Homotopical Approach to Quantum Contextuality

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Homotopical Approach to Quantum Contextuality Homotopical approach to quantum contextuality Cihan Okay1,2 and Robert Raussendorf1,2 1Department of Physics and Astronomy, University of British Columbia, Vancouver, BC, Canada 2Stewart Blusson Quantum Matter Institute, University of British Columbia, Vancouver, BC, Canada We consider the phenomenon of quan- on Čech cohomology by Abramsky and cowork- tum mechanical contextuality, and specif- ers [16], the geometric approach by Arkhipov [17], ically parity-based proofs thereof. Mer- and the approach based on cohomology of chain min’s square and star are representative complexes [18]. For other approaches to contex- examples. Part of the information invoked tuality see [19–23] and for refinements of the Čech in such contextuality proofs is the com- cohomology approach see [24–27]. mutativity structure among the pertain- In this paper we unify the approach of ing observables. We investigate to which Arkhipov and the approach based on chain com- extent this commutativity structure alone plexes, thereby generalizing one of Arkhipov’s determines the viability of a parity-based results [17]. Both [17] and [18] are concerned contextuality proof. We establish a topo- with so-called parity-based contextuality proofs, logical criterion for this, generalizing an of which Mermin’s square and star are represen- earlier result by Arkhipov. tative examples [28]. Generally, a parity-based contextuality proof is a set of linear constraints on hypothetical value assignments that has no so- 1 Introduction lution. Although concerned with the same type of contextuality proof, [17] and [18] use different Contextuality is a characteristic feature of quan- abstractions and address slightly different ques- tum mechanics [1,2] that distinguishes quantum tions. from classical physics. It rules out the descrip- Ref. [18] asks: Does a given set O of observ- tion of quantum phenomena by so-called non- ables produce a parity-based contextuality proof? contextual hidden variable models, in which each The first step in answering this question is in ex- observable has a pre-determined value which is tracting the essential information of the set O of merely revealed by the act of measurement. Such observables, in terms of a chain complex C that models are either internally inconsistent, or fail to captures the commutativity structure within O, reproduce the predictions of quantum mechanics. and a cocycle β that captures the phase infor- What leads to paradoxes under too strin- mation of product relations among commuting gent assumptions about physical reality be- elements in O. Then, a parity-based contextu- comes a commodity if these assumptions are not ality proof arises in the setting specified by O if made: contextuality is also a resource in quan- and only if the cocycle β is cohomologically non- tum computation. For two models of quantum trivial, [β] 6= 0. computation—quantum computation with magic Arkhipov [17] invokes a different abstraction arXiv:1905.03822v2 [quant-ph] 18 Dec 2019 states [3] and measurement-based quantum com- and addresses a different question. Rather than a putation [4]—it has been shown that a quantum chain complex, [17] defines an intersection graph speedup can occur only if contextuality is present G, with the edges labeling observables and the [5–12]. vertices labeling contexts. Again, G captures the At its core, contextuality is about the interplay commutativity structure among the observables between local consistency and global inconsis- involved. The counterpart to the cocycle β of tency [13]; and therefore topological methods are [18] is a sign function defined on the vertices of particularly suited to discuss it. Presently four G. Arkhipov’s question is, in a sense, the re- approaches to contextuality have been described verse of the above; namely: Given the intersec- that employ topology: the topos approach by tion graph G, does there exist a corresponding Döring and Isham [14, 15], the approach based set O of observables that produces a parity-based Accepted in Quantum 2019-12-09, click title to verify. Published under CC-BY 4.0. 1 contextuality proof? This question has a surpris- [17] all observables are constrained to have eigen- ingly simple—and topological—answer. Namely, values ±1, whereas the present treatment permits the intersection graph G can give rise to a parity- operators with eigenvalues e2πi/d, for any d ≥ 2. based contextuality proof if and only if G is non- The remainder of this paper is organized as fol- planar. lows. In Section2 we introduce magic arrange- In [17], rather than a set O of observables, the ments and explain the connection to the notion intersection graph G is the primary object. The of contextuality. Section3 we introduce the ba- broader significance of this is that a geometrical sic tools: topological realizations and path opera- object encoding commutativity relations among tors. Section4 contains our main result (Theorem observables emerges at the base of quantum me- 4.6). In Section4 we study topological realiza- chanical contextuality. In this paper, we seek gen- tions via the fundamental sequence of homotopy eralizations of Arkhipov’s results to a greater va- groups. Then in Section5 we move on to define riety of physical settings and to understand the a representation of the fundamental group of a structure of the emerging geometric objects. topological realization and use this to refine our main result (Corollary 5.6). Section6 is on the We now summarize how the two above- algorithmic approach [29, 30] to parity-based con- described approaches [17] and [18] are unified, textuality proofs and how it relates to the topo- how one of Arkhipov’s results is thereby general- logical approach presented in this paper. ized, and why such a generalization is desirable. First, we observe that the intersection graph G employed in [17] is defined only for settings in 2 Magic arrangements which each observable in O is part of no more than two contexts. This is a consequence of the Many proofs of contextuality of quantum me- simple fact that an edge in a graph has no more chanics employ fixed sets of observables to find than two end points. obstructions to the existence of non-contextual The extension of Arkhipov’s results to settings value assignments. Two key examples are Mer- with observables contributing to more than two min’s square and star [28]. However, the ex- contexts is, for example, relevant for the dis- istence of the obstruction does not depend on cussion of contextuality in measurement-based the precise choice of the observables; for exam- quantum computation (MBQC). In the stan- ple, conjugating each observable in the set by dard MBQC setting [4], applied to evaluation of the same unitary produces an equivalent proof. Boolean functions on m input bits [10], there are Rather, it depends only on which subsets of 2m measurement contexts overall. Each local ob- observables commute, and how commuting ob- servable measurable in the process, chosen from servables multiply. In Arkhipov’s formulation, a set of 2, appears in one half of these contexts. this information makes up the so-called “arrange- Therefore, each such observable appears in more ment", and the commutativity part of it the so- than two measurement contexts whenever m > 2. called “intersection graph" of the arrangement. Our main result is that one direction of The definition of the intersection graph is as Arkhipov’s result can be generalized in the for- follows. Given a fixed set of observables for a malism of [18] based on a chain complex C, with contextuality proof, such as Mermin’s square or no bounds on the number of contexts that any star, these observables become the edges of the given observable can appear in. Specifically, a intersection graph, and the sets of commuting complex C can yield a parity-based contextual- observables, i.e., the contexts, become the ver- ity proof only if the topological space XC corre- tices of the intersection graph. Thus, two edges sponding to C is not simply connected, i.e., only if have the same vertex as end point if and only if π1(XC) 6= 1. For example, in the case of Arkhipov the corresponding observables commute. To stick the complex C can be described by a closed sur- with the above examples, the intersection graphs face Σg of some genus g together with a cell struc- of Mermin’s square and star (see Fig. (2)) are the ture on it. The intersection graph G corresponds bipartite complete graph K3,3 and the complete to the dual cell structure of Σg. Vanishing of the graph K5, respectively. fundamental group coincides with the planarity Central in [17] is the notion of “magic" arrange- of the intersection graph in this case. Also, in ments. They appear in the context of nonlocal Accepted in Quantum 2019-12-09, click title to verify. Published under CC-BY 4.0. 2 games [31], cooperative strategies that demon- magic if it is quantum realizable but not classi- strate contextuality as a resource for winning cally realizable. with high probability. An arrangement is magic When the arrangement satisfies the property if the edges of its intersection graph can be popu- that each observable is contained in exacly two lated with Hermitian operators with eigenvalues contexts one can define the intersection graph. ±1, but not with numbers ±1. The significance Can it be judged from the intersection graph of of this notion is that every magic arrangement an arrangement alone whether the arrangement gives rise to a proof of contextuality. Formally, is magic? Arkipov answers this question in an a set of contraints among quantum observables is affirmative way, and provides the following char- specified, and a contextuality proof would be a acterization. demonstration of the failure to satisfy these con- Theorem A.
Recommended publications
  • Memory Cost of Quantum Contextuality
    Master of Science Thesis in Physics Department of Electrical Engineering, Linköping University, 2016 Memory Cost of Quantum Contextuality Patrik Harrysson Master of Science Thesis in Physics Memory Cost of Quantum Contextuality Patrik Harrysson LiTH-ISY-EX--16/4967--SE Supervisor: Jan-Åke Larsson isy, Linköpings universitet Examiner: Jan-Åke Larsson isy, Linköpings universitet Division of Information Coding Department of Electrical Engineering Linköping University SE-581 83 Linköping, Sweden Copyright © 2016 Patrik Harrysson Abstract This is a study taking an information theoretic approach toward quantum contex- tuality. The approach is that of using the memory complexity of finite-state ma- chines to quantify quantum contextuality. These machines simulate the outcome behaviour of sequential measurements on systems of quantum bits as predicted by quantum mechanics. Of interest is the question of whether or not classical representations by finite-state machines are able to effectively represent the state- independent contextual outcome behaviour. Here we consider spatial efficiency, rather than temporal efficiency as considered by D. Gottesmana, for the partic- ular measurement dynamics in systems of quantum bits. Extensions of cases found in the adjacent study of Kleinmann et al.b are established by which upper bounds on memory complexity for particular scenarios are found. Furthermore, an optimal machine structure for simulating any n-partite system of quantum bits is found, by which a lower bound for the memory complexity is found for each n N. Within this finite-state machine approach questions of foundational concerns2 on quantum mechanics were sought to be addressed. Alas, nothing of novel thought on such concerns is here reported on.
    [Show full text]
  • Lecture 8 Measurement-Based Quantum Computing
    Introduction to quantum computation and simulability Ernesto F. Galvão Instituto de Física, Universidade Federal Fluminense (Niterói, Brazil) 1−ε 0 + ε 1 q = ε p 0 p 0 U ! 0 ICTP-SAIFR – IFT/UNESP , October 15th-19th, 2018 Introduction to quantum computation and simulability Lecture 8 : Measurement-based QC (MBQC) II Outline: • Applications of MBQC: • models for quantum spacetime • blind quantum computation • Time-ordering in MBQC • MBQC without adaptativity: • Clifford circuits • IQP circuits • Introduction to quantum contextuality • Contextuality as a computational resource • in magic state distillation • in MBQC • For slides and links to related material, see Application: blind quantum computation • Classical/quantum separation in MBQC allow for implementation of novel protocols – such as blind quantum computation • Here, client has limited quantum capabilities, and uses a server to do computation for her. • Blind = server doesn’t know what’s being computed. Broadbent, Fitzsimons, Kashefi, axiv:0807.4154 [quant-ph] Application: model for quantum spacetime • MBQC can serve as a discrete toy model for quantum spacetime: quantum space-time MBQC quantum substrate graph states events measurements principle establishing global determinism requirement space-time structure for computations [Raussendorf et al., arxiv:1108.5774] • Even closed timelike curves (= time travel) have analogues in MBQC! [Dias da Silva, Kashefi, Galvão PRA 83, 012316 (2011)] Time-ordering in MBQC from: Proc. Int. School of Physics "Enrico Fermi" on "Quantum Computers,
    [Show full text]
  • On Graph Approaches to Contextuality and Their Role in Quantum Theory
    SPRINGER BRIEFS IN MATHEMATICS Barbara Amaral · Marcelo Terra Cunha On Graph Approaches to Contextuality and their Role in Quantum Theory 123 SpringerBriefs in Mathematics Series editors Nicola Bellomo Michele Benzi Palle Jorgensen Tatsien Li Roderick Melnik Otmar Scherzer Benjamin Steinberg Lothar Reichel Yuri Tschinkel George Yin Ping Zhang SpringerBriefs in Mathematics showcases expositions in all areas of mathematics and applied mathematics. Manuscripts presenting new results or a single new result in a classical field, new field, or an emerging topic, applications, or bridges between new results and already published works, are encouraged. The series is intended for mathematicians and applied mathematicians. More information about this series at http://www.springer.com/series/10030 SBMAC SpringerBriefs Editorial Board Carlile Lavor University of Campinas (UNICAMP) Institute of Mathematics, Statistics and Scientific Computing Department of Applied Mathematics Campinas, Brazil Luiz Mariano Carvalho Rio de Janeiro State University (UERJ) Department of Applied Mathematics Graduate Program in Mechanical Engineering Rio de Janeiro, Brazil The SBMAC SpringerBriefs series publishes relevant contributions in the fields of applied and computational mathematics, mathematics, scientific computing, and related areas. Featuring compact volumes of 50 to 125 pages, the series covers a range of content from professional to academic. The Sociedade Brasileira de Matemática Aplicada e Computacional (Brazilian Society of Computational and Applied Mathematics,
    [Show full text]
  • Non-Deterministic Semantics for Quantum States
    entropy Article Non-Deterministic Semantics for Quantum States Juan Pablo Jorge 1 and Federico Holik 2,* 1 Physics Department, University of Buenos Aires, Buenos Aires 1428, Argentina; [email protected] 2 Instituto de Física La Plata, UNLP, CONICET, Facultad de Ciencias Exactas, 1900 La Plata, Argentina * Correspondence: [email protected] Received: 16 October 2019; Accepted: 27 January 2020; Published: 28 January 2020 Abstract: In this work, we discuss the failure of the principle of truth functionality in the quantum formalism. By exploiting this failure, we import the formalism of N-matrix theory and non-deterministic semantics to the foundations of quantum mechanics. This is done by describing quantum states as particular valuations associated with infinite non-deterministic truth tables. This allows us to introduce a natural interpretation of quantum states in terms of a non-deterministic semantics. We also provide a similar construction for arbitrary probabilistic theories based in orthomodular lattices, allowing to study post-quantum models using logical techniques. Keywords: quantum states; non-deterministic semantics; truth functionality 1. Introduction According to the principle of truth-functionality or composability (TFP), the truth-value of a complex formula is uniquely determined by the truth-values of its subformulas. It is a basic principle of logic. However, as explained in [1], many real-world situations involve dealing with information that is incomplete, vague or uncertain. This is especially true for quantum phenomena, where only probabilistic assertions about possible events can be tested in the lab. These situations pose a threat to the application of logical systems obeying the principle of truth-functionality in those problems.
    [Show full text]
  • Continuous Variable Nonloclality and Contextuality
    Continuous-variable nonlocality and contextuality Rui Soares Barbosa Tom Douce Department of Computer Science Laboratoire d’Informatique de Paris 6 University of Oxford CNRS and Sorbonne Universite´ [email protected] School of Informatics University of Edinburgh [email protected] Pierre-Emmanuel Emeriau Elham Kashefi Shane Mansfield Laboratoire d’Informatique de Paris 6 Laboratoire d’Informatique de Paris 6 Laboratoire d’Informatique de Paris 6 CNRS and Sorbonne Universite´ CNRS and Sorbonne Universite´ CNRS and Sorbonne Universite´ [email protected] School of Informatics [email protected] University of Edinburgh [email protected] Contextuality is a non-classical behaviour that can be exhibited by quantum systems. It is increas- ingly studied for its relationship to quantum-over-classical advantages in informatic tasks. To date, it has largely been studied in discrete variable scenarios, where observables take values in discrete and usually finite sets. Practically, on the other hand, continuous-variable scenarios offer some of the most promising candidates for implementing quantum computations and informatic protocols. Here we set out a framework for treating contextuality in continuous-variable scenarios. It is shown that the Fine–Abramsky–Brandenburger theorem extends to this setting, an important consequence of which is that nonlocality can be viewed as a special case of contextuality, as in the discrete case. The contextual fraction, a quantifiable measure of contextuality that bears a precise relationship to Bell inequality violations and quantum advantages, can also be defined in this setting. It is shown to be a non-increasing monotone with respect to classical operations that include binning to discretise data.
    [Show full text]
  • Arxiv:1904.05306V3 [Quant-Ph] 30 May 2021 Fax: +34-954-556672 E-Mail: [email protected] 2 Ad´Ancabello
    Noname manuscript No. (will be inserted by the editor) Bell non-locality and Kochen-Specker contextuality: How are they connected? Ad´anCabello Received: July 4, 2020/ Accepted: July 3, 2020 Abstract Bell non-locality and Kochen-Specker (KS) contextuality are logi- cally independent concepts, fuel different protocols with quantum vs classical advantage, and have distinct classical simulation costs. A natural question is what are the relations between these concepts, advantages, and costs. To ad- dress this question, it is useful to have a map that captures all the connections between Bell non-locality and KS contextuality in quantum theory. The aim of this work is to introduce such a map. After defining the theory-independent notions of Bell non-locality and KS contextuality for ideal measurements, we show that, in quantum theory, due to Neumark's dilation theorem, every quan- tum Bell non-local behavior can be mapped to a formally identical KS contex- tual behavior produced in a scenario with identical relations of compatibility but where measurements are ideal and no space-like separation is required. A more difficult problem is identifying connections in the opposite direction. We show that there are \one-to-one" and partial connections between KS contex- tual behaviors and Bell non-local behaviors for some KS scenarios, but not for all of them. However, there is also a method that transforms any KS contextual behavior for quantum systems of dimension d into a Bell non-local behavior between two quantum subsystems each of them of dimension d. We collect all these connections in map and list some problems which can benefit from this map.
    [Show full text]
  • Arxiv:2102.13036V2 [Quant-Ph] 12 Mar 2021 2
    Quantum Contextuality Costantino Budroni,1, 2 Ad´anCabello,3, 4 Otfried G¨uhne,5 Matthias Kleinmann,5 and Jan-Ake˚ Larsson6 1Faculty of Physics, University of Vienna, Boltzmanngasse 5, 1090 Vienna, Austria 2Institute for Quantum Optics and Quantum Information (IQOQI), Austrian Academy of Sciences, Boltzmanngasse 3, 1090 Vienna, Austria 3 Departamento de F´ısicaAplicada II, Universidad de Sevilla, 41012 Sevilla, Spain 4 Instituto Carlos I de F´ısicaTe´oricay Computacional, Universidad de Sevilla, 41012 Sevilla, Spain 5 Naturwissenschaftlich-Technische Fakult¨at,Universit¨at Siegen, Walter-Flex-Straße 3, 57068 Siegen, Germany 6 Institutionen f¨orSystemteknik och Matematiska Institutionen, Link¨opingsUniversitet, 58183 Link¨oping, Sweden (Dated: March 15, 2021) A central result in the foundations of quantum mechanics is the Kochen-Specker theorem. In short, it states that quantum mechanics is in conflict with classical models in which the result of a measurement does not depend on which other compatible measurements are jointly performed. Here, compatible measurements are those that can be performed simultaneously or in any order without disturbance. This conflict is generically called quantum contextuality. In this article, we present an introduction to this subject and its current status. We review several proofs of the Kochen-Specker theorem and different notions of contextuality. We explain how to experimentally test some of these notions and discuss connections between contextuality and nonlocality or graph theory. Finally, we review some applications of contextuality in quantum information processing. Contents 5. Final considerations on KS contextuality experiments 25 I. Introduction 2 E. A different notion of contextuality: Spekkens' approach 26 II. Quantum contextuality in a nutshell 2 1.
    [Show full text]
  • Violation of the Bell's Type Inequalities As a Local Expression Of
    Violation of the Bell’s type inequalities as a local expression of incompatibility Andrei Khrennikov Linnaeus University, International Center for Mathematical Modeling in Physics and Cognitive Sciences V¨axj¨o, SE-351 95, Sweden February 20, 2019 Abstract By filtering out the philosophic component we can be said that the EPR-paper was directed against the straightforward interpreta- tion of the Heisenberg’s uncertainty principle or more generally the Bohr’s complementarity principle. The latter expresses contextuality of quantum measurements: dependence of measurement’s output on the complete experimental arrangement. However, Bell restructured the EPR-argument against complementarity to justify nonlocal theo- ries with hidden variables of the Bohmian mechanics’ type. Then this Bell’s kind of nonlocality - subquantum nonlocality - was lifted to the level of quantum theory - up to the terminology “quantum nonlocal- ity”. The aim of this short note is to explain that Bell’s test is simply a special test of local incompatibility of quantum observables, similar to interference experiments, e.g., the two-slit experiment. 1 Introduction In this note I repeat the message presented in papers [1]-[3]. This arXiv:1902.07070v1 [quant-ph] 19 Feb 2019 note was motivated by the recent INTERNET discussion on the Bell inequality. This discussion involved both sides: those who support the conventional interpretation of a violation of the Bell type inequalities and those who present a variety of non-conventional positions. As always happens in such discussions on the Bell inequality, the diversity of for and against arguments was really amazing, chaotic, and mainly misleading.1 My attempt to clarify the situation by replying R.
    [Show full text]
  • Classical and Quantum Memory in Contextuality Scenarios
    Universidade Federal de Minas Gerais Departamento de F´ısica Instituto de Ci^enciasExatas | ICEx Classical and Quantum Memory in Contextuality Scenarios Gabriel Fagundes PhD Thesis Presented to the Graduate Program in Physics of Federal University of Minas Gerais, as a partial requirement to obtain the title of Doctor in Physics. Abstract Quantum theory can be described as a framework for calculating probabilities of mea- surement outcomes. A great part of its deep foundational questions comes from the fact that these probabilities may disagree with classical calculations, under reasonable premises. The classical notion in which the observables are frequently assumed as predefined before their measurement motivates the assumption of noncontextuality, i.e. that all the observables have preassigned values before the interaction with the experimental apparatus, independently on which other observables are jointly measured with it. It is known that this classical view is inconsistent with quantum predictions. The main question of this thesis can be phrased as: can we use memory to classically obtain results in agreement with quantum theory applied to se- quential measurements? If so, how to quantify the amount of memory needed? These questions are addressed in a specific contextuality scenario: the Peres-Mermin square. Previous results are extended by using a comprehensive scheme, which shows that the same bound of a three- internal-state automaton is sufficient, even when all probabilistic predictions are considered. Trying to use a lower dimensional quantum resource, i.e. the qubit, to reduce the memory cost in this scenario led us to another question of whether or not there is contextuality for this type of system.
    [Show full text]
  • Hypergraph Contextuality
    entropy Article Hypergraph Contextuality Mladen Paviˇci´c Center of Excellence for Advanced Materials and Sensors, Research Unit Photonics and Quantum Optics, Institute Ruder Boškovi´c,Zagreb 10000, Croatia; [email protected] Received: 14 October 2019 ; Accepted: 10 November 2019; Published: 12 November 2019 Abstract: Quantum contextuality is a source of quantum computational power and a theoretical delimiter between classical and quantum structures. It has been substantiated by numerous experiments and prompted generation of state independent contextual sets, that is, sets of quantum observables capable of revealing quantum contextuality for any quantum state of a given dimension. There are two major classes of state-independent contextual sets—the Kochen-Specker ones and the operator-based ones. In this paper, we present a third, hypergraph-based class of contextual sets. Hypergraph inequalities serve as a measure of contextuality. We limit ourselves to qutrits and obtain thousands of 3-dim contextual sets. The simplest of them involves only 5 quantum observables, thus enabling a straightforward implementation. They also enable establishing new entropic contextualities. Keywords: quantum contextuality; hypergraph contextuality; MMP hypergraphs; operator contextuality; qutrits; Yu-Oh contextuality; Bengtsson-Blanchfield-Cabello contextuality; Xu-Chen-Su contextuality; entropic contextuality 1. Introduction Recently, quantum contextuality found applications in quantum communication [1,2], quantum computation [3,4], quantum nonlocality [5] and lattice theory [6,7]. This has prompted experimental implementation with photons [8–19], classical light [20–23], neutrons [24–26], trapped ions [27], solid state molecular nuclear spins [28] and superconducting quantum systems [29]. Quantum contextuality, which the aforementioned citations refer to, precludes assignments of predetermined values to dense sets of projection operators, and in our approach we shall keep to this feature of the considered contextual sets.
    [Show full text]
  • Experimentally Testable Noncontextuality Inequalities Via Fourier-Motzkin Elimination
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by University of Waterloo's Institutional Repository Experimentally Testable Noncontextuality Inequalities Via Fourier-Motzkin Elimination by Anirudh Krishna A thesis presented to the University of Waterloo in fulfillment of the thesis requirement for the degree of Master of Science in Physics - Quantum Information Waterloo, Ontario, Canada, 2015 ©Anirudh Krishna 2015 Declaration I hereby declare that I am the sole author of this thesis. This is a true copy of the thesis, including any required final revisions, as accepted by my examiners. I understand that my thesis may be made electronically available to the public. ii Abstract Generalized noncontextuality as defined by Spekkens is an attempt to make precise the distinction between classical and quantum theories. It is a restriction on models used to reproduce the predictions of quantum mechanics. There has been considerable progress recently in deriving experimentally robust noncontextuality inequalities. The violation of these inequalities is a sufficient condition for an experiment to not admit a generalized noncontextual model. In this thesis, we present an algorithm to automate the derivation of noncontextuality inequalities. At the heart of this algorithm is a technique called Fourier Motzkin elimination (abbrev. FM elimination). After a brief overview of the generalized notion of contextuality and FM elimination, we proceed to demon- strate how this algorithm works by using it to derive noncontextuality inequalities for a number of examples. Belinfante’s construction, presented first for the sake of pedagogy, is based on a simple proof by Belinfante to demonstrate the invalidity of von Neumann’s notion of noncontextuality.
    [Show full text]
  • Contextuality and the Kochen-Specker Theorem
    Grundlagen der modernen Quantenphysik – Seminar WS 2007/08 Contextuality and the Kochen-Specker Theorem (Interpretations of Quantum Mechanics) by Christoph Saulder (0400944) 19. 12. 2007 Contextuality and the Kochen-Specker Theorem ABSTRACT Since local hidden variables are forbidden by Bell’s theorem, the Kochen-Specker theorem forces a theory for quantum mechanics based on hidden variables to be contextual. Several experiments have been performed to proof this powerful theorem. I will review the consequences of the Kochen-Specker theorem and contextuality on the interpretation of quantum mechanics. TABEL OF CONTENTS ABSTRACT............................................................................................................................... 1 TABEL OF CONTENTS........................................................................................................... 1 INTRODUCTION...................................................................................................................... 2 INTERPRETATIONS OF QUANTUM MECHANICS............................................................ 2 Copenhagen Interpretation ..................................................................................................... 2 Hidden-Variable Theories...................................................................................................... 2 Other Interpretations .............................................................................................................. 3 Comparison ...........................................................................................................................
    [Show full text]