Cavell, Skepticism, and the Ordinary Mind by Eric Joseph Ritter

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Cavell, Skepticism, and the Ordinary Mind by Eric Joseph Ritter Cavell, Skepticism, and the Ordinary Mind By Eric Joseph Ritter Dissertation Submitted to the Faculty of the Graduate School of Vanderbilt University in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY in Philosophy August 9th, 2019 Nashville, Tennessee Copyright © 2019 by Eric Joseph Ritter All Rights Reserved ii For my friends – Not an equal part to each, but for each the whole. iii ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS Professor Larry May’s consistent feedback on this project have left both noticeable and unnoticeable traces in every chapter. His directness, support, and practical wisdom have been invaluable. At several key moments over the life of this project, Professor David Wood has renewed my conviction in philosophy as a worthwhile – if necessarily never finished – humanistic undertaking, over meals, coffee, and conversation in Nashville, Woodbury, and Berlin, Germany. I am deeply grateful to Professor Kelly Oliver for our intermittent philosophical conversations and her steady support of my work and professional success. She has made graduate school more livable for many, many students in the Vanderbilt philosophy department, including myself. My thanks to Professor Jim Conant of the University of Chicago for sponsoring my trip to the philosophy department, and the Center for German Philosophy in particular, at the University of Chicago during the spring of 2019, where I edited significant parts of this dissertation, and for his support of my work more generally. For Professor Tyler Roberts, of Grinnell College, the first professor of philosophy from whom I learned philosophy, for his feedback on the fourth chapter, for conversations this past summer, and for introducing me to Stanley Cavell in his Philosophy of Religion seminar over eight years ago at that abolitionist school in Iowa. And I am deeply grateful to Professor Stephen Mulhall, of Oxford University, UK, for his interest in this project and for joining the dissertation committee at such a late stage. His books and articles on Cavell are sources of inspiration for me and their influence is, I think, apparent. Conversations with Cathleen Cavell about her late husband’s life and work and her support of my philosophical scholarship more generally have been extremely encouraging. I hope I can do justice to Stanley Cavell’s philosophy when, from his study in Brookline this summer, Cathleen and I begin a labor of love: organizing Cavell’s texts, letters, and papers for future scholars. I am grateful to Sabeen Ahmed for her painstaking edits on several chapters and on the bibliography, as well as for her loving encouragement throughout much of this process. She has walked next to me, at her own pace, throughout this project; her thoughtfulness and influence are evident throughout. Wout Cornelissen reminded me, when I needed reminding, that I had something to say. Robert Engleman and Sarah Gorman read and gave feedback on parts of this dissertation, and Liz Fiss and Jonathan Bremer were always supportive and did much to make this possible. Chad Attenborough always listened, Julie was bright, Michael was cool, and my brother, Sam Ritter, was there for me always, including at each moment of existential panic. Ashur and Gabe did nothing, but also somehow, it seems to me, made everything happen. Finally, Professor John Lachs’s patience, practicality, and support of my individual intellectual development through dozens of phone conversations and in-person meetings over two years have sustained this project. His pedagogical world is, among other things (and like Cavell’s) a world of plurality. The best I can think of to thank Lachs, since he needs so little but has given so much, is to promise to carry some of the pedagogical gifts he has provided and pass them along to others. iv TABLE OF CONTENTS Page DEDICATION………………………………...…………………………………………………………………….v ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS ………………………………...…………………………………………..………vi INTRODUCTION …………………...……………………………………………..…………………..............1 Cavell’s Philosophical Biography …………………...………………………………………...............1 The Knowledge of Pain and Skepticism of Other Minds ...……………………………………. 4 Skepticism as a Human Difficulty ...……………………………………. …………………….….....10 Cavell and the Limits of Philosophical Authority………………………………………………...12 Cavell and “The New Wittgenstein” (in America) …………………………………………….....14 Framing of the Dissertation ……………………………………………………………………………...18 Brief Outline of the Chapters …………………………………………………………………..…….....20 Chapter I. Cavell, Wittgenstein, Meaning, and Use…………………………………………………..............25 Words and Tools……………………. …………………...……………………………………….............28 Conant’s Cavell on Meaning and Use ...………………………………………………………….…. 36 Conant and Cavell on Language Idling and “Metaphysical” Uses of Language….….....44 Projection and Intersubjectivity………………………………………………..............................48 Conclusion ………………………………………………………………………………………….……….....53 II. Towards Leading the Correspondence Theory of Meaning Back to Earth: Cavell at Criticism………………………………………………………………………..……………….………........55 Language (and) Games…………………………..……..……………………………………….............56 The Augustinian Picture of the Essence of Language ...…………..……………………….…..61 Concept Use as a Technique or Practice ….…................................................................72 Cavell at Criticism…………………………………………………………………………………..…........81 III. Cavell and the Mixed Legacy of Skepticism….…........................................................84 Affeldt and Mulhall on Linguistic Normativity …………………………..…………….............87 Cavellian Skepticism – an “Unconventional Idiom” ...…………..……………………………..91 Skepticism’s Chagrin ….….............................................................................................95 Non-Criterial Differences and Other Invitations to Skepticism……….……………..….....98 Conclusion – and Return to Mulhall/Affeldt Debate……….……………..…....................105 v IV. The Threat of Skepticism in Early Modern Philosophy: Thinking with Cavell…….110 Introduction …………………………..…………….................................................................110 Setting the Skeptical Scene… ...…………..……………………………………………………………118 The “Dialectical Space” of Skepticism ........................................................................121 Hobbes’s Metaphysics of Space and Time ……….……………..……………………………......123 Conant’s Kantian and Cartesian Features of Skepticism in Hobbes’s Metaphysics About Space and Time………………………………………………………………………………127 Cause and Effect as the “Bridge” Across Kantian and Cartesian Gaps…………………..135 Concluding Thoughts……….……………..……………………………………………………….….....139 V. Conclusion: Cavell’s Philosophy the Day After Tomorrow……….……………….…….....142 REFERENCES………..……………………...............................................................................149 vi INTRODUCTION Cavell’s Philosophical Biography Stanley Cavell’s philosophical methodology and biography begins with J.L. Austin, whose work revealed to Cavell the depth and contingency of embedded practical commitments and activities within ordinary language, and in the work of the later Wittgenstein. In a lifelong, evolving, and well-known set of readings of Wittgenstein’s Philosophical Investigations, Cavell claimed that the Investigation’s main theme was an encounter with temptations toward skepticism or metaphysics; and that the voices or interlocutors which comprise the chorus of the Investigations are in various stages of yielding to that skeptical temptation, including acquiescing to paradox. And then there is Wittgenstein’s voice, Cavell thinks, which stands out above the rest. It is not a voice which defeats skepticism, but one which, over the course of that text, exemplifies a responsiveness to each particular temptation toward skepticism when and as it emerges from a human being, seeking “to discover the specific plight of mind and circumstance within which a human being gives voice to his condition.”1 Throughout his work, as Cavell’s philosophical writings progressed away from traditional scholarship on Wittgenstein, Austin, and ordinary language philosophy, and into deeply original philosophical essays on themes and figures unfamiliar to most philosophers, Cavell continued to foreground a Wittgensteinian responsiveness to particular skeptical or metaphysical temptations as a particular human being gives voice to them. And in this vein, Cavell gradually became frustrated, even despairing, of what 1 Stanley Cavell, “Knowing and Acknowledging,” in Must We Mean What We Say (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 2001), 238-266. 1 he perceived to be the tendency of academic philosophers to engage in what he came to call a chronic “flight from the ordinary.” By the late 1970s and certainly by the mid 1980s, Cavell had begun to suggest that apparently different but interrelated “areas” of philosophy such as philosophy of language, mind, and perception were permeated with what he called skepticism; and so Cavell, like Rorty, turned away from many recognizable philosophical problems. In a sense, this dissertation is an attempt to understand Cavell’s turn away from the sort of problems he thought were hopelessly entangled with skepticism, but also to understand Cavell’s return to something he thought was worth calling philosophy, a way of (philosophical) thinking that acknowledged the inescapable threat of skepticism. So, what is skepticism, for Cavell? As is well known, in the process of tackling traditional skeptical problems of other mind and external world skepticism, the concept of skepticism undergoes
Recommended publications
  • An Autobiography
    An Autobiography Richard Ryder Devon, England I recoiled at the obvious sufferings of my prey I was chided for being silly. Although it was considered the proper thing to do to kill an animal "cleanly" and to put wounded creatures "out of their misery" swiftly, the basic right of humankind to dominate and tyrannise was not to be challenged. Killing and exploiting animals was something that made a man a man. Yet I never really doubted that we sentients were all alike-and lowe that mainly to my mother. My father, one of the last of the old sort of English squire, owned thousands of acres of willdlife-rich moorland, forestry and farmland, all of which had been Long before I began campaigning against speciesism in the family for generations. He wore the same huge in 1969 I had felt on the same wavelength as other hobnailed shoes and leather-patched tweed jackets sentients. I shared my bedroom with a monkey for decade after decade and ruled his estate wilb a feudal about three years. His name was Bimbo and he had fmnness and sense of duty. He was sometimes fierce been "rescued" by my mother from a pet shop. She but always fair. went on to rescue others, accommodating them in a As part of the "privileged" upper four percent, I was spacious cage in the garden and taking some of them sent to boys' boarding schools between eight and for walks in the woods. We used to have a photograph eighteen where I was caned and bullied and forced to of a South American capuchin swinging at the top of undergo almost continuous physical and mental a British larch tree! hardship.
    [Show full text]
  • Stanley Cavell's Method of Reading Literature1
    Estetyka The Polish Journal i Krytyka of Aesthetics 43 (4/2016), DOI: 10.19205/43.16.3 Magdalena Filipczuk* “Epistemological Reading”: Stanley Cavell’s Method of Reading Literature1 Abstract Not many readers will recognize Disowning Knowledge: Seven Plays of Shakespeare by Stanley Cavell as either a piece of philosophical writing or literary criticism, so it may be useful to ask what method Cavell uses to read literature, what are the main features of his approach, and whether he has a coherent view on what reading lit‑ erature means. I examine Cavell’s interdisciplinary eclecticism, the feature which makes his work so original, and I describe his moving away from the British and American analytic tradition in which he was trained to other sources of inspiration, especially Thoreau. I also stress the important fact that Cavell does not avoid auto‑ biographical motifs in his writings, the style of which derives to some extent from the Jewish tradition of storytelling. In his writings Cavell declares his adherence to an ahistorical approach, maintaining that in a sense philosophy is trans‑histor‑ ical. In many of his books the central issue is the challenge that skepticism poses, and he endeavors to make a convincing case against it. Although Cavell’s work cov‑ ers a broad range of interests, including tragedy and literature, as well as Roman‑ tic poetry, Shakespeare, Henry James and Samuel Beckett, I try to answer the ques‑ tion of why his analyses of skepticism in literature focus especially on the works of Shakespeare. Key words Stanley Cavell, method of reading literature, literature, skepticism, literary criticism, analytic philosophy * InstituteEmail: [email protected] of Philosophy Jesuit University Ignatianum in Kraków, Poland ‑ 1 This article is a modified version of my paper delivered during the Interna tional Congress on Hermeneutics Today: Philosophers on Literature, April 20–22, 2016, Granada (Spain).
    [Show full text]
  • Book Review: Stanley Cavell. <Em>
    Early Theatre 8.1 (2005) Book Reviews Stanley Cavell. Disowning Knowledge in Seven Plays by Shakespeare. Updated edition. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2003. Pp 250. The first essay in this collection, ‘Disowning Knowledge in King Lear,’ was written in 1967 and published in 1969 as the culminating exemplification of the philosophical argument of Stanley Cavell’s Must We Mean What We Say?1 It was subsequently republished in 1987, as the first essay of the original edition of Disowning Knowledge, Cavell’s magisterial reading of Shakespeare’s tragic drama. 1967, 1987, 2003. These dates tell the story of an extraordinary philosopher and critic whose work has never been part of mainstream Shakes- peare scholarship, but which exposes the blind spots and evasions of that criticism while at the same time anticipating many of its fruitful directions. Amongst scholars of literature the pioneering essay on King Lear is probably Cavell’s best known work. It most clearly sets the stage for Cavell’s abiding, some might say obsessive, interest in the equally alluring and incapacitating role of scepticism in human beings’ relations to each other and the world in which they live. For Cavell, Shakespeare’s tragedies are the most complete working out, in all its cunning subtleties and alluring perversities, of the sceptical alienation from the world and from the love of others. The sceptic – who can be anybody – demands certainty beyond the human capacity or condition to provide it. He thereby loses or rejects the world, which appears to lie beyond his fastidious requirement for absolute knowledge. (I use the masculine pronoun deliberately, for Cavell’s later essays suggests that scepti- cism may be gender specific.) Cavell argues, via Shakespeare’s tragedies, that scepticism with regard to our possible knowledge of objects in the world takes a peculiarly debilitating form when it inhabits human relationships.
    [Show full text]
  • Stanley Cavell's Wittgenstein
    WITTGENSTEIN Stanley Cavell’s Wittgenstein By James Conant HE AIM OF THIS PAPER IS TO PROVIDE AN OVERVIEW OF ONE ASPECT OF Stanley Cavell’s reading of Wittgenstein: his interpretation of Wittgenstein’s teaching concerning the relation between meaning Tand use. After furnishing a rough overview of this aspect of Cavell’s reading of Wittgenstein, I shall attempt to bring into focus what is most distinctive and elusive about it by illustrating, by means of some examples drawn from commentators on Cavell’s work, how easy it can be to miss Cavell’s and— if Cavell is right about who Wittgenstein is—Wittgenstein’s point. Now Wittgenstein has become quite famous in recent years for putting forward something that gets called a “use-theory of meaning.” Wittgenstein writes: For a large class of cases—though not for all—in which we employ the word “meaning” it can be defined thus: the meaning of a word is its use in the language.1 If you look at commentaries on Wittgenstein’s work, you will find that commentators have wildly different understandings of what Wittgenstein is saying in this passage. Here is what Cavell says: “The meaning is the use” calls attention to the fact that what an expression means is a function of what it is used to mean or to say on specific occasions by human beings. [T]o trace the intellectual history of philosophy’s concentration on the meaning of particular words and sentences, in isolation from a systematic attention to their concrete uses would be a worthwhile undertaking.
    [Show full text]
  • Curriculum Vitae Michael Tooley
    CURRICULUM VITAE MICHAEL TOOLEY Education University of Toronto, 1959-64. B.A., 1964. Princeton University, 1964-67. Ph.D., 1968. Personal Date of birth: 17 March 1941 Place of birth: Toronto, Canada Married to Sylvia Tooley, with daughters Sandra and Suzanne, and grandchildren Anthony, Joshua, Donald, Joseph, and Sofia. Citizenship: American and Canadian. Academic Honors and Awards President, American Philosophical Association, Pacific Division, 2010-2011. Vice President, American Philosophical Association, Pacific Division, 2009-2010. The Cecil H. and Ida Green Honors Chair Professor, Texas Christian University, Spring, 2010 The John Dewey Lecture, "A Philosophical Journey," American Philosophical Association, Central Division, Chicago, February, 2009. College Professor of Distinction, Arts and Sciences, University of Colorado at Boulder, 2006- Faculty Fellowship. University of Colorado at Boulder, 2006-2007. Boulder Faculty Assembly Excellence in Research Award, 1998-1999. JSPS Invitation Fellowship for Research in Japan. Awarded by the Japan Society for the Promotion of Science, 1999. Fellow of the Australian Academy of the Humanities. President, Australasian Association of Philosophy, 1983-1984. Woodrow Wilson Dissertation Fellow, 1966-1967. Woodrow Wilson Fellow, 1964-1965. Most Recent Position Distinguished College Professor, Arts and Sciences, University of Colorado. 2006- University of Colorado, Philosophy Department: Professor, 1992–present, now retired. Previous Positions Bowling Green State University, Adjunct Professor, 2004-09. The Australian National University, Philosophy Program, Research School of Social Sciences: Senior Research Fellow, 1988-92; Senior Fellow, 1992. University of Western Australia, Philosophy Department: Professor, 1983-88; Head of Department, 1985-88. University of Miami, Philosophy Department: Associate Professor, 1981-82; Professor, 1982-83. 2 Wichita State University, Philosophy Department: Visiting Associate Professor, 1980-81.
    [Show full text]
  • Aesthetic Interpretation and the Claim to Community in Cavell
    CONVERSATIONS 5 Seeing Selves and Imagining Others: Aesthetic Interpretation and the Claim to Community in Cavell JON NAJARIAN Politics is aesthetic in principle. JACQUES RANCIÈRE From his early childhood, Stanley Cavell learned to tread carefully the intervening space between twin pillars: of aesthetic sensibility on the one hand, and political be- longing on the other. Early in his memoir Little Did I Know, Cavell establishes a set of differences between his mother and father that far exceed both gender and age (his father was ten years older than his mother), as he notes the starkly contrasting dis- pensations of their respective families: The artistic temperament of my mother’s family, the Segals, left them on the whole, with the exception of my mother and her baby brother, Mendel, doubt- fully suited to an orderly, successful existence in the new world; the orthodox, religious sensibility of my father’s family, the Goldsteins, produced a second generation—some twenty-two first cousins of mine—whose solidarity and se- verity of expectation produced successful dentists, lawyers, and doctors, pillars of the Jewish community, and almost without exception attaining local, some of them national, some even a certain international, prominence.1 From his mother’s family, Cavell would inherit the musical sensibility that, had he not ventured into the world of academic philosophy, might have led him towards a career as a musician or in music. In his father’s family Cavell observes a religious belonging that, in the decades in which Cavell is raised, becomes morally inseparable from politi- $1. Cavell, Little Did I Know: Excerpts from Memory (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 2010), 3.
    [Show full text]
  • YEARBOOK of The
    YEARBOOK of the IRISH PHILOSOPHICAL SOCIETY Special Issue Humans and Other Animals Fealsúnacht Φ 2017/18 Edited by: Noel Kavanagh Cara Nine Noel Kavanagh 4 Elderwood, Philosophy Department of Humanities University College Cork Carlow College, St. Patrick’s Cork College St., Co. Cork Carlow, Co. Carlow IRELAND IRELAND E-mail: [email protected] E-mail: [email protected] Board of Editorial Advisors: Maeve Cooke (UCDublin) Richard Kearney (Boston College) William Desmond (KULeuven) Cynthia Macdonald (QUBelfast) John Dillon (TCDublin) Dermot Moran (UCDublin) John Hayes (MI Limerick) Graham Parkes (UCCork) Teresa Iglesias (UCDublin) Peter Simons (TCDublin) Markus Wörner (NUIGalway) The Yearbook of the Irish Philosophical Society is a publication of the Irish Philosophical Society. It publishes peer-reviewed articles on a bi-annual basis, often originating in the Society’s conferences, and shares the Society’s purpose of promoting philosophy in Ireland. Papers to be considered for publication should be sent to the General Editor, or to the Associate Editor at their respective addresses above. Please comply with the Society’s style guide available on the society’s website and include an abstract of c. 100 words. See, www.irishphilosophicalsociety.ie The price of the Yearbook to members of the Irish Philosophical Society is €10; to non-members: €25. Institutional membership and subscription can be arranged. Please contact: Katherine Furman (Honorary Secretary) 4 Elderwood, Philosophy University College Cork Co. Cork IRELAND Email: [email protected] The views and opinions expressed in the articles do not necessarily represent those of the editors. The articles published are indexed in the Philosopher’s Index.
    [Show full text]
  • Vulnerability and Human Rights Don Kulick
    1 VULNERABILITY AND HUMAN RIGHTS DON KULICK Fall Term 2018 Fridays 10-12 pm Vulnerability and human rights are intimately intertwined. Human rights advocates argue that rights must be extended to vulnerable populations, but what does vulnerability actually signify and entail? The idea of vulnerability is currently undergoing re-evaluation in philosophy, the social sciences and the humanities. From having been perceived as a condition from which subjects should be defended, rescued or liberated, vulnerability and passivity have increasingly come to be theorized as a position and experience that confronts us with the limits of understanding, empathy, ethics and theory. This course will discuss work that attempts to engage with vulnerability as a challenge that can guide us towards new ways of thinking about and engaging with the world. COURSE REQUIREMENTS 1. Active class participation and presentations. Throughout the course, you will be asked at various points to prepare introductions to the literature. The point of these introductions, which must last no longer than 5 minutes, is to quickly summarize the material and open the discussion to topics that you feel merit attention. These presentations will form part of your final grade. 2. A total of four critical/reaction papers posted on the course site. You may choose whichever four weeks you like. The papers should be about one page in length, at 16 pt. line spacing, Times New Roman font. They may deal with any questions the readings raise for you, such as queries or criticisms you have of the authors' method or argument; connections to other readings; disparities among the readings; implications of the readings for important issues in anthropology or ethnography, and the like.
    [Show full text]
  • Brigid Brophy Anniversary Conference 9Th-10Th October 2015
    Brigid Brophy Anniversary Conference 9th-10th October 2015 Avenue Campus, University of Northampton, England 2 Brigid Brophy Anniversary Conference 2015 University of Northampton, England 9th-10th October 2015: To commemorate the twentieth anniversary of the death of Brigid Brophy (1929-1995) and the fiftieth anniversary of her article ‘The Rights of Animals’, published in the Sunday Times on 10th October 1965 (and later collected in the ground-breaking 1971 anthology Animals, Men and Morals), the School of the Arts at the University of Northampton is delighted to host a two-day conference to celebrate all aspects of Brophy’s literary career, as well as her leading contribution to animal rights, vegetarianism, anti- vivisectionism, humanism, feminism and her advocacy of the Public Lending Right. Organiser: Professor Richard Canning Contact: [email protected] 3 Friday 9th October: Brigid Brophy: Novelist, Biographer, Dramatist and Cultural Thinker 9-9.30 Registration & Morning Tea and Coffee 9.30-11.00 Welcome & Plenary Lecture Philip Hensher - ‘Outer Crust and Inner Turmoil: the principles of fiction, by a beginner’ 11.00-11.30 Tea and Coffee 11.30-13.00 Panel Session 1: Brigid Brophy, Novelist and Biographer Jonathan Gibbs, ‘The Erotics of Flesh and Sex in the Sixties’ Robert McKay, ‘Brigid Brophy's Pro-animal Fictions’ Peter Parker, ‘Prancing Novelist and Black and White: Experiments in Biography’ 13.00-14.00 Lunch 14.00-15.00 Plenary Lecture Carole Sweeney - ‘“Why this rather than that?” The Delightful Perversity of Brigid Brophy’ 15.00-15.30 Tea and Coffee 4 15.30-17.00 Panel Session 2: Brigid Brophy, Dramatist and Cultural Thinker Michael Bronski, ‘Sex, Death, and the Transfiguration of Queerness’ Michael Caines, ‘“I have been a dramatist since I was six”: The theatrical Brigid Brophy’ Pamela Osborn, ‘“Stop.
    [Show full text]
  • Editors' Introduction
    Editors’ Introduction Extending the Boundaries of “The Ethical” I also think that quite clearly, even if it is not as simple as that, even if animals are not considered as human beings, the ethical extends to living beings. I really think so. —Emmanuel Levinas, “The Animal Interview” Since the topic of Levinas and animals has by now received rather a lot of attention, the reader may be wondering why we felt compelled to compile this volume of essays. The short answer is that though Levinas’s neglect of animals in his philosophical work has already been subject to repeated criticism,1 the majority of commentators and critics still write as though Levinas’s “profound anthropocentrism and humanism”2 rather than a serious flaw in need of remedy, were entirely justified. Most take it for granted that it is not possible for the Other to be anything other than human. Only posterity knows whether this will ever change, though it looks unlikely that it will. This is not due to any deficiencies in the arguments for including animals within the scope of Levinas’s ethics. It is probably because the force behind the conviction that humans are the center of the moral universe is more affective than philosophical, and wells from the same source as what Freud called “the universal narcissism of men.” But even if a single collection of essays like this one is unlikely to make much of a difference here, it behooves us as academics to keep reminding ourselves that the animal question is a live one and as long as an ethics like Levinas’s does not take the question into account, then so much the worse for it philosophically.
    [Show full text]
  • How Ought We to Live with Nonhuman Animals? Peter Singerâ•Žs Answer: Animal Liberation Part I
    BETWEEN THE SPECIES Issue IX August 2009 http://cla.calpoly.edu/bts/ How Ought We To Live With Nonhuman Animals? Peter Singer’s Answer: Animal Liberation Parts I & II (two papers) PART I Lesley McLean University of New England, Armidale NSW Australia Email address: [email protected] Between the Species, IX, August 2009, http://cla.calpoly.edu/bts/ Abstract In this paper and the next I discuss Peter Singer’s approach to answering the question of how one ought to live with nonhuman animals. In the first paper I situate Singer’s work within the larger historical context of moral concern for animals, looking at previous public consensus on the issue, its breakdown and its re-emergence with Singer in the 1970s. In the second paper, I take a closer look at Singer’s highly influential book, Animal Liberation (1975), and argue that as activist literature, his chapter on animal experimentation for example can be seen as morally persuasive in ways other than simply as an example of (the consequences) of speciesism. How I do this is to place Singer’s work side by side that of 19th century activist Francis Power Cobbe’s, in particular her pamphlet Light in Dark Places (1883), and examine their work against the criticisms from scientists defending the practice of animal experimentation. Between the Species, IX, August 2009, http://cla.calpoly.edu/bts/ Peter Singer played a key role in bringing a particular moral problem to light; he came to name this problem in a now famous philosophical treatise. Animal Liberation was first published as a review essay in The New York Review of Books (NYRB) and two years later, in 1975, as a full-length book published by the New York Review.
    [Show full text]
  • The Oxford Vegetarians - a Personal Account
    WellBeing International WBI Studies Repository 1982 The Oxford Vegetarians - A Personal Account Peter Singer Monash University Follow this and additional works at: https://www.wellbeingintlstudiesrepository.org/acwp_aafhh Part of the Animal Studies Commons, Other Anthropology Commons, and the Other Nutrition Commons Recommended Citation Singer, P. (1982). The Oxford Vegetarians - A personal account. International Journal for the Study of Animal Problems, 3(1), 6-9. This material is brought to you for free and open access by WellBeing International. It has been accepted for inclusion by an authorized administrator of the WBI Studies Repository. For more information, please contact [email protected]. y-- A.NRowan Editorial P. Singer Editorial s1xt1es. This particular event is described below by Peter Singer, one of the phil­ neglect of the interests of animals, gave me a lot to think about, but I was not about osophy students, whose life was changed as a result of his meeting with the "Oxford to change my diet overnight. Over the next two months Renata and I met Richard's Vegetarians." wife Mary and two other Canadian philosophy students, Roslind and Stanley Godlovitch, who had been responsible for Richard and Mary becoming vegetarians. Ros and Stan had become vegetarians a year or two earlier, before reaching Oxford. They had come to see our treatment of non human animals as analogous to the The Oxford Vegetarians- A Personal Account brutal exploitation of other races by whites in earlier centuries. This analogy they now urged on us, challenging us to find a morally relevant distinction between Peter Singer humans and nonhumans which could justify the differences we make in our treat­ ment of those who belong to our own species and those who do not.
    [Show full text]