Norms As Mental Objects -- from Normative Beliefs to Normative Goals

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Norms As Mental Objects -- from Normative Beliefs to Normative Goals From: AAAI Technical Report SS-93-05. Compilation copyright © 1993, AAAI (www.aaai.org). All rights reserved. Norms as mental objects. From normative beliefs to normative goals. RosariaConte* Cristiano Castelfranchi* set up the value of the resources 1. Introduction exchanged, that is, what each is entitled to expect from others in retum, given the The study of norms (Ns) is resources invested. Without a norm of recent but growing concern in the AI reciprocation, such expectation would be field (cf. [MOS92];[SHO92]) as well easily disconfirmed when social within other formal approaches to social exchange, as often happens, does not action, such as Game Theory (where occur simultaneously. The utilitarian theories of Ns began to appear long agent would spontaneously respect the before, cf.[LEW69]; [ULL77]). The agreement only if the partner is regarded normative is an essential dimension of as stronger. Otherwise, he would get social life. An explicit model of such away with no costs, in a word, he would dimension is crucial for any theory of cheat. social action. Notions such as "social Analogously, joint intentions and commitment" (cf. [GAS91]; [COH90]; teamwork arise from true negotiation etc.) "joint intentions", "teamwork" and create rights based on commitments. [COH91], "negotiation" [DAV83], Finally, roles are but sets of obligations "social roles" [WER89] etc. will not and rights. escape a purely metaphorical use if their A norm-abiding behavior need normative character is not accounted for. not be based on the cognitive processing Indeed, one’s committing oneself of Ns (it might be simply due to before someoneelse causes the latter to imitation), nor does a normative mind be entitled, on the very basis of necessarily produce a behavior commitment, to expect, control, and corresponding to Ns (Ns are operating in exact the action one has committed the mind even if the agent’s final oneself to. Social commitment is a decision is to transgress against them). customary, if not the most frequent, To model the normative reasoning does source of entitlements in everyday not imply to model a norm-abiding interaction: first of all, a promisecreates system. However, a large portion of an entitled expectation in the addressee, autonomous agents’ normative behavior namely a belief that the promised course is allowed by a cognitive processing of of action will be realized. As a Ns. Therefore, Ns are not only an consequence, the addressee feels entitled essentially social but also a mentalistic to exact the action expected, that is, to notion. Ns are indeed a typical node of control its occurrence and react if it is the micro-macrolink, of the link between not performed. In particular, the individual agents and collective addressee is entitled to express a public phenomena, minds and social structures. protest and receive the consent and A view of normative systems as support of the community of witnesses "emerging properties" of the social before whomthe action of commitment systems, improving coordination within took place. the social systems themselves (cf. Furthermore, there is no true [MOS92])is not sufficient. negotiation without control for cheaters On one hand, that of and norm of reciprocation (of. coordination is only one of the [GOU60]). Whensocial agents negotiate functionalities of Ns. Amongothers, an exchange of resources, they actually consider the function of identification, (the good manners, for example, improve identification rather than coordination: on their grounds, in- SBSP- Social BehaviorSimulation Project, Istituto di Psicologia,CNR, V.le Marx15, 1- groups are allowed to be identified, etc.); 00137Roma, Italy. that of protecting the single’s interests Tel: (06) 8292626,Fax: (06) 824737,e-mail: beyond its own will (as happens with the PSCS~IRMKANT.BITNET norms prescribing to fasten seat belts, to wear helmets when riding motorcycles 40 etc.) Furthermore,there are at least two and someinitial solutions proposed. types of norms of coordination: those The problemsare the following: whichare aimedat improvingthe agents’ performances(like the traffic norms), - Howare Ns represented in the and those which are intended to reduce agents’ minds? Should they be displayed aggression (like the normof seen as a specific mental object, reciprocation). and if so, whichone? On the other hand, the - Whichrelation do they bear with emergenceparadigm gives an account of beliefs and goals? Howcan they conventional norms and conforming regulate the agents’ behaviors? behaviors (cf. [BIC90]), but leaves - Howis their prescriptive (and not unexplainedthe prescriptive character of simply conventional) character norms. Within the game-theoretic (that is, a more or less explicit paradigm,a social normis defined as an request and the corresponding equilibrium, a combinationof strategies duty) expressed? such that "each maximizeshis expected - Whydoes an autonomous agent utility by conforming,on the condition complywith norms, thus fulfilling that nearly everybodyelse conforms to others’ expectations? the norm." (cf. [BIC90: 842]) Social norms are defined as behavioral 2. The normativecoin. regularities which emerge from the strategic agents’ choices to conform. What is a norm in an agent’s This is an account of the spreading of mind?This question leaves aside another certain behaviors over a population of fundamental question, namely what is a strategic agents, in a word, a modelof N tout court. Althoughprioritary, wewill social conventions. However, such a not face this question here (however,see model does not account for a crucial [CAS91]).Therefore, we will not try to aspect of the normative mechanism, answer the question what the "external" which plays a role in the spreading of side of Ns is, namely, how Ns are normative behaviors, namely the encountered in social life, which normativerequest. Whatis lacking in the functionalities they have, whichfeatures game-theoretic definition define de facto (independent of agents’ aforementioned is a reference to the beliefs) a normativesource, etc.. agent’s will that others conformto the Here, we will focus exclusively norms. A social norm, indeed, is such if on the "internal" side of Ns, that is: it is associated at least with a general Whichcognitive role do Ns play in the wantthat it be observed. Such a wantis agents’ minds and in which format are usually conveyed in many ways: from they represented? Whatkind of mental simple expectations (note that the term object is a N? Whatis a normativesource expectation is often used to refer to a in the agents’beliefs? hybrid mental object, namely a There are at least two distinct goal/belief: if you expect the weather ways in which norms can be tomorrow to be sunny and warm you implemented on a computer system: as both believe and wish it to be so), to built-in functioning rules and constraints explicit commandsand requests; from (like productionrules) or as explicit and implicit disapproval of transgressors, to specific mentalobjects (i.e. obligations, explicit reproachetc.. duties, etc.) distinct from, say, goals and Therefore, here it is intended to beliefs. Of course, there might be draw the attention on both the following intermediate solutions: for example,and aspects: in line with the game-theoreticview, one might think of noms as a way of ¯ the prescriptive character of Ns, describing the behaviors of strategic that is, their role in controlling and agents in interaction: no specific regulating the behaviors of agents normativeobject is implementedin those subject to them; agents’ mindsalthough cognitive action is allowed. A further alternative consists ¯ a need for a mentalistic notion of of implementingNs just as goals, namely Ns allowing cognitive agents to final ends: In this case, cognitive agents becomenormative agents as well. Ns would be allowed to choose amongtheir are not yet sufficiently characterized (competing) goals (instead of simply as mental objects (cf [SHO92]).Here, applying procedures and routines) but some crucial problems concerning they wouldtreat Ns as any other goal of the mentalnature of Ns will be raised theirs. At least two undesirable 41 consequences seem to derive from the the future behavior of the agents subject latter eventuality: the observance of Ns to them, their addressees (As). would come to depend exclusively upon To this end, they ought to give the agents’ subjective preferences, and rise to some new goal in an A’s mind there would be no social control and (cfr. [CON91b]): for autonomous agents influencing. To implement norms as to undertake (or abstain from) a course specific mental objects, although a costly of action, it is not sufficient that they alternative, is required in a cognitive knowthat this course of action is wanted modelling approach to social agenthood, (by someone else) (cf. [ROS88]; in which the present work is framed. [GAL90]). It is necessary that these Moreover, the cognitive regulatory agents have the goal to do so. Norms endowment of the human species has may act as a mechanism of goal- undoubtedly profited by the explicit generation. Indeed, they represent a representation of norms. A crucial but powerful mechanism for inducing new difficult task, beyond the scope of the goals in people’s minds in a cognitive present work, would then be to explore way. Howis this possible? these advantages and confront them with At first, Ns need being those of all alternatives considered. represented as beliefs in an A’s mind. Let Our language draws on us start from beliefs about requests. A [COH90]’smodel for describing rational simple request, before succeeding and interaction. For the readability of the producing acceptance on the side of the paper, let us provide the semantics of the required person, is nothing but a belief, main predicates used and the axiom namely a belief about someone’s will. (A1) here called the axiom of goal- Such a belief can be expressed as generation (for further analysis, see follows: [COH90], [CON91a], [CON91b]): (BELx (GOALy (GOALx p))) (1) a: action; p andq: states of the world; where agent x believes someone else, v: a worldstatepositively valued; agent y, has the goal that x has the goal x ,y, andz single agents; that p.
Recommended publications
  • Social Norms and Social Influence Mcdonald and Crandall 149
    Available online at www.sciencedirect.com ScienceDirect Social norms and social influence Rachel I McDonald and Christian S Crandall Psychology has a long history of demonstrating the power and and their imitation is not enough to implicate social reach of social norms; they can hardly be overestimated. To norms. Imitation is common enough in many forms of demonstrate their enduring influence on a broad range of social life — what creates the foundation for culture and society phenomena, we describe two fields where research continues is not the imitation, but the expectation of others for when to highlight the power of social norms: prejudice and energy imitation is appropriate, and when it is not. use. The prejudices that people report map almost perfectly onto what is socially appropriate, likewise, people adjust their A social norm is an expectation about appropriate behav- energy use to be more in line with their neighbors. We review ior that occurs in a group context. Sherif and Sherif [8] say new approaches examining the effects of norms stemming that social norms are ‘formed in group situations and from multiple groups, and utilizing normative referents to shift subsequently serve as standards for the individual’s per- behaviors in social networks. Though the focus of less research ception and judgment when he [sic] is not in the group in recent years, our review highlights the fundamental influence situation. The individual’s major social attitudes are of social norms on social behavior. formed in relation to group norms (pp. 202–203).’ Social norms, or group norms, are ‘regularities in attitudes and Address behavior that characterize a social group and differentiate Department of Psychology, University of Kansas, Lawrence, KS 66045, it from other social groups’ [9 ] (p.
    [Show full text]
  • What Normative Terms Mean and Why It Matters for Ethical Eory
    What Normative Terms Mean and Why It Matters for Ethical eory* Alex Silk University of Birmingham [email protected] Forthcoming in M. Timmons (Ed.), Oxford Studies in Normative Ethics, Vol. Abstract is paper investigates how inquiry into normative language can improve substantive normative theorizing. First I examine two dimensions along which normative language differs: “strength” and “subjectivity.” Next I show how greater sensitivity to these features of the meaning and use of normative lan- guage can illuminate debates about three issues in ethics: the coherence of moral dilemmas, the possibility of supererogatory acts, and the connection between making a normative judgment and being motivated to act accord- ingly. e paper concludes with several brief reections on the theoretical utility of the distinction — at least so-called — between “normative” and “non- normative” language and judgment. e discussions of these specic linguistic and normative issues can be seen as case studies illustrating the fruitfulness of utilizing resources from philosophy of language for normative theory. Get- ting clearer on the language we use in normative conversation and theorizing can help us diagnose problems with bad arguments and formulate better mo- tivated questions. is can lead to clearer answers and bring into relief new theoretical possibilities and avenues to explore. *anks to Eric Swanson and the audience at the Fih Annual Arizona Normative Ethics Work- shop for discussion, and to two anonymous referees for comments. Contents Introduction Weak and strong necessity Endorsing and non-endorsing uses Dilemmas Supererogation Judgment internalism and “the normative” Conclusion Introduction e strategy of clarifying philosophical questions by investigating the language we use to express them is familiar.
    [Show full text]
  • Epistemic Justification, Normative Guidance, and Knowledge
    13 Epistemic Justication, Normative Guidance, and Knowledge ∗ ARTURS LOGINS Abstract. Recently, Pascal Engel has defended a version of a compatibilist view in epistemology that combines both an element of externalism and an element of internalism (Engel 2007, 2012). According to this position exter- nalism has to be adopted about knowledge, whereas internalism has to be endorsed concerning epistemic justification. In this paper I argue that consi- derations that, allegedly, motivates Engel’s internalism about epistemic justi- fication, can be explained equally well, or, indeed, even better by a knowledge based externalist account of epistemic justification. ∗This paper is dedicated to Pascal Engel. I would like to express my gratefulness to Pascal for his teaching and support. His work has made an important impact on me. In particular his Engel 2000, and his Engel 2007 contributed largely to my initiation to analytic philosophy and contem- porary epistemology, respectively. The research work that lead to this article was supported by the Swiss National Science Foundation (SNSF) grant number 100015_131794 (project Knowledge, Evidence, and Practice). 169 170 ARTURS LOGINS 1. Introduction Recently, Pascal Engel has defended a version of a compatibilist view in epis- temology that combines both an element of externalism and an element of internalism (Engel 2007, 2012). In short, according to this view, knowledge has to be characterized in externalist terms, whereas epistemic justification and ra- tionality has to be characterized in internalist terms. The externalist view about knowledge that Engel favours integrates a ver- sion of safety account of knowledge that requires that knowledge is safe belief and does not require that a subject has a reflective access top in order for the subject to know thatp (see Engel 2012 : 8).
    [Show full text]
  • Hartian Positivism and Normative Facts: How Facts Make Law II
    UCLA UCLA Public Law & Legal Theory Series Title Hartian Positivism and Normative Facts: How Facts Make Law II Permalink https://escholarship.org/uc/item/81q9p7hk Author Greenberg, Mark Publication Date 2006-03-03 Peer reviewed eScholarship.org Powered by the California Digital Library University of California Hartian Positivism and Normative Facts: How Facts Make Law II Mark Greenberg UCLA School of Law and Department of Philosophy I. Introduction In How Facts Make Law and other recent papers,1 I argue that a full constitutive account of the content of the law – of legal facts – must appeal to normative facts. The project of HFML is to defend this position without assuming that legal facts are themselves normative facts. The argument’s engine is a requirement that a constitutive account of legal facts must meet. According to this rational-relation requirement,2 it is not enough for a constitutive account of legal facts to specify non-legal facts that modally determine the legal facts. The constitutive determinants of legal facts must provide reasons for the obtaining of the legal facts (in a sense of “reason” that I develop). In HFML,3 I argue that non-normative, contingent facts – descriptive facts, for short – do not provide such reasons without normative facts.4 In the present paper, I focus on the rational-relation requirement. I deploy it in three related projects. First, I respond to a family of objections that challenge me to explain why normative facts and descriptive facts together are better placed to provide 1 Mark Greenberg, How Facts Make Law, <INSERT CITE FOR HFML IN THIS VOLUME HERE 2006> [hereinafter HFML].
    [Show full text]
  • Normative Surrender
    Michigan Journal of International Law Volume 9 Issue 1 1988 Normative Surrender Jerome B. Elkind University of Wyoming, College of Law Follow this and additional works at: https://repository.law.umich.edu/mjil Part of the Human Rights Law Commons, International Law Commons, and the Public Law and Legal Theory Commons Recommended Citation Jerome B. Elkind, Normative Surrender, 9 MICH. J. INT'L L. 263 (1988). Available at: https://repository.law.umich.edu/mjil/vol9/iss1/9 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Michigan Journal of International Law at University of Michigan Law School Scholarship Repository. It has been accepted for inclusion in Michigan Journal of International Law by an authorized editor of University of Michigan Law School Scholarship Repository. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Normative Surrender Jerome B. Elkind* INTRODUCTION In the published papers of a recent colloquium on the life and works of Hugo Grotius, the observation was made that Grotius attempted to steer a path between "Utopian idealism which had no chance of exercising any influence on the actual behavior of States, and Machiavellian realism which would have amounted to total surrender to their will and whim."' Concern for the distinction between idealism and realism, an issue even at the dawn of the era of power politics, is very much a current issue. In the world of modem international law doctrine there is no greater scorn than that reserved by self-professed "realists" for those whom they choose to regard as "idealists." In the cynical atmosphere of the late twentieth century, it is fashionable to be a realist.
    [Show full text]
  • Normative and Descriptive Aspects of Management Education: Differentiation and Integration
    Journal of Educational Issues ISSN 2377-2263 2015, Vol. 1, No. 1 Normative and Descriptive Aspects of Management Education: Differentiation and Integration Gavriel Meirovich (Corresponding author) Department of Management, Bertolon School of Business, Salem State University 352 Lafayette Street, Salem, MA 01930, United States Tel: 978-543-6948 Fax: 978-542-6027 E-mail: [email protected] Received: April 7, 2015 Accepted: May 27, 2015 Published: June 3, 2015 doi:10.5296/jei.v1i1.7395 URL: http://dx.doi.org/10.5296/jei.v1i1.7395 Abstract This study advocates strongly for clear differentiation and synthesis of descriptive and normative approaches in management education. There is a certain isolation of normative and descriptive theoretical frameworks presented in management courses. Normative frameworks in management explain how organizations should be managed, while descriptive frameworks show how they actually are managed. Significant portions of what we teach in the business curriculum are predominantly descriptive; other parts are mostly normative, or prescriptive. If these domains are not sufficiently connected, the relevance of both approaches diminishes. When one piece of material explains only the current reality without providing tools to improve it, while another piece prescribes steps for improvement that are not grounded in a particular context, students lose interest in both. The paper presents various modes of differentiation and integration between two realms and pertinent ways to recalibrate management courses. Keywords: Normative and descriptive framework, Differentiation, Integration 1. Introduction The purpose of business education is preparing future business professionals for successful careers and meaningful lives. The continued rise of its cost poses difficult questions about the relevance of contemporary business education in general and management education in particular.
    [Show full text]
  • Positive Constraints on Normative Political Theory
    Manchester Centre for Political Theory (MANCEPT) Working Paper Series - 2007 ISSN 1749-9747 POSITIVE CONSTRAINTS ON NORMATIVE POLITICAL THEORY Geoffrey Brennan Research School of Social Sciences Australian National University and Alan Hamlin School of Social Sciences University of Manchester Abstract We consider the relationship between positive and normative political theory, emphasising both the role of normative ideas in motivating political behaviour and particularly the constraints on normative theory imposed by positive theory. Our point of departure is Christiano’s recent claim that the rational choice approach to positive and normative political theory is self-defeating. In arguing against this position, we outline a revisionist rational choice approach that we believe provides a bridge between positive and normative political theories, and clarifies the nature of the constraints on normative theory. Introduction What should be the relationship between positive political theory and normative political theory? This is the large question towards which this essay edges. The answer to this large question will depend, in part, on our understanding of the purposes of positive and normative political theory respectively. We will not dwell for long on discussing the range of potential purposes and will simply stipulate that a primary purpose of positive political theory is to explain observed political behaviour. We will make no attempt to specify what we mean by ‘explain’, or the differences between explanation, prediction and other related ideas, but we will stress that the central idea of explanation goes beyond mere description while leaving open a wide variety of approaches to positive political theory1. With respect to normative political theory, we identify three possible aims.
    [Show full text]
  • Law and Morality: a Kantian Perspective
    Columbia Law School Scholarship Archive Faculty Scholarship Faculty Publications 1987 Law and Morality: A Kantian Perspective George P. Fletcher Columbia Law School, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarship.law.columbia.edu/faculty_scholarship Part of the Jurisprudence Commons, and the Law and Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation George P. Fletcher, Law and Morality: A Kantian Perspective, 87 COLUM. L. REV. 533 (1987). Available at: https://scholarship.law.columbia.edu/faculty_scholarship/1071 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Faculty Publications at Scholarship Archive. It has been accepted for inclusion in Faculty Scholarship by an authorized administrator of Scholarship Archive. For more information, please contact [email protected]. LAW AND MORALITY: A KANTIAN PERSPECTIVE George P. Fletcher* The relationship between law and morality has emerged as the cen- tral question in the jurisprudential reflection of our time. Those who call themselves positivists hold with H.L.A. Hart' that calling a statute or a judicial decision "law" need not carry any implications about the morality of that statute or decision.2 Valid laws might be immoral or unjust. Those who resist this reduction of law to valid enactments sometimes argue, with Lon Fuller, that moral acceptability is a neces- sary condition for holding that a statute is law; 3 or, with Ronald Dworkin, that moral principles supplement valid enactments as compo- 4 nents of the law. Whether the positivists or their "moralist" opponents are right about the nature of law, all seem to agree about the nature of morality. We have to distinguish, it is commonly said, between conventional and critical morality.
    [Show full text]
  • Ayer-Freedom-Necessity.Pdf
    10 A. J Ayer III to this 'feeling' offreedom that some philosophers appeal when they wish, in the supposed interes,ts of morality, to prove that not all human action is A. J. Ayer, causally determined. But if these philosophers are right in their assump- tion that a man cannot be acting freely ifhis action is causally determined, "Freedom and Necessity" then the fact that someone feels free to do, o( not to do, a certain action does not prove that he really is so. It may prove that the .agent does not himself know what it is that makes him act in one way rather than another: A. J Ayer(1910-1989)was a professor at Oxford University and advo- but from the fact that a man is unaware of the causes of his action, it does cated a positivist scientific world view from the 1930s until his death. In not follow that no such causes exist. "Freedom and Necessity" he advocatesa compatibilisttheoryof thesort of So much may be allowed to the determinist; but his belief that all freedom requiredfor moral responsibility. Ayer maintains that when agents human actions are subservient to causal laws still remains to be justified. are under constraint they do not have this sort of freedom. .But since agents !; If, indeed, it is necessary that every event should have a cause, then the "" do act without beingconstrained,they are morally responsiblefor someof "" rule must apply to human behaviour as much as to anything else. But why u: their actions, despite the truth of causal determinism.
    [Show full text]
  • Methods in Normative Political Theory Guest Speakers: Ian Carter (Università Di Pavia), Andrew Mason (University of Warwick), Mark Philp (University of Warwick)
    SPS 3rd term workshop 2016-2017 Methods in Normative Political Theory Guest speakers: Ian Carter (Università di Pavia), Andrew Mason (University of Warwick), Mark Philp (University of Warwick) Organised by Rainer Bauböck and Rutger Birnie and the Max Weber Programme Thursday 11 May 2017 (10.30-16:30 with lunch break) Friday 12 May 2017 (09:30-17:30 with lunch and coffee breaks) Seminar room 3, Badia Fiesolana Please register online (Contact: [email protected]) Description Issues of methodology have long been a neglected part of normative political theory, but are now being paid increasing attention. What kinds of questions should we ask in political theory and how should we address these questions? What are the criteria for good normative analysis in political theory? To what extent are diverging substantive conclusions determined by different methods of theorising? In this workshop, we will discuss such questions by focusing on three of the most prominent topics in this field, namely the role of conceptual analysis, the distinction between ‘ideal’ and ‘non-ideal’ or ‘realist’ theory, and the relevance of intellectual history for contemporary normative theory. In focusing on these topics, we are specifically interested in the links between normative theory and empirical research. What can normative theory contribute to empirical research, for example through rigorous analysis of those concepts which are also the main focus of political scientists? Conversely, what can empirical research tell us about the feasibility constraints which should guide normative theorising? Furthermore, the workshop should also be of interest to law researchers with normative elements in their research and intellectual historians.
    [Show full text]
  • Utilitarianism, Deontology, and Virtue Ethics
    Dr. Massimiliano Pellegrini Normative ethical theories: Utilitarianism, Deontology, and Virtue Ethics Foundation of European Thought: A Business Ethics perspective. 2/02/2017 Normative ethical theories Ethical theories should help in determining ‘right’ and ‘wrong’ for a certain situation, and in general for any circumstance, through the use rules and principles. Normative ethical theories are those that prescribe a ‘correct’ way to act morally (opposed to describe ethics that concern how ethical decisions are taken). Traditional approach Major normative theories Egoism Utilitarianism Ethics of duties Rights & justice Contributors Adam Smith Jeremy Bentham Immanuel Kant John Locke John Stuart Mill John Rawls Focus Individual desires or Collective welfare Duties Rights interests Rules Maximization of Act/rule utilitarianism Categorical imperative Respect for human desires/self interest beings Concept of Man as an actor with Man is controlled by Man is a rational moral Man is a being that is human limited knowledge and avoidance of pain and actor distinguished by dignity beings objectives gain of pleasure (“hedonist”) Type Consequentialist Consequentialist Non-consequentialist Non-consequentialist Source: Crane and Matten (2010) Utilitarianism • According to utilitarianism, an action is morally right if it results in the greatest amount of good for the greatest number of people affected by the action • Also called the ‘greatest happiness principle’ • Based on cost-benefit analysis Utilitarianism elements (1) • What is Good? • For Hedonism intrinsic good is the pleasure and the intrinsic bad is pain. • For Pluralistic Utilitarianism good is a variety of values, but this requires to rank or weigh them and this may be difficult. • How to measure Good? • Quantitative Utilitarianism, utility calculus.
    [Show full text]
  • A. the Three Main Branches of the Philosophical Study of Ethics 1
    A. The Three Main Branches of the Philosophical Study of Ethics 1. Meta-ethics 2. Normative Ethics 3. Applied Ethics 1 B. Meta-ethics consists in the attempt to answer the fundamental philosophical questions about the nature of ethical theory itself. Examples: 1. Are ethical statements such as "lying is wrong", or "friendship is good" true or false? a) cognitivism: the view that moral judgments are capable of being true or false b) non-cognitivism: the view that moral judgments are not capable of being true or false (instead they are like commands or interjections) c) debate limited to statements like examples above NOT statements like “Most Catholics oppose abortion” 2 B. Meta-ethics consists in the attempt to answer the fundamental philosophical questions about the nature of ethical theory itself. Examples: 2. Assuming there are truths of morality, what sorts of facts make them true? a) subjectivism: the view that moral truths are subjective, i.e., dependent upon the subjective attitudes, values, desires and beliefs of individuals, not on anything external to these things. b) objectivism: the view that moral truths are objective, i.e., based on facts that are independent of the attitudes, values, desires and beliefs of any individual. 3 1 B. Meta-ethics consists in the attempt to answer the fundamental philosophical questions about the nature of ethical theory itself. Examples: 3. What makes ethical discourse meaningful? Is it different from what makes other sorts of discourse meaningful? 4. How do the rules of logic apply to ethical arguments and ethical reasoning? Is it possible to validly infer a moral conclusion based on non-moral premises? 4 B.
    [Show full text]