The Importance of Being Understood: Folk Psychology As Ethics

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

The Importance of Being Understood: Folk Psychology As Ethics The Importance of Being Understood ‘A very enjoyable and provocative book on an important topic, in Morton’s inimitable style.’ Peter Goldie, King’s College London ‘A very valuable addition to the literature. Morton brings together material from game theory, philosophy and psychology in genuinely new and illumi- nating ways.’ Gregory Currie, University of Nottingham The Importance of Being Understood is an innovative and thought-provoking exploration of the links between the way we think about each other’s mental states and the fundamentally cooperative nature of everyday life. Adam Morton begins with a consideration of ‘folk psychology’, the ten- dency to attribute emotions, desires, beliefs and thoughts to human minds. He takes the view that it is precisely this tendency that enables us to understand, predict and explain the actions of others, which in turn helps us to decide on our own course of action. This reflection suggests, claims Morton, that certain types of cooperative activity are dependent on everyday psychological under- standing and, conversely, that we act in such a way as to make our actions easily intelligible to others so that we can benefit from being understood. Using examples of cooperative activities such as car driving and playing tennis, Adam Morton analyses the concepts of belief and simulation, the idea of explanation by motive and the causal force of psychological explanation. In addition to argument and analysis, Morton also includes more speculative explorations of topics such as moral progress, and presents a new point of view on how and why cultures differ. The Importance of Being Understood forges new links between ethics and the philosophy of mind, and will be of interest to anyone in either field, as well as to developmental psychologists. Adam Morton is Professor of Philosophy at the University of Oklahoma. He is author of Frames of Mind (1980), Disasters and Dilemmas (1990), Philoso- phy in Practice (1996) and A Guide Through the Theory of Knowledge (1997). International Library of Philosophy Edited by José Luis Bermúdez,Tim Crane and Peter Sullivan Advisory Board: Jonathan Barnes, Fred Dretske, Frances Kamm, Brian Leiter, Huw Price and Sydney Shoemaker Recent titles in the ILP: The Facts of Causation D. H. Mellor The Conceptual Roots of Mathematics J. R. Lucas Stream of Consciousness Barry Dainton Knowledge and Reference in Empirical Science Jody Azzouni Reason Without Freedom David Owens The Price of Doubt N. M. L. Nathan Matters of Mind Scott Sturgeon Logic, Form and Grammar Peter Long The Metaphysicians of Meaning Gideon Makin Logical Investigations,Vols I & II Edmund Husserl Truth Without Objectivity Max Kölbel Departing from Frege Mark Sainsbury The Importance of Being Understood Adam Morton The Importance of Being Understood Folk psychology as ethics Adam Morton First published 2003 by Routledge 11 New Fetter Lane, London EC4P 4EE Simultaneously published in the USA and Canada by Routledge 29 West 35th Street, New York,NY 10001 Routledge is an imprint of the Taylor & Francis Group This edition published in the Taylor & Francis e-Library, 2005. “To purchase your own copy of this or any of Taylor & Francis or Routledge’s collection of thousands of eBooks please go to www.eBookstore.tandf.co.uk.” © 2003 Adam Morton All rights reserved.No part of this book may be reprinted or reproduced or utilized in any form or by any electronic, mechanical, or other means, now known or hereafter invented, including photocopying and recording, or in any information storage or retrieval system, without permission in writing from the publishers. British Library Cataloguing in Publication Data A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library Library of Congress Cataloging in Publication Data A catalog record for this book has been requested ISBN 0-203-99493-0 Master e-book ISBN ISBN 0–415–27242–4 (hbk) ISBN 0–415–27243–2 (pbk) Contents Foreword: where we’re going vii 1 Microethics 1 Appendix: preferences from choices 28 2 Motives and virtues 34 3 Belief and coordination 55 4 Explanatory contrast and causal depth 81 Appendix: attractors and contrasts 107 5 Learning to simulate 116 Appendix: maximization and complexity 141 Summary: where we’ve got to 148 Exploration I Attribution biases and the statistics of cooperation 151 Exploration II Interspection and expression 161 Exploration III Ethos 175 Exploration IV Moral progress 187 Notes 206 Bibliography 211 Index 222 Foreword Where we’re going The central idea of this book should be intuitively to attract anyone who has driven in Rome, Paris, or Manhattan. You can rarely predict what any other driver is going to do. To that extent all folk psychology and all social con- tracts are useless. What you can do is notice what outcomes everyone would rather avoid, and then cautiously and very visibly to act in a way that makes those outcomes less likely. When you do, then often enough you create a situ- ation in which the other drivers are constrained by their own interest (in not having their clean cars dented or bloodstained) to go along with that course of action. When you make yourself intelligible you gain a predictive hold over the behavior of others. We are a mind-attributing species. We very readily think of one another in terms of emotions, desires, beliefs, thinking. We are also a cooperative species. Human life has always required that we share projects and work together, doing our best to avoid the possibilities for exploitation that this presents. This is the not inherently very promising niche that humans have chosen and flourished in, that of social animals whose sociality is flexible because of its relative poverty of innate social routines. It is a not very daring suggestion that these two characteristics are linked. One important reason for attributing states of mind is to generate the expec- tations that make cooperation possible and allow us to anticipate and forestall exploitation, fake cooperation or cheating. We do not usually explain one another’s actions out of pure scientific curiosity: there are reasons why we want to know why people act as they do, and these are generally practical social reasons. In this way folk psychology, the body of knowledge, opinions and routines that we use in conceptualizing and anticipating one another’s actions, functions as a background to cooperative activity. Indeed one might take it as a background to ethics, taken very broadly as the enterprise of helping one another to the best lives. (Whether or not rights, duties and obli- gations are actors in this particular story.) The aim of this book is to explore one family of connections between mind-ascription and cooperative activity. I explore a variety of ways in which the everyday explanation or prediction of actions is aided by the fact that the viii Foreword person whose actions are explained shares the routines of explanation or pre- diction in question. When this is the case then the presence of the routine is one of the reasons for the behavior that it explains, and this will rarely occur unless the behavior is shaped in a direction that tends towards mutually prof- itable interaction. Or, more generally, the presence in a culture of ways of understanding action can create a situation in which patterns of shared action are encouraged, which themselves help make the understanding appropriate. Beneficial circularities. And in the course of looking for exam- ples of these phenomena I investigate more general interdependencies of modes of everyday psychological understanding and types of cooperative activity. There is a big central idea here. We make ourselves intelligible, in order to have the benefits of being understood. It should not be exaggerated, though. I am not claiming that the function of facilitating cooperative activity by itself creates or determines any easily-named aspect of folk psychology. The thread that I am following runs through much of the fabric of everyday understanding, but it may not bear the full weight at any point. As a result, my exposition consists of analyses of a number of topics – explanation by motive, the concept of belief, the causal force of psychological explanation, simulation – in which I argue for claims from which conclusions relevant to my themes follow. I am sure that the thread extends further than I have traced it. And I can give reasons for suspecting or conjecturing that it is found in several places where I do not have definite arguments for its presence. I don’t think that phi- losophy should consist only of definite arguments for clear conclusions, though. We also need suggestive considerations that let us see possibilities that we can then slowly try to deal with. Every philosopher strikes the balance between ‘clearly true but possibly boring’ and ‘clearly interesting but possibly false’ in a different way. My strategy is to include both, but to label them as such. So the form of this book is that after five chapters in which argument and analysis are taken as far as I can take them, there is a conclusion. And then there are four shorter items, which I do not call chapters but explo- rations, which make suggestions about how the points I have made could be pushed rather further. They are speculative, and they help themselves to premises where they need to. Some readers may find some of them more inter- esting than the more careful chapters that precede them. But others may prefer to ignore them. You can decide which type of reader you are. Writing this book has had an effect on my attitude to other people. When I began it I thought of people primarily as bearers of individual beliefs and desires, who have to negotiate their way around one another to get what they want.
Recommended publications
  • The Folk Psychology of Souls
    BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (2006) 29, 453–498 Printed in the United States of America The folk psychology of souls Jesse M. Bering Institute of Cognition and Culture, Queen’s University Belfast, Belfast BT7 1NN, United Kingdom. [email protected] qub.ac.uk/icc http://www.qub.ac.uk/schools/InstituteofCognitionCulture/Staff/ JesseMBering/ Abstract: The present article examines how people’s belief in an afterlife, as well as closely related supernatural beliefs, may open an empirical backdoor to our understanding of the evolution of human social cognition. Recent findings and logic from the cognitive sciences contribute to a novel theory of existential psychology, one that is grounded in the tenets of Darwinian natural selection. Many of the predominant questions of existential psychology strike at the heart of cognitive science. They involve: causal attribution (why is mortal behavior represented as being causally related to one’s afterlife? how are dead agents envisaged as communicating messages to the living?), moral judgment (why are certain social behaviors, i.e., transgressions, believed to have ultimate repercussions after death or to reap the punishment of disgruntled ancestors?), theory of mind (how can we know what it is “like” to be dead? what social-cognitive strategies do people use to reason about the minds of the dead?), concept acquisition (how does a common-sense dualism interact with a formalized socio-religious indoctrination in childhood? how are supernatural properties of the dead conceptualized by young minds?), and teleological reasoning (why do people so often see their lives as being designed for a purpose that must be accomplished before they perish? how do various life events affect people’s interpretation of this purpose?), among others.
    [Show full text]
  • In Defence of Folk Psychology
    FRANK JACKSON & PHILIP PETTIT IN DEFENCE OF FOLK PSYCHOLOGY (Received 14 October, 1988) It turned out that there was no phlogiston, no caloric fluid, and no luminiferous ether. Might it turn out that there are no beliefs and desires? Patricia and Paul Churchland say yes. ~ We say no. In part one we give our positive argument for the existence of beliefs and desires, and in part two we offer a diagnosis of what has misled the Church- lands into holding that it might very well turn out that there are no beliefs and desires. 1. THE EXISTENCE OF BELIEFS AND DESIRES 1.1. Our Strategy Eliminativists do not insist that it is certain as of now that there are no beliefs and desires. They insist that it might very well turn out that there are no beliefs and desires. Thus, in order to engage with their position, we need to provide a case for beliefs and desires which, in addition to being a strong one given what we now know, is one which is peculiarly unlikely to be undermined by future progress in neuroscience. Our first step towards providing such a case is to observe that the question of the existence of beliefs and desires as conceived in folk psychology can be divided into two questions. There exist beliefs and desires if there exist creatures with states truly describable as states of believing that such-and-such or desiring that so-and-so. Our question, then, can be divided into two questions. First, what is it for a state to be truly describable as a belief or as a desire; what, that is, needs to be the case according to our folk conception of belief and desire for a state to be a belief or a desire? And, second, is what needs to be the case in fact the case? Accordingly , if we accepted a certain, simple behaviourist account of, say, our folk Philosophical Studies 59:31--54, 1990.
    [Show full text]
  • How Music Makes Us Feel
    Georgia State University ScholarWorks @ Georgia State University Philosophy Theses Department of Philosophy 8-7-2012 How Music Makes Us Feel Alexander Economides Georgia State University Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarworks.gsu.edu/philosophy_theses Recommended Citation Economides, Alexander, "How Music Makes Us Feel." Thesis, Georgia State University, 2012. https://scholarworks.gsu.edu/philosophy_theses/106 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Department of Philosophy at ScholarWorks @ Georgia State University. It has been accepted for inclusion in Philosophy Theses by an authorized administrator of ScholarWorks @ Georgia State University. For more information, please contact [email protected]. HOW MUSIC MAKES US FEEL by ALEXANDER ECONOMIDES Under the Direction of Andrea Scarantino ABSTRACT According to folk psychology, instrumental music regularly elicits emotions in listeners. Philos- ophers and psychologists such as Kivy, Konecni and Zangwill have questioned the existence of these musically elicited emotions, arguing that instrumental music elicits moods or aesthetic judgments rather than emotions. I defend the folk psychological position against these skeptics. The first chapter sets up the debate surrounding musically elicited emotions, while chapters two and three defend the thesis that instrumental music elicits emotions against the critics’ argu- ments. Chapter four outlines the implications of this defense for a variety of fields. INDEX WORDS: Emotion, Affect, Mood, Cognitivism,
    [Show full text]
  • The Role of Language in Theory of Mind Development
    Top Lang Disorders Vol. 34, No. 4, pp. 313–328 Copyright c 2014 Wolters Kluwer Health | Lippincott Williams & Wilkins The Role of Language in Theory of Mind Development Jill G. de Villiers and Peter A. de Villiers Various arguments are reviewed about the claim that language development is critically connected to the development of theory of mind. The different theories of how language could help in this process of development are explored. A brief account is provided of the controversy over the capacities of infants to read others’ false beliefs. Then the empirical literature on the steps in theory of mind development is summarized, considering studies on both typically developing and various language-delayed children. Suggestions are made for intervention by speech language pathologists to enhance the child’s access to understanding the minds of others. Key words: conversation, false beliefs, false complements, language, narrative, theory of mind N THIS ARTICLE, we review arguments on interactions between language and ToM I and evidence for the claim that children’s in both typically developing and language- language acquisition is crucially connected to delayed children. We end with suggestions their development of a theory of mind (ToM). for using language interventions to facilitate Theory of mind refers to the child’s ability to children’s understanding of their own mental understand that other people have minds, and states as well as the minds of others. those minds contain beliefs, knowledge, de- sires, and emotions that may be different from THEORIES OF THE RELATIONSHIP those of the child. If the child can figure out BETWEEN LANGUAGE AND ToM those contents, then other people’s behavior will begin to make sense and, therefore, be Many writers have made a convincing case predictable and explainable.
    [Show full text]
  • Naive Psychology: Preschoolers' Understanding of Intention and False Belief and Its Relationship to Mental Word
    Naive Psychology: Preschoolers' Understanding of Intention and False Belief and Its Relationship to Mental Word Item Type text; Electronic Dissertation Authors Jian, Jianhua Publisher The University of Arizona. Rights Copyright © is held by the author. Digital access to this material is made possible by the University Libraries, University of Arizona. Further transmission, reproduction or presentation (such as public display or performance) of protected items is prohibited except with permission of the author. Download date 29/09/2021 04:28:04 Link to Item http://hdl.handle.net/10150/193561 NAIVE PSYCHOLOGY: PRESCHOOLER S’ UNDERSTANDING OF INTENTION AND FALSE BELIEF AND ITS RELATIONSHIP TO MENTAL WORD by Jianhua Jian _____________________ Copyright © Jianhua Jian 2006 A Dissertation Submitted to the Faculty of the DEPARTMENT OF EDUCATION AL PSYCHOLOGY In Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements For the Degree of DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY In the Graduate College THE UNIVERSITY OF ARIZONA 2 0 0 6 2 THE UNIVERSITY OF ARIZONA GRADUATE COLLEGE As members of the Dissertation Committee, we certify that we have read the dissertation prepared by Jianhua Jian entitled Naïve psychology: Preschoolers’ understanding of intention and false belief and its relationship to mental word and recommend that it be accepted as fulfilling the dissertation require ment for the Deg ree of Doctor of Philosophy _______ ___________________________ __________________ ________ _______ ____ Date : 3/23/2006 Rosemary Rosser, Ph.D. _______ ___________________________ __________________ ________ ___________ Date: 3/23/2006 Lawre nce Aleamoni, Ph.D. _______ ___________________________ __________________ ________ ___________ Date: 3/23/2006 Sheri Bauman, Ph.D. _______ ___________________________ __________________ ________ ___________ Date: 3/23/2006 Glenda Wilkes, Ph.D.
    [Show full text]
  • A Pluralistic Folk Psychology
    WellBeing International WBI Studies Repository 11-2008 It's in Your Nature: A Pluralistic Folk Psychology Kristin Andrews York University Follow this and additional works at: https://www.wellbeingintlstudiesrepository.org/acwp_asie Part of the Animal Studies Commons, Comparative Psychology Commons, and the Other Animal Sciences Commons Recommended Citation Andrews, K. (2008). It’s in your nature: a pluralistic folk psychology. Synthese, 165(1), 13-29. This material is brought to you for free and open access by WellBeing International. It has been accepted for inclusion by an authorized administrator of the WBI Studies Repository. For more information, please contact [email protected]. It's in Your Nature: A Pluralistic Folk Psychology Kristin Andrews York University 1. Folk psychology as attribution of the attitudes The everyday human practices of predicting, explaining, interpreting, judging, coordinating and otherwise socially interacting with others are grounded in an understanding of others as minded agents. This understanding of others is commonly understood as requiring the ability to attribute mental states— paradigmatically beliefs and desires. However, there is good reason to think that the commonsense conception of the mind is pluralistic, and not limited to the attribution of propositional attitudes. While it is true that part of the commonsense view is that people act for reasons, and that those reasons are mentally represented propositions, the folk also think that people act because of who they are as persons. I will argue that people predict and explain behavior by appeal to personality traits, and that at least some personality traits cannot be understood as an oblique reference to beliefs, desires, or any other propositional attitude.
    [Show full text]
  • The Unconscious in Social Explanation
    UC Berkeley UC Berkeley Previously Published Works Title The Unconscious in Social Explanation Permalink https://escholarship.org/uc/item/23z014dj Journal Philosophical Psychology, 17 Author Bevir, Mark Publication Date 2004 Peer reviewed eScholarship.org Powered by the California Digital Library University of California THE UNCONSICOUS IN SOCIAL EXPLANATION By Mark Bevir I. CONTACT INFORMATION Department of Political Science, University of California, Berkeley, CA 94720-1950 [E-mail: [email protected] ] II. ABSTRACT The proper range and content of the unconscious in the human sciences should be established by reference to its conceptual relationship to the folk psychology that informs the standard form of explanation therein. A study of this relationship shows that human scientists should appeal to the unconscious only when the language of the conscious fails them, that is typically when they find a conflict between people's self-understanding and their actions. This study also shows that human scientists should adopt a broader concept of the unconscious than the one developed by Freud, that is, one free from his ahistorical concept of the instincts and his ahistorical emphasis on the sexual experiences of childhood. The unconscious, understood in this way, has an ambiguous relationship to more recent linguistic and narrativist strands of psycho-analysis. III. KEY WORDS Explanation, Freud, Mind, Narrative, Psychology, Sociology, Unconscious THE UNCONSCIOUS IN SOCIAL EXPLANATION The genius of Freud lies in the concepts he gave us to discuss things people barely could discuss before (Wollheim, 1993, pp. 106-24). Where people had found meaningless stuff, they now find patterns of behaviour that make sense.
    [Show full text]
  • Damage, Flourishing, and Two Sides of Morality
    ESHARE: AN IRANIAN JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY, Vol. 1, No 1, pp. 1-11. DAMAGE, FLOURISHING, AND TWO SIDES OF MORALITY ADAM MORTON University of British Columbia ABSTRACT: Humans are at their best when they are making things: families, social systems, music, mathematics, etc. This is human flourishing, to use the word in the somewhat un-idiomatic way that has come to be standard in translating Aristotle and developing views like his. We admire well-made things of all these kinds, and the people who make them well. And although "happiness" is not a good translation of Aristotle's edudaimonia, it is a plausible conjecture about human psychology that people are happiest — most content, most satisfied with their lives, least troubled — when they are accomplishing, making, things of all these kinds, from families to mathematics. And they are miserable when they cannot. One kind of misery comes when one's efforts are not successful. Families fail, music is detested, "theorems" have counterexamples. Another kind of misery comes when one is blocked from being able to achieve any of the things that human life is shaped around. The focus of this paper is on ways that people's actions can make other people incapable of achieving properly human lives. This is what I call damage. I think its importance has only recently come to be appreciated; the delay in acknowledging it as a central moral concept has been particularly long in philosophy. And in human cultures worldwide an appreciation of how vulnerable we are to psychological damage is very recent. KEYWORDS: atrocity, cooperation, damage, ethics, evil, harm, human flourishing, imagination, morality, utilitarianism.
    [Show full text]
  • The Place of the Psyche in a Constructed World
    Swarthmore College Works Psychology Faculty Works Psychology 12-1-1997 The Place Of The Psyche In A Constructed World Kenneth J. Gergen Swarthmore College, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://works.swarthmore.edu/fac-psychology Part of the Psychology Commons Let us know how access to these works benefits ouy Recommended Citation Kenneth J. Gergen. (1997). "The Place Of The Psyche In A Constructed World". Theory And Psychology. Volume 7, Issue 6. 723-746. DOI: 10.1177/0959354397076001 https://works.swarthmore.edu/fac-psychology/321 This work is brought to you for free by Swarthmore College Libraries' Works. It has been accepted for inclusion in Psychology Faculty Works by an authorized administrator of Works. For more information, please contact [email protected]. See discussions, stats, and author profiles for this publication at: https://www.researchgate.net/publication/258190640 The Place of the Psyche in a Constructed World ARTICLE in THEORY & PSYCHOLOGY · DECEMBER 1997 Impact Factor: 0.7 · DOI: 10.1177/0959354397076001 CITATIONS READS 63 55 2 AUTHORS, INCLUDING: Kenneth J. Gergen Swarthmore College 278 PUBLICATIONS 11,202 CITATIONS SEE PROFILE Available from: Kenneth J. Gergen Retrieved on: 05 April 2016 Draft copy for Theory and Psychology, 1997, 7, 31-36. The Place of the Psyche in a Constructed World Kenneth J. Gergen Interest in the family of ideas loosely labeled "social constructionist" has burgeoned within recent years, and now spans the full range of the social sciences and humanities.
    [Show full text]
  • Folk Psychology317
    Folk Psychology317 In the study of naive biology, disagreement arises over Bulmer, R. (1967). Why is the cassowary not a bird? Man 2: 5–25. whether higher-order principles evince strong or weak Carey, S. (1995). On the origins of causal understanding. In S. NATIVISM; that is, whether they reflect the innate modularity Sperber, D. Premack, and A. Premack, Eds., Causal Cognition. and DOMAIN-SPECIFICITY of folk biology (Inagaki and Oxford: Clarendon Press. Hatano 1996), or are learned on the basis of cognitive prin- Darwin, C. (1859). On the Origins of Species by Natural Selec- tion. London: Murray. ciples inherent to other domains, such as NAIVE PHYSICS or Ellen, R. (1993). The Cultural Relations of Classification. Cam- FOLK PSYCHOLOGY (Carey 1995). One candidate for a bridge: Cambridge University Press. domain-specific principle involves a particular sort of Gilmour, J., and S. Walters. (1964). Philosophy and classification. ESSENTIALISM, which carries an invariable presumption that In W. Turrill, Ed., Vistas in Botany, vol. 4: Recent Researches in the various members of each generic species share a unique Plant Taxonomy. Oxford: Pergamon Press. underlying nature, or biological essence. Such an essence Hunn, E. (1976). Toward a perceptual model of folkbiological clas- may be considered domain-specific insofar as it is an intrin- sification. American Ethnologist 3: 508–524. sic (i.e., nonartifactual) teleological agent, which physically Inakagi, K., and G. Hatano. (1996). Young children’s recognition (i.e., nonintentionally) causes the biologically relevant parts of commonalities between plants and animals. Child Develop- and properties of a generic species to function and cohere ment 67: 2823–2840.
    [Show full text]
  • (Tomi): a Study of Typically Developing Children and Children with Autism Spectrum Disorder
    J Autism Dev Disord DOI 10.1007/s10803-011-1244-7 ORIGINAL PAPER Psychometric Evaluation of the Theory of Mind Inventory (ToMI): A Study of Typically Developing Children and Children with Autism Spectrum Disorder Tiffany L. Hutchins • Patricia A. Prelock • Laura Bonazinga Ó Springer Science+Business Media, LLC 2011 Abstract Two studies examined the psychometric prop- underlies our folk psychology with which we impute erties of the Theory of Mind Inventory (ToMI). In Study mental states to others and ourselves’’ (Perner and Lang One, 135 caregivers completed the ToMI for children (ages 2000, p. 150) and ‘‘an intentional stance that characterizes 3 through 17) with autism spectrum disorder (ASD). human social interaction’’ (Astington 2003, p. 14). Indeed, Findings revealed excellent test–retest reliability and ToM has been described as a term that ‘‘refuses to be internal consistency. Principle Components Analysis corralled’’ (Astington and Baird 2005, p. 4) and so one revealed three subscales related to the complexity of ToM useful description of ToM is its construal as a complex and understanding. In Study Two, data were collected for 124 multifaceted construct that reflects the understanding of an typically developing children (2 through 12 years). Find- interconnected network of mental states. ings again revealed excellent test–retest and internal con- Despite the tremendous activity in the field and devel- sistency. The ToMI distinguished groups by age (younger opments in ToM assessment procedures (for reviews see vs. older children) and developmental status (typically Baron-Cohen 2000; Sprung 2010), the measurement of developing vs. ASD), and predicted child performance on a ToM has traditionally been associated with several chal- ToM task battery.
    [Show full text]
  • Public Lecture in Philosophy
    March 2011 DEPARTMENT OF PHILOSOPHY • UNIVERSITY OF ALBERTA MESSAGE FROM THE CHAIR, Bruce Hunter A warm welcome to all readers of the Department of Philosophy newsletter that keeps you in touch with developments in your department. I thank the editor, Robert Burch, for the work that he put into the newsletter. One event that we hope keeps you in touch is our Annual Public Lecture in Philosophy. This year’s lecture will be given by Allen Carlson on April 7, 2011, and is entitled “How Should We Aesthetically Appreciate Nature.” Everyone is welcome to both the lecture and the reception that will follow. Details can be found below. continued on page 3 INSIDE Thursday, April 7 PUBLIC 3:30 pm 2 Faculty Research Profiles H.M. Tory Building Allen Carlson PROFESSOR EMERITUS Room B-95 3 Message from the Chair DEPT. OF PHILOSOPHY LECTURE (Basement of Tory) 4 Conference Activity How Should We 5 Philosophy Faculty Awards Aesthetically Appreciate Nature? 6 Philosophy for Children The question of how we should aesthetically appreciate nature has both historical 7 Student Awards & Recent Graduates and contemporary significance, since our appreciation of natural environments has greatly influenced and continues to influence how we treat such environments, in particular, which of them we preserve and which we allocate to various human uses, such as resource extraction and development. The question has been addressed by several different accounts of the aesthetic appreciation of nature, ranging from time-honoured approaches such as the picturesque tradition and landscape formalism to more recent points of view, which are typically associated with cultural relativism and postmodernism.
    [Show full text]