [email protected]
    Kaleidoscope: A Graduate Journal of Qualitative Communication Research Volume 14 Article 3 2015 Banksy at Disneyland: Generic Participation in Culture Jamming Joshua Carlisle Harzman University of the Pacific, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: http://opensiuc.lib.siu.edu/kaleidoscope Recommended Citation Harzman, Joshua Carlisle (2015) "Banksy at Disneyland: Generic Participation in Culture Jamming," Kaleidoscope: A Graduate Journal of Qualitative Communication Research: Vol. 14 , Article 3. Available at: http://opensiuc.lib.siu.edu/kaleidoscope/vol14/iss1/3 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by OpenSIUC. It has been accepted for inclusion in Kaleidoscope: A Graduate Journal of Qualitative Communication Research by an authorized administrator of OpenSIUC. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Banksy at Disneyland: Generic Participation in Culture Jamming Cover Page Footnote Many thanks to all of my colleagues and mentors at the University of the Pacific; special thanks to my fiancé Kelly Marie Lootz. This article is available in Kaleidoscope: A Graduate Journal of Qualitative Communication Research: http://opensiuc.lib.siu.edu/ kaleidoscope/vol14/iss1/3 Banksy at Disneyland: Generic Participation in Culture Jamming Joshua Carlisle Harzman Culture jamming is a profound genre of communication and its proliferation demands further academic scholarship. However, there exists a substantial gap in the literature, specifically regarding a framework for determining participation within the genre of culture jamming. This essay seeks to offer such a foundation and subsequently considers participation of an artifact. First, the three elements of culture jamming genre are established and identified: artifact, distortion, and awareness. Second, the street art installment, Banksy at Disneyland, is analyzed for participation within the genre of culture jamming.
    [Show full text]
  • Volume 25, 2016 D Nott-Law Jnl25 Cover Nott-Law Cv 25/07/2016 13:18 Page 2
    d_Nott-law jnl25_cover_Nott-Law_cv 25/07/2016 13:18 Page 1 N O T T I N In this issue: G H A M L Helen O’Nions A EDITORIAL W J O U R N A ARTICLES L How Many Contracts in an Auction Sale? James Brown and Mark Pawlowski NOTTINGHAM LAW JOURNAL The Legal Prospective Force of Constitutional Courts Decisions: Reflections from the Constitutional Jurisprudence of Kosovo and Beyond Visar Morina Journal of Nottingham Law School Don’t Take Away My Break-Away: Balancing Regulatory and Commercial Interests in Sport Simon Boyes The Creative Identity and Intellectual Property Janice Denoncourt THEMATIC ARTICLES: PERSPECTIVES ON THE ISLAMIC FACE VEIL Introduction Tom Lewis Articles S.A.S v France : A Reality Check Eva Brems Human Rights, Identity and the Legal Regulation of Dress Jill Marshall No Face Veils in Court Felicity Gerry QC Face Veils and the Law: A Critical Reflection Samantha Knights The Veiled Lodger – A Reflection on the Status of R v D Jeremy Robson Why the Veil Should be Repudiated* Yasmin Alibhai-Brown 2 0 1 6 *Extract from Refusing the Veil, 2014. Published with kind permission of Biteback V Publishing, London. O L U Continued on inside back cover M E T W E N Nottingham Law School T The Nottingham Trent University Y Burton Street F I V Nottingham E NG1 4BU England £30.00 Volume 25, 2016 d_Nott-law jnl25_cover_Nott-Law_cv 25/07/2016 13:18 Page 2 Continued from outside back cover Book Reviews E Brems (ed.) The Experiences of Face Veil Wearers in Europe and the Law Cambridge University Press, 2014 Amal Ali Jill Marshall Human Rights Law and Personal Identity Routledge, 2014 Tom Lewis CASE NOTES AND COMMENTARY Killing the Parasite in R v Jogee Catarina Sjolin-Knight Disputing the Indisputable: Genocide Denial and Freedom of Expression in Perinçek v Switzerland Luigi Daniele Innocent Dissemination: The Type of Knowledge Concerned in Shen, Solina Holly v SEEC Media Group Limited S.H.
    [Show full text]
  • Dolus Eventualis in South African Criminal Law
    THE INTERPRETATION AND APPLICATION OF DOLUS EVENTUALIS IN SOUTH AFRICAN CRIMINAL LAW by LINUS TAMBU AWA Submitted in accordance with the requirements for the degree of DOCTOR OF LAWS in the subject Criminal and Procedural Law at the UNIVERSITY OF SOUTH AFRICA SUPERVISOR: PROF NINA MOLLEMA NOVEMBER 2019 i Table of Contents Page DECLARATION .......................................................................................................... v ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS .......................................................................................... vi DEDICATION ............................................................................................................ vii SUMMARY ............................................................................................................... viii KEY WORDS ............................................................................................................. ix GLOSSARY OF ACRONYMS AND ABBREVIATIONS ............................................ xi CHAPTER ONE .......................................................................................................... 1 INTRODUCTION ......................................................................................................... 1 1.1 Background information ................................................................................. 1 1.2 Research problem .......................................................................................... 3 1.3 Research questions and hypotheses of study ...............................................
    [Show full text]
  • Banksy Was Here: State Strategy Versus Individual Tactics in the Form of Urban Art Author: Meghan Hughes Source: Prandium - the Journal of Historical Studies, Vol
    Title: Banksy Was Here: State Strategy Versus Individual Tactics in the Form of Urban Art Author: Meghan Hughes Source: Prandium - The Journal of Historical Studies, Vol. 1, No. 1 (Spring, 2017). Published by: The Department of Historical Studies, University of Toronto Mississauga Stable URL: http://jps.library.utoronto.ca/index.php/prandium/article/view/28581 Urban art, according to Lu Pan entails a sense of “illicitness that may either pass by unnoticed or disturb the predominant order.”1 In creating this art, the ‘writers’ as they call themselves, seek to subvert the perceived framework of power represented by the city, and create alternate spaces to contest these structures outside the state-sponsored scope. Urban art seeks to subvert and disrupt normative relations between producers and consumers, by creating a space of free exchange. Through this changing and re-appropriating of space, the graffitist challenges the “illusion of ownership” and draws attention to the unseen struggle between the individual and the institutions of the metropolis.2 Using the theories of Michel de Certeau and Georg Simmel to frame my analysis, I will examine the ways in which the works of London-based urban artist Banksy engage in this practice. In exploring the ‘alternate’ spaces that Banksy creates, I seek to demonstrate how his anti-consumer, anti-political works function as avenues to negotiate and re- conceptualize relations between the individual and the structures of power represented by the city. Michel de Certeau’s work, The Practice of Everyday Life is an exploration of the daily practices, or ‘tactics’ of individuals that utilize urban space in a unique or unconventional way.
    [Show full text]