Hyperintensionality and Synonymy

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Hyperintensionality and Synonymy HYPERINTENSIONALITY AND SYNONYMY A logical, philosophical, and cognitive investigation MSc Thesis (Afstudeerscriptie) written by Levin Hornischer (born October 17th, 1991 in Filderstadt, Germany) under the supervision of Prof. Dr. Franz Berto and Prof. DDr. Hannes Leitgeb, and submitted to the Board of Examiners in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of MSc in Logic at the Universiteit van Amsterdam. Date of the public defense: Members of the Thesis Committee: June 23rd, 2017 Dr. Maria Aloni Prof. Dr. Franz Berto Dr. Luca Incurvati Prof. DDr. Hannes Leitgeb Prof. Dr. Benedikt Löwe (chair) Prof. Dr. Frank Veltman ABSTRACT We investigate the related and important concepts of synonymy and hyperintension- ality (i.e. criteria for identity that are more fine-grained than necessary equivalence). We show how, for every language, validity uniquely determines a co-hyperinten- sionality relation (that ensures substitution salva veritate). The ordering of operators by their ability to discriminate sentences is not linear (e.g. truthmaking and necessity are incomparable). However, co-hyperintensionality is not a cognitively adequate individuation of content. Instead, we analyze cognitive synonymy (or likeness in cognitive role) concep- tually via defeasible rules, algorithmically via logic programming, and neurally by constructing an appropriate neural network. This explains the contextual stability of synonymy (given by the rules) and its flexibility (some contexts defeat the rules). We introduce the notion of a scenario that has a representational component (like Fregean senses) and an interpretational component (like a possible world). Scenarios can be grounded, e.g., in neural networks, and they have a constructive notion of distance. We use them to provide a hyperintensional semantics including a counter- factual and belief and conceivability operators. This scenario framework allows reconstructing many notions of synonymy. We provide a logic for content identity in scenario semantics. We observe that it is incon- sistent to hold both (i) if no scenario distinguishes two sentences, they are identical in content, and (ii) content identity entails identity in subject matter. Scenario se- mantics satisfies (i) and Fine’s logic of analytic containment satisfies (ii), though it is not the most coarse-grained one above scenario semantics. A semantics with a content-granularity like analytic containment requires moving from scenarios to sets of scenarios. We conclude our investigation with a pluralistic conception of synonymy: because of the sheer number of notions of synonymy, and because it is the only way to reconcile the many opposing features of synonymy. iii ACKNOWLEDGMENTS First of all, I would like to thank my supervisors Franz and Hannes: Franz, thank you for your many helpful comments, for the inspiring meetings discussing the thesis, for your honest interest in my ideas, for encouraging me to further pursue this research, for inviting me to give a talk at your LoC seminar, for your academic support— and for so much more. Hannes, thank you for your astute remarks, for suggesting very helpful literature, for your fruitful questions, for the great conversations, and – especially – for accepting to supervise the thesis from abroad—this means a lot to me. Moreover, I would like to thank Michiel van Lambalgen for introducing me to logic programming, its neural implementation, and its fruitfulness in modeling cognitive phenomena—as well as for many other stimulating insights ranging from Kant, over the philosophy of spacetime, to large cardinals in set theory. Also, I would like to thank Mark Jago and Greg Restall for their comments when I presented chapter2 in Franz’ seminar. And, in general, I would like to thank the audiences at that seminar and at the 2017 Logik zwischen Mathematik und Philosophie conference in Göttingen for their remarks and questions. Furthermore, I’m grateful to all those from whom I’ve learned during my studies. I’m glad I could spend two years at the ILLC. I enjoyed the open-minded and inspir- ing community of researchers and fellow students—and the fact that you can keep talking logic all night long without having to worry weird looks. Last but not least, I want to thank my family, my partner, and my friends for their great support during my studies—without you this thesis wouldn’t exist! v CONTENTS Abstract iii 1 Introduction1 1.1 General introduction.............................1 1.2 The background................................4 1.2.1 A very brief history of synonymy.............5 1.2.2 Intensionality and hyperintensionality...........6 1.2.3 Modern approaches to hyperintensionality.........8 1.2.4 A glance at synonymy in linguistics and cognitive science.... 10 1.3 The problem(s)................................ 11 1.3.1 The problem of co-hyperintensionality........... 12 1.3.2 Related problems................... 13 1.3.3 The Lewis-Stalnaker objection to hyperintensionality...... 13 1.4 Importance of hyperintensionality and synonymy............ 14 1.5 Outlook..................................... 15 1.5.1 The main contributions of this work............ 17 2 The structure of hyperintensionality 19 2.1 The problem of co-hyperintensionality................... 19 2.2 There is exactly one co-hyperintensionality relation........... 20 2.2.1 The notion of a language underlying the problem....... 21 2.2.2 Co-hyperintensionality for an operator........... 22 2.2.3 Co-hyperintensionality for a language........... 25 2.2.4 Putting the results into perspective............ 27 2.3 The structure of hyperintensional operators: The granularity order.. 28 2.4 Further philosophical consequences and open questions........ 32 2.4.1 Co-hyperintensionality is not cognitively adequate...... 32 2.4.2 A universal co-hyperintensionality relation?......... 34 2.4.3 Logical pluralism?.................. 35 2.4.4 Further ideas and open questions............. 36 2.5 Conclusion................................... 38 3 Cognitive synonymy 39 3.1 Cognitive synonymy: Conceptually.................... 40 3.1.1 A first approximation of cognitive synonymy........ 40 3.1.2 What kind of content does cognitive synonymy individuate?... 41 vii 3.1.3 The agent-based and generic knowledge base........ 42 3.1.4 An informal criterion for cognitive synonymy........ 44 3.2 Cognitive synonymy: Algorithmically................... 45 3.2.1 Logic programming.................. 46 3.2.2 A logico-algorithmic individuation of cognitive role...... 49 3.3 Cognitive synonymy: Neurally....................... 51 3.3.1 Neural implementation of logic programming........ 51 3.3.2 Some further comments................ 59 3.3.3 Neural individuation of cognitive role........... 59 4 Scenarios 61 4.1 Describing scenarios............................. 61 4.1.1 Defining scenarios.................. 61 4.1.2 The structure of the class of scenarios: Accessibility relations... 63 4.1.3 The structure of the class of scenarios: Pseudometric...... 64 4.1.4 The structure of the class of scenarios: Negligible sets..... 66 4.1.5 Grounding scenarios................. 66 4.1.6 Comparing scenarios................. 67 4.2 Semantics with scenarios........................... 68 4.2.1 Defining the semantics................. 68 4.2.2 Describing the notions of validity............. 73 4.2.3 The counterfactual in the semantics............ 78 5 Notions of synonymy 81 5.1 A zoo of notions of synonymy........................ 81 5.2 Characterizing content identity....................... 85 5.2.1 A sound and complete logic for strict synonymy....... 86 5.2.2 Related systems................... 89 5.3 Something paradoxical about synonymy.................. 90 5.3.1 Characterizing Fine’s analytic containment (AC)....... 91 5.3.2 Move on up: From strict synonymy to analytic synonymy.... 93 5.3.3 Resolving the paradox................. 95 5.4 Pluralism about synonymy......................... 95 Appendix 99 A More on knowledge bases.......................... 99 B Outsourced proofs.............................. 100 B.1 Proof of the replacement rule.............. 100 B.2 Proof of the theorem characterizing AC........... 100 B.3 Proof of the theorem characterizing super strict synonymy.... 102 B.4 Proof of the “semantics with sets of scenarios” theorem..... 104 Bibliography 107 viii 1st Chapter INTRODUCTION We start with a broad and informal introduction to the topic of the thesis, including a description of the perplexing phenomenon of synonymy. Then we provide the background for our investigation of synonymy and hyper- intensionality. This includes a brief history of synonymy and a characterization of the concept of hyperintensionality, also indicating why it is tightly linked to synonymy. Moreover, we sketch existing approaches to provide a hyperinten- sional notion of meaning—that is, a notion of meaning according to which some necessarily equivalent sentences still can differ in meaning. Next, we outline the main open problems of hyperintensionality and mention why they are important. Finally, we summarize what we will do in this thesis including a list of its main contributions. 1.1 General introduction We give a broad and informal introduction to the topic of the thesis. The focus is not on precision and completeness but on “giving a feel” for the topic. One of the big questions in philosophy is: What is meaning? More specific sub- questions include: What is the meaning of words and sentences? Is “the meaning” of a sentence an entity? And if so, is it something like a mind-independent abstract
Recommended publications
  • Within the Sphere of Analytic Philosophical Tradition, We Read Quine As a Critique. His Theory of Naturalized Epistemology Actua
    CHAPTER FOUR ANTI-NATURALISM AND ANTI- REDUCTIONISM: A DEBATE BETWEEN QUINE AND KANT AND QUINE AND CARNAP Within the sphere of analytic philosophical tradition, we read Quine as a critique. His theory of naturalized epistemology actually hinges on his very interpretation of meaning. Besides, being a critique, Quine involves in conflict with other well-known philosophical theories previously developed by original philosophers, such as, Kant, Carnap and Chomsky. In this sequel, we propose to analyze and examine Quine‟s debate with other philosophers. Quine, while developing his theory of meaning, criticizes Kant‟s well-established distinction between analytic and synthetic judgments. He then criticizes the reductionism of Rudolf Carnap. Accordingly, this sequel may be segmented into two sub-sections. In Section One, an attempt will be made to show in what sense Kant‟s distinction between analytic and synthetic judgment has appeared to Quine as the First Dogma of empiricism. In Section Two, an attempt will be made to examine and explicate in what sense Carnap‟s reductionism appeared as the Second Dogma of empiricism to Quine. SECTION ONE ANTI-NATURALISM: A DEBATE BETWEEN QUINE AND KANT Quine in his “Two Dogmas of Empiricism” appeared in The Philosophical Review in 1951 raised some serious philosophical issues that would go against Kant as well as Carnap. According to Quine, Kant is responsible to create a philosophical dogma that would lead the distinction between analytic and synthetic. In this section, an attempt would be made to explore the root of 133 the debate between Kant and Quine regarding First Philosophy. In his paper Quine challenges two doctrines which are directly or indirectly linked to Logical Positivism.
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophical Review
    Philosophical Review Main Trends in Recent Philosophy: Two Dogmas of Empiricism Author(s): W. V. Quine Source: The Philosophical Review, Vol. 60, No. 1 (Jan., 1951), pp. 20-43 Published by: Duke University Press on behalf of Philosophical Review Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/2181906 . Accessed: 19/01/2011 11:47 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at . http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use. Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at . http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=duke. Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission. JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. Duke University Press and Philosophical Review are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to The Philosophical Review. http://www.jstor.org TWO DOGMAS OF EMPIRICISM' M ODERN empiricismhas been conditionedin large part by two dogmas.
    [Show full text]
  • Willard Van Orman Quine: the Analytic/Synthetic Distinction
    Willard Van Orman Quine: The Analytic/Synthetic Distinction Willard Van Orman Quine was one of the most well-known American “analytic” philosophers of the twentieth century. He made significant contributions to many areas of philosophy, including philosophy of language, logic, epistemology, philosophy of science, and philosophy of mind/psychology (behaviorism). However, he is best known for his rejection of the analytic/synthetic distinction. Technically, this is the distinction between statements true in virtue of the meanings of their terms (like “a bachelor is an unmarried man”) and statements whose truth is a function not simply of the meanings of terms, but of the way the world is (such as, “That bachelor is wearing a grey suit”). Although a contentious thesis, analyticity has been a popular explanation, especially among empiricists, both for the necessity of necessary truths and for the a priori knowability of some truths. Thus, in some contexts “analytic truth,” “necessary truth,” and “a priori truth” have been used interchangeably, and the analytic/synthetic distinction has been treated as equivalent to the distinctions between necessary and contingent truths, and between a priori and a posteriori (or empirical) truths. Empirical truths can be known only by empirical verification, rather than by “unpacking” the meanings of the terms involved, and are usually thought to be contingent. Quine wrestled with the analytic/synthetic distinction for years, but he did not make his thoughts public until 1950, when he delivered his paper, “The Two Dogmas of Empiricism” at a meeting of the American Philosophical Association. In this paper, Quine argues that all attempts to define and understand analyticity are circular.
    [Show full text]
  • Preserving Normativity in Epistemology: Quine's Thesis
    Master of Arts Research Essay 2011 Preserving Normativity in Epistemology: Quine’s Thesis Revisited Dioné Harley Supervisor: Prof Mark Leon The financial assistance of the National Research Foundation (NRF) towards this research is hereby acknowledged. Opinions expressed and conclusions arrived at, are those of the author and are not necessarily to be attributed to the NRF. 1 Abstract Quine‟s epistemology amounts to what has been called the replacement thesis, according to which epistemology becomes a part of science by being replaced by the latter. The most forceful criticism of the thesis asserts that this sort of replacement is not successful due to the fact that an essential element of any epistemological endeavour has been eliminated, namely, normativity. The normativity charge claims that due to the descriptive nature of Quine‟s thesis normativity cannot be said to feature in his account. To begin with, the notion of normativity will be clarified, and it will be seen that normativity is not a simple notion as it admits of various formulations. In speaking of normativity one could be speaking of empiricist norms, the norms of rationality, prescriptive normativity within the context of practical reasoning as well as descriptive normativity. Also, in developing a theory of knowledge it becomes apparent that one is engaging with various sorts of beliefs, all of which must be accommodated and which I will articulate. The possible defenses presented by proponents of the Quinean project aim to meet the normativity charge by demonstrating that the replacement thesis is indeed normative, and the success of these defenses will be assessed.
    [Show full text]
  • Two Dogmas of Empiricism1a
    Two Dogmas of Empiricism1a Willard Van Orman Quine Originally published in The Philosophical Review 60 (1951): 20-43. Reprinted in W.V.O. Quine, From a Logical Point of View (Harvard University Press, 1953; second, revised, edition 1961), with the following alterations: "The version printed here diverges from the original in footnotes and in other minor respects: §§1 and 6 have been abridged where they encroach on the preceding essay ["On What There Is"], and §§3-4 have been expanded at points." Except for minor changes, additions and deletions are indicated in interspersed tables. I wish to thank Torstein Lindaas for bringing to my attention the need to distinguish more carefully the 1951 and the 1961 versions. Endnotes ending with an "a" are in the 1951 version; "b" in the 1961 version. (Andrew Chrucky, Feb. 15, 2000) Modern empiricism has been conditioned in large part by two dogmas. One is a belief in some fundamental cleavage between truths which are analytic, or grounded in meanings independently of matters of fact and truths which are synthetic, or grounded in fact. The other dogma is reductionism: the belief that each meaningful statement is equivalent to some logical construct upon terms which refer to immediate experience. Both dogmas, I shall argue, are ill founded. One effect of abandoning them is, as we shall see, a blurring of the supposed boundary between speculative metaphysics and natural science. Another effect is a shift toward pragmatism. 1. BACKGROUND FOR ANALYTICITY Kant's cleavage between analytic and synthetic truths was foreshadowed in Hume's distinction between relations of ideas and matters of fact, and in Leibniz's distinction between truths of reason and truths of fact.
    [Show full text]
  • The Strategic Naturalism of Sandra Harding's Feminist Standpoint Epistemology
    University of South Florida Scholar Commons Graduate Theses and Dissertations Graduate School March 2018 The trS ategic Naturalism of Sandra Harding's Feminist Standpoint Epistemology: A Path Toward Epistemic Progress Dahlia Guzman University of South Florida, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarcommons.usf.edu/etd Part of the Epistemology Commons, and the Philosophy of Science Commons Scholar Commons Citation Guzman, Dahlia, "The trS ategic Naturalism of Sandra Harding's Feminist Standpoint Epistemology: A Path Toward Epistemic Progress" (2018). Graduate Theses and Dissertations. https://scholarcommons.usf.edu/etd/7626 This Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by the Graduate School at Scholar Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Graduate Theses and Dissertations by an authorized administrator of Scholar Commons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. The Strategic Naturalism of Sandra Harding’s Feminist Standpoint Epistemology: A Path Toward Epistemic Progress by Dahlia Guzman A dissertation submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy Department of Philosophy College of Arts and Sciences University of South Florida Major Professor: Alex Levine, Ph.D. Stephen Turner, Ph.D. Joanne Waugh, Ph.D. Wei Zhang, Ph.D. Date of Approval: February 22, 2018 Keywords: Quine, feminist philosophy of science, feminist epistemology, critical theory Copyright © 2018, Dahlia Guzman ACKNOWLEDGMENTS This dissertation is a culmination of sorts, but I believe it is more aptly described as another harvest for me. I’ve learned so much. Heartfelt thanks to Dr. Alex Levine for his good humor, hard work, and patience.
    [Show full text]
  • 1 Reading Quine's Claim That Definitional Abbreviations Create Synonymies Gary Ebbs Draft June 15, 2015 in Section 2 Of
    Reading Quine’s claim that definitional abbreviations create synonymies Gary Ebbs Draft June 15, 2015 In section 2 of “Two Dogmas of Empiricism” Quine claims that when we explicitly introduce a new, previously meaningless expression, As, to serve as an abbreviation for a longer, already meaningful expression, S, we thereby create a “transparent” synonymy between As and S. (Quine 1953a, p. 26) In sections 3 and 5 of “Two Dogmas”, Quine explains why he is skeptical of all other species of synonymy. According to H. P. Grice, P. F. Strawson, Paul Boghossian, Scott Soames, and many others, Quine’s claim that definitional abbreviations create synonymies is in tension with his skepticism about the notion of synonymy for other cases. I shall argue that this kind of criticism is based on a fundamental misunderstanding of Quine’s reasoning in “Two Dogmas.” 1. A first look at the context for Quine’s claim In section 1 of “Two Dogmas of Empiricism” Quine grants that first-order logical truths are analytic and asks how to extend this partial characterization of the set of analytic sentences to include such supposedly analytic sentences as “Bachelors are unmarried.” He accepts, provisionally, that a sentence is in the wider class if “it can be turned into a logical truth by putting synonyms for synonyms” (Quine 1953a, p. 23), but notes that this characterization of analyticity “lean[s] on a notion of ‘synonymy’ which is no less in need of clarification than analyticity itself.” (Quine 1953a, p. 23) In sections 2 and 3 of “Two Dogmas” Quine considers various ways of trying to clarify the relevant sense of the term ‘synonymy’ and its cognates, as these terms appear in his assumed, preliminary characterization of the wider class of analytic sentences.
    [Show full text]
  • Main Trends in Recent Philosophy: Two Dogmas of Empiricism Author(S): W
    Philosophical Review Main Trends in Recent Philosophy: Two Dogmas of Empiricism Author(s): W. V. Quine Reviewed work(s): Source: The Philosophical Review, Vol. 60, No. 1 (Jan., 1951), pp. 20-43 Published by: Duke University Press on behalf of Philosophical Review Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/2181906 . Accessed: 03/12/2011 12:12 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at . http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. Duke University Press and Philosophical Review are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to The Philosophical Review. http://www.jstor.org TWO DOGMAS OF EMPIRICISM' M ODERN empiricismhas been conditionedin large part by two dogmas. One is a belief in some fundamental cleavage between truths which are analytic, or grounded in meanings independently of matters of fact, and truth which are synthetic, or grounded in fact. The other dogma is reductionism: the belief that each meaningful statement is equivalent to some logical construct upon terms which refer to immediate experience. Both dogmas, I shall argue, are ill founded. One effect of abandoning them is, as we shall see, a blurring of the supposed boundary between speculative metaphysics and natural science. Another effect is a shift toward pragmatism.
    [Show full text]
  • Distinctive Synonymy in Translation Dictionaries 1. Introduction
    International Journal of Academic Research and Reflection Vol. 6, No. 3, 2018 ISSN 2309-0405 DISTINCTIVE SYNONYMY IN TRANSLATION DICTIONARIES BENSAFI DELLANI Kheira SERIR MORTAD Ilhem Abu Bakr Belkaid University Abu Bakr Belkaid University Tlemcen , ALGERIA. Tlemcen , ALGERIA. ABSTRACT Users of translation dictionaries often have problems to make the right lexical choice while translating source language form into another target language . This is mainly due to the lack of information needed to make the appropriate choice during the translation process because the translator , given its work, needs more than a repertoire of equivalents . The purpose of this paper is to solve some of the lexicography and translation issues by discussing the so- called distinctive synonymy and the advantage of its integration into bilingual lexicography. It is an attempt to propose a new bilingual synonym dictionary by developing an original methodology for the active dictionary designed solely and exclusively to the translator . The study concludes that both synonyms and equivalents are salient and relevant data categories in the translation dictionary and that introducing semantic distinction between close synonyms can thouroughly assist the translator in decision making. Therefore, this research opens up some interesting and still little-explored perspectives in bilingual lexicography. Keywords: Distinctive synonymy, translation dictionaries, bilingual lexicography, near synonyms, equivalents. 1. INTRODUCTION Distinctive synonymy is a linguistic phenomenon largely used in synonym dictionaries ( thesauruses) . The semantic distinction is the process of distinguishing between words which are so related and close in meaning or in applicability that it is hard to identify the slight difference between them . That is to say , the distinction process works on the relation of synonymy , it deals particularly with close synonyms that have in common the same main meaning ( e.g.
    [Show full text]
  • Re-Thinking Synonymy: Semantic Sameness and Similarity in Languages and Their Description Book of Abstracts
    Re-thinking synonymy: semantic sameness and similarity in languages and their description Book of Abstracts 28.-30.10.2010, Helsinki Table of Contents LIST OF PARTICIPANTS: ___________________________________________________________________________ 1 INVITED SPEAKERS _______________________________________________________________________________ 3 GEERAERTS DIRK_________________________________________________________________________________ 3 HASPELMATH MARTIN _____________________________________________________________________________ 4 LEVIN BETH ____________________________________________________________________________________ 5 SCIENTIFIC COMMITTEE___________________________________________________________________________ 6 ORGANIZING COMMITTEE ________________________________________________________________________ 6 WORKSHOP ON COMPUTATIONAL APPROACHES TO SYNONYMY _________________________________________ 7 GRAEME HIRST, KENTARO INUI AND STEDE MANFRED ________________________________________________________ 7 ABSTRACTS _____________________________________________________________________________________ 8 ANDERSSON MARTA ______________________________________________________________________________ 8 ANISHCHANKA ALENA, SPEELMAN DIRK AND GEERAERTS DIRK __________________________________________________ 9 ARPPE ANTTI AND DIVJAK DAGMAR ___________________________________________________________________ 11 BACKUS AD AND MOS MARIA _______________________________________________________________________ 13 BORIN LARS AND FORSBERG MARKUS
    [Show full text]
  • FROM a LOGICAL POINT of VIEW © Copyright 1953, 1961 by the President and Fellows of Harvard College
    FROM A LOGICAL POINl. OF VIEW @ Logico-Philosophical Essays Willard Van Orman Cluine Second Edition, revised HARPER TORCHBOOKS I • Harper & Row, Publishers New York, Hagerstown, San Francisco, London To my Mother and Father H. V. Q. - C. R. Q. FROM A LOGICAL POINT OF VIEW © Copyright 1953, 1961 by the President and Fellows of Harvard College Printed in the United States of America This book was first published in 1953 by Harvard University Press, with a second, revised, edition in 1961. It is here reprinted by arrangement. First HARPER TORCHBOOK edition published 1963 by Harper & Row, Publishers, Incorporated New York and Evanston library of Congress catalog card number: 61-15277 76777879 80 20191817161514 0 CO INTENTS I. On what there is II. Two dogmcrs of empiricism 20 Ill. The problern of meaning in linguistics 47 IV. Identity, os1·ension, and hypostasis 65 v. New foundj:itions for mathematical logic 80 VI. Logic and the reification of universals 102 VII. Notes on th•! theory of reference 130 VIII. Reference and modcility 139 IX. Meaning an1d existenticil inference 160 Origins of 1he essays 169 Bibliographical references 171 Index 179 v FOREWORD TO THE SECOND EDITION The principal revision affects pages 152-159, on the contro­ versial topic of modal logic. A point that was made in those pages underwent radical extension on page 198 of my Word and Object (New York, 1960) ; and lately the situation has fur­ ther clarified itself, thanks in part to a current doctoral disserta­ tion by my student Dagfinn F1!1llesdal. These revised pages embody the resulting assessment of the situation.
    [Show full text]
  • Arguments for an Alternative Account of Analyticity
    ARGUMENTS FOR AN ALTERNATIVE ACCOUNT OF ANALYTICITY By Copyright 2009 Clark Alan Sexton Submitted to the graduate degree program in Philosophy and the Graduate Faculty of the University of Kansas in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy. ________________________________ Chairperson* ________________________________ ________________________________ ________________________________ ________________________________ Date Defended________________________________ The Dissertation Committee for Clark Alan Sexton certifies that this is the approved version of the following dissertation: ARGUMENTS FOR AN ALTERNATIVE ACCOUNT OF ANALYTICITY Committee: ________________________________ Chairperson* _______________________________ _______________________________ _______________________________ _______________________________ Date approved:_______________________ ii ARGUMENTS FOR AN ALTERNATIVE ACCOUNT OF ANALYTICITY ABSTRACT This dissertation presents an alternative account of analyticity, as well as arguments for that account. Although an analysis and interpretation of previous accounts of analyticity are presented, the focus is on the analysis of, and the arguments for a solution to, the philosophical problem of the existence of analyticities. The consideration of classical and contemporary texts provides a context for the alternative account of analyticity presented, and the analysis of the arguments against previous accounts of analyticity serve to demonstrate both the need for an alternative account and
    [Show full text]