Deleuze, Expressionism in Philosophy: Spinoza

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Deleuze, Expressionism in Philosophy: Spinoza Expressionism In Philosophy : Spinoza Translated by Martin Joughin Expressionism in Philosophy: Spinoza Gilles Deleuze ZONE BOOKS · NEW YORK 1992 © 1990 Urzone Inc. ZONE BOOKS 1226 Prospect Avenue Brooklyn, NY 11218 First Paperback Edition Fourth Printing, 2005 All rights reserved. No part of this book may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted in any form or by any means, including electronic, mechanical, photocopying, microfilming, recording, or otherwise (except for that copying permitted by Sections 107 and ro8 of the U.S. Copyright Law and except by reviewers for the public press) without written permission from the Publisher. Originally published in France as Spinoza et la probleme de I'expression. © 1968 Les Editions de Minuit Printed in the United States of America Distributed by The MIT Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts, and London, England Library of Congress Cataloging in Publication Data Deleuze, Gilles. [Spinoza et le probleme de l' expression. English] Expressionism in philosophy: Spinoza / Gilles Deleuze; translated by Martin Joughin. p. em. Translation of: Spinoza et le probleme de l' expression. Bibliography: p. Index ISBN 0-942299-51-5 (pbk.) r. Spinoza, Benedictus de, 1632-1677 -Contributions in concept of expression. 2. Expression. r. Title. B3999.E9D4513 1990 ' 199 -492-dc19 88-2o6o7 CIP Contents Translator's Preface 5 Introduction: The Role and Importance of Expression 13 PART ONE THE TRIADS OF SUBS TANCE Chapter I Numerical and Real Distinction 27 II Attribute as Expression 41 III Attributes and Divine Names 53 IV TheAbsolute 69 v Power 83 PART Tw o PARALLELISM AND IMMANENCE VI Expression in Parallelism 99 VII The Two Powers and theIdea of God 113 VIII Expression and Idea 129 IX Inadequacy 145 X Spinoza A9ainst Descartes 155 XI Immanence and the Historical Components of Expression 169 PART THREE THE THEORY OF FINITE MODES XII Modal Essence: Th e Passage from Infinite to Finite 191 XIII Modal Existence 201 XIV Wh at Can a Body Do? 217 XV Th e Three Orders and the Problem of Evil 235 XV I Th e Ethical Jtlsionof the World 255 XV II Common Notions 273 XV III To ward the ThirdKind of Knowledge 289 IXX Beatitude 303 Conclusion: Th e Th eory of Expression in Leibniz and Spinoza: Expressionism in Philosophy 321 Appendix 337 Notes 351 Translator's Notes 403 Index 429 Index of Te xtual References 437 Tr ans l at o r ' s P r e fa c e "We discover new ways of folding ...but we are always folding, unfolding, refolding": so ends Le Pli, Deleuze's latest book, on Leibniz, his first major historical study of a philosopher since the present book was published twenty years before. Here the main text doses: "It is hard, in the end, to say which is more impor­ tant: the differences between Leibniz and Spinoza in their evalua­ tion of expression; or their common reliance on this concept in founding a Postcartesian philosophy." Spinoza and Leibniz: two different expressions of "expressionism in philosophy," an expres­ sionism characterized in this book as a system of implicatio and explicatio, enfolding and unfolding, implication and explication, implying and explaining, involving and evolving, enveloping and developing. Two systems of universal fo lding: Spinoza's unfolded from the bare "simplicity" of an Infinity into which all things are ultimately fo lded up, as into a universal map that fo lds back into a single point; while Leibniz starts from the infinite points in that map, each of which enfolds within its infinitely "com­ plex" identity all its relations with all other such points, the unfolding of all these infinite relations being the evolution of a Leibnizian Universe. We are always involved in things and their implications and 5 EXPRESSIONISM IN PHILOSOPHY: SPINOZA developments, always ourselves developing in our bodily "enve­ lope," always explaining and implying. In Spinoza's Latin the distinctions between these various ways of being enfolded in a universal "complication" or complexity of things are home by the different contexts, mental, physical, and so on, in which implicare, explicare, and their derivatives are used. An English translator must often identifYthe implicit or explicit context of a particular use of one of these words and choose between, say, "imply," "impli­ cate," "enfold" - or "explain," "explicate," "unfold" - while Deleuze can retain in the French impliquer and expliquer several of the multiple senses of the Latin. The English language has developed differently from the French language. It has integrated Latin and Germanic roots, where French has unfolded directly from Latin. And this double system of English roots has allowed a splitting of senses in the language of "folding" itself, so that a Germanic vocabulary of "folds" must often be used in external, physical, contexts, and one can only talk of a universal "folding" of thoughts and things metaphorically. But what then becomes, in English translation, of Deleuze's attempt to organize Spinoza's Universe of internal Thought and external Extension in terms of an "unfolding" of which the distinction of "inner" and "outer" sides of things (ideas and bodies) is precisely the initial fold? The problem does not end with folding itself, but becomes more complex as the discussion extends to a general dynamics of Spin­ oza's system. Thus while the Latin comprehendere and the French comprendre cover both the "mental" sense of understanding (con­ taining or comprehending in thought) and the "physical" sense of comprising, including (containing, "properly speaking"), an English translator must either stretch his language beyond break­ ing point in an attempt to find some term (say, "comprehend") 6 TRANSLATOR'S PREFACE to cover both "sides" ofthe Latin or French word (everywhere substituting it, then, for "understand," "include," "comprise"), or simply ask the reader to try to constantly bear in mind that both sorts of containment are always to be understood as cor­ responding to a single "term" of the exposition, a term whose single grammar or expressive logic must be understood as organ­ izing the relations of the two English "sides" of the term through­ out the book. Then consider the Latin couple involvere and evolvere: an order of continuous "turning" inward and outward, involution and evo­ lution, rather than the elementary order of folds. The French envelopper covers both abstract and physical senses of "involving" and "enveloping" or (once more) "enfolding." (Just to compli­ cate matters further, the "envelope" which is the human body, later identified by Deleuze as the primary "fold" of internal sub­ jective space in external visible space, is linked in French to that order of folding by the fact that pli and enveloppe are two names for the "envelope" in which we enfold things we send through the postal system.) Is this aU a case ofa seductive metaphor being finallyneutral­ ized in English, once the implicit divergences of the "mental" and "physical" grammars of folding in Latin and French are at last made explicit? The metaphorical use of the language of"folding" would then amount (in a familiar analysis) to a partial transposi­ tion or translation of the logic of some term ("fold," say) from its true or proper linguistic context (all the sentences in which it can properly occur, with all their implications and explications) into some only partly or superficially similar "analogous" context. English might then be said to have developed in accordance with the Scholastic project of systematically distinguishing between the multiple senses of "equivocal" words, in order to construct a complete logic of true (as opposed to specious) implications 7 EXPRESSIONISM IN PHILOSOPHY: SPINOZA and explications - with the "technical" or formal use of words like "mode" (for example) properly distinguished from the impre­ cise informal use of the Latin modus or French mode, informally rendered in English as "manner," "way." Deleuze's reconstruction of Spinoza's system as a logic of expres­ sion is diametrically opposed to such a conception of "equivoca­ tion." Curley does not list (the "equivocal," "informal") exprimere as a "systematic". term in his glossary, and most commentators, as Deleuze notes in his Introduction, have also passed over this term in their reconstructions of the "logic" of the system. Deleuze's use of a disregarded term as the principal axis of his reconstruc­ tion of a philosophical or literary system had already character­ ized his earlier studies of Nietzsche and Proust (and has analogies with, say, Barthes' contemporary reading of Racine "in terms of" solar imagery, which so scandalized the Old Criticism). Indeed the language of "folding," and an insistence upon the "meta­ phorical" multiplicity of sense as prior to any projected unitary logical syntax, had already been applied in the 1964 reading of Proust. And in the Logic of Sense that followed the present study of Spinoza we find Deleuze inverting the traditional figures of metaphorical use as a partial transposition or translation of a given logic or grammar from its true context to some partly similar con­ text, and of metaphor or analogy "breaking down" at some point where the logic of the two contexts diverges. Words are there considered as "multiplicities" of sense, with no stable "home" context, no primary identity: as transferrable among multiple con­ texts to produce various patterns of relations between things as their essentially incomplete grammars or logics unfold in inter­ action with those of other words. Already in Difference and Repe­ tition, published jointly with the present book, it was precisely 8 TRANS LATOR'S PREFACE the "breakdown" of the traditional logic of identity that organ­ ized fundamental "divergences" or radical differences as the prime dimensionality or structure of unfolding experience. Deleuze's thought evolved from his first book (on Hmbe, 1953) down to the present work in a series of historical studies (on Nietzsche, Kant, Proust, Bergson and Sacher-Masoch).
Recommended publications
  • Participation and Predication in Plato's Middle Dialogues Author(S): R
    Participation and Predication in Plato's Middle Dialogues Author(s): R. E. Allen Source: The Philosophical Review, Vol. 69, No. 2, (Apr., 1960), pp. 147-164 Published by: Duke University Press on behalf of Philosophical Review Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/2183501 Accessed: 10/08/2008 14:32 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use. Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=duke. Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission. JSTOR is a not-for-profit organization founded in 1995 to build trusted digital archives for scholarship. We work with the scholarly community to preserve their work and the materials they rely upon, and to build a common research platform that promotes the discovery and use of these resources. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. http://www.jstor.org PARTICIPATION AND PREDICATION IN PLATO'S MIDDLE DIALOGUES* I PROPOSE in this paper to examine three closely related issues in the interpretation of Plato's middle dialogues: the nature of Forms, of participation, and of predication.
    [Show full text]
  • Overturning the Paradigm of Identity with Gilles Deleuze's Differential
    A Thesis entitled Difference Over Identity: Overturning the Paradigm of Identity With Gilles Deleuze’s Differential Ontology by Matthew G. Eckel Submitted to the Graduate Faculty as partial fulfillment of the requirements for the Master of Arts Degree in Philosophy Dr. Ammon Allred, Committee Chair Dr. Benjamin Grazzini, Committee Member Dr. Benjamin Pryor, Committee Member Dr. Patricia R. Komuniecki, Dean College of Graduate Studies The University of Toledo May 2014 An Abstract of Difference Over Identity: Overturning the Paradigm of Identity With Gilles Deleuze’s Differential Ontology by Matthew G. Eckel Submitted to the Graduate Faculty as partial fulfillment of the requirements for the Master of Arts Degree in Philosophy The University of Toledo May 2014 Taking Gilles Deleuze to be a philosopher who is most concerned with articulating a ‘philosophy of difference’, Deleuze’s thought represents a fundamental shift in the history of philosophy, a shift which asserts ontological difference as independent of any prior ontological identity, even going as far as suggesting that identity is only possible when grounded by difference. Deleuze reconstructs a ‘minor’ history of philosophy, mobilizing thinkers from Spinoza and Nietzsche to Duns Scotus and Bergson, in his attempt to assert that philosophy has always been, underneath its canonical manifestations, a project concerned with ontology, and that ontological difference deserves the kind of philosophical attention, and privilege, which ontological identity has been given since Aristotle.
    [Show full text]
  • Aristotle on Predication
    DOI: 10.1111/ejop.12054 Aristotle on Predication Phil Corkum Abstract: A predicate logic typically has a heterogeneous semantic theory. Sub- jects and predicates have distinct semantic roles: subjects refer; predicates char- acterize. A sentence expresses a truth if the object to which the subject refers is correctly characterized by the predicate. Traditional term logic, by contrast, has a homogeneous theory: both subjects and predicates refer; and a sentence is true if the subject and predicate name one and the same thing. In this paper, I will examine evidence for ascribing to Aristotle the view that subjects and predicates refer. If this is correct, then it seems that Aristotle, like the traditional term logician, problematically conflates predication and identity claims. I will argue that we can ascribe to Aristotle the view that both subjects and predicates refer, while holding that he would deny that a sentence is true just in case the subject and predicate name one and the same thing. In particular, I will argue that Aristotle’s core semantic notion is not identity but the weaker relation of consti- tution. For example, the predication ‘All men are mortal’ expresses a true thought, in Aristotle’s view, just in case the mereological sum of humans is a part of the mereological sum of mortals. A predicate logic typically has a heterogeneous semantic theory. Subjects and predicates have distinct semantic roles: subjects refer; predicates characterize. A sentence expresses a truth if the object to which the subject refers is correctly characterized by the predicate. Traditional term logic, by contrast, has a homo- geneous theory: both subjects and predicates refer; and a sentence is true if the subject and predicate name one and the same thing.
    [Show full text]
  • CHAPTER 1 and Unexemplified Properties, Kinds, and Relations
    UNIVERSALS I: METAPHYSICAL REALISM existing objects; whereas other realists believe that there are both exemplified CHAPTER 1 and unexemplified properties, kinds, and relations. The problem of universals I Realism and nominalism The objects we talk and think about can be classified in all kinds of Metaphysical realism ways. We sort things by color, and we have red things, yellow things, and blue things. We sort them by shape, and we have triangular things, circular things, and square things. We sort them by kind, and 0 Realism and nominalism we have elephants, oak trees, and paramecia. The kind of classification The ontology of metaphysical realism at work in these cases is an essential component in our experience of the Realism and predication world. There is little, if anything, that we can think or say, little, if anything, that counts as experience, that does not involve groupings of Realism and abstract reference these kinds. Although almost everyone will concede that some of our 0 Restrictions on realism - exemplification ways of classifying objects reflect our interests, goals, and values, few 0 Further restrictions - defined and undefined predicates will deny that many of our ways of sorting things are fixed by the 0 Are there any unexemplified attributes? objects themselves.' It is not as if we just arbitrarily choose to call some things triangular, others circular, and still others square; they are tri- angular, circular, and square. Likewise, it is not a mere consequence of Overview human thought or language that there are elephants, oak trees, and paramecia. They come that way, and our language and thought reflect The phenomenon of similarity or attribute agreement gives rise to the debate these antecedently given facts about them.
    [Show full text]
  • Predication and the Problem of Universals Catherine Legg
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Research Commons@Waikato Philosophical Papers Vol. 30, No. 2 (July 2001): 117-143 Predication and the Problem of Universals Catherine Legg Abstract: This paper contrasts the scholastic realists of David Armstrong and Charles Peirce. It is argued that the so-called 'problem of universals' is not a problem in pure ontology (concerning whether universals exist) as Armstrong construes it to be. Rather, it extends to issues concerning which predicates should be applied where, issues which Armstrong sets aside under the label of 'semantics', and which from a Peircean perspective encompass even the fundamentals of scientific methodology. It is argued that Peir ce's scholastic realism not only presents a more nuanced ontology (distinguishing the existent front the real) but also provides more of a sense of why realism should be a position worth fighting for. ... a realist is simply one who knows no more recondite reality than that which is represented in a true representation. C.S. Peirce Like many other philosophical problems, the grandly-named 'Problem of Universals' is difficult to define without begging the question that it raises. Laurence Goldstein, however, provides a helpful hands-off denotation of the problem by noting that it proceeds from what he calls The Trivial Obseruation:2 The observation is the seemingly incontrovertible claim that, 'sometimes some things have something in common'. The 1 Philosophical Writings of Peirce, ed. Justus Buehler (New York: Dover Publications, 1955), 248. 2 Laurence Goldstein, 'Scientific Scotism – The Emperor's New Trousers or Has Armstrong Made Some Real Strides?', Australasian Journal of Philosophy, vol 61, No.
    [Show full text]
  • The Problem: the Theory of Ideas in Ancient Atomism and Gilles Deleuze
    Duquesne University Duquesne Scholarship Collection Electronic Theses and Dissertations 2013 The rP oblem: The Theory of Ideas in Ancient Atomism and Gilles Deleuze Ryan J. Johnson Follow this and additional works at: https://dsc.duq.edu/etd Recommended Citation Johnson, R. (2013). The rP oblem: The Theory of Ideas in Ancient Atomism and Gilles Deleuze (Doctoral dissertation, Duquesne University). Retrieved from https://dsc.duq.edu/etd/706 This Immediate Access is brought to you for free and open access by Duquesne Scholarship Collection. It has been accepted for inclusion in Electronic Theses and Dissertations by an authorized administrator of Duquesne Scholarship Collection. For more information, please contact [email protected]. THE PROBLEM: THE THEORY OF IDEAS IN ANCIENT ATOMISM AND GILLES DELEUZE A Dissertation Submitted to the McAnulty College & Graduate School of Liberal Arts Duquesne University In partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy By Ryan J. Johnson May 2014 Copyright by Ryan J. Johnson 2014 ii THE PROBLEM: THE THEORY OF IDEAS IN ANCIENT ATOMISM AND GILLES DELEUZE By Ryan J. Johnson Approved December 6, 2013 _______________________________ ______________________________ Daniel Selcer, Ph.D Kelly Arenson, Ph.D Associate Professor of Philosophy Assistant Professor of Philosophy (Committee Chair) (Committee Member) ______________________________ John Protevi, Ph.D Professor of Philosophy (Committee Member) ______________________________ ______________________________ James Swindal, Ph.D. Ronald Polansky, Ph.D. Dean, McAnulty College & Graduate Chair, Department of Philosophy School of Liberal Arts Professor of Philosophy Professor of Philosophy iii ABSTRACT THE PROBLEM: THE THEORY OF IDEAS IN ANCIENT ATOMISM AND GILLES DELEUZE By Ryan J. Johnson May 2014 Dissertation supervised by Dr.
    [Show full text]
  • 2.2 Glock Et Al
    Journal for the History of Book Symposium: Analytical Philosophy Hans-Johann Glock, What is Analytic Philosophy? Volume 2, Number 2 Introduction Hans-Johann Glock..................... 1 Editor in Chief Mark Textor, King’s College London Commentaries Guest Editor Leila Haaparanta......................... 2 Mirja Hartimo, University of Helsinki Christopher Pincock....................6 Editorial Board Panu Raatikainen........................11 Juliet Floyd, Boston University Graham Stevens.......................... 28 Greg Frost-Arnold, Hobart and William Smith Colleges Ryan Hickerson, University of Western Oregon Replies Henry Jackman, York University Hans-Johann Glock..................... 36 Sandra Lapointe, McMaster University Chris Pincock, Ohio State University Richard Zach, University of Calgary Production Editor Ryan Hickerson Editorial Assistant Daniel Harris, CUNY Graduate Center Design Douglas Patterson and Daniel Harris ©2013 The Authors What is Analytic Philosophy? shall not be able to respond to all of the noteworthy criticisms and questions of my commentators. I have divided my responses ac- Hans-Johann Glock cording to commentator rather than topic, while also indicating some connections between their ideas where appropriate. Let me start by thanking the Journal for the History of Analytical Phi- losophy for offering me this opportunity to discuss my book What is Analytical Philosophy? (Cambridge, 2008). I am also very grateful Hans-Johann Glock for the valuable feedback from the contributors. And I thank both University of Zurich the journal and the contributors for their patience in waiting for [email protected] my replies. I was pleased to discover that all of my commentators express a certain sympathy with the central contention of my book, namely that analytic philosophy is an intellectual movement of the twentieth-century (with roots in the nineteenth and offshoots in the twenty-first), held together by family-resemblances on the one hand, ties of historical influence on the other.
    [Show full text]
  • How Analytic Philosophy Has Failed Cognitive Science
    How Analytic Philosophy Has Failed Cognitive Science Robert Brandom I. Introduction We analytic philosophers have signally failed our colleagues in cognitive science. We have done that by not sharing central lessons about the nature of concepts, concept-use, and conceptual content that have been entrusted to our care and feeding for more than a century. I take it that analytic philosophy began with the birth of the new logic that Gottlob Frege introduced in his seminal 1879 Begriffsschrift. The idea, taken up and championed to begin with by Bertrand Russell, was that the fundamental insights and tools Frege made available there, and developed and deployed through the 1890s, could be applied throughout philosophy to advance our understanding of understanding and of thought in general, by advancing our understanding of concepts—including the particular concepts with which the philosophical tradition had wrestled since its inception. For Frege brought about a revolution not just in logic, but in semantics. He made possible for the first time a mathematical characterization of meaning and conceptual content, and so of the structure of sapience itself. Henceforth it was to be the business of the new movement of analytic philosophy to explore and amplify those ideas, to exploit and apply them wherever they could do the most good. Those ideas are the cultural birthright, heritage, and responsibility of analytic philosophers. But we have not done right by them. For we have failed to communicate some of the most basic of those ideas, failed to explain their significance, failed to make them available in forms usable by those working in allied disciplines who are also professionally concerned to understand the nature of thought, minds, and reason.
    [Show full text]
  • Predication and the Problem of Universals Catherine Legg
    Philosophical Papers Vol. 30, No. 2 (July 2001): 117-143 Predication and the Problem of Universals Catherine Legg Abstract: This paper contrasts the scholastic realists of David Armstrong and Charles Peirce. It is argued that the so-called 'problem of universals' is not a problem in pure ontology (concerning whether universals exist) as Armstrong construes it to be. Rather, it extends to issues concerning which predicates should be applied where, issues which Armstrong sets aside under the label of 'semantics', and which from a Peircean perspective encompass even the fundamentals of scientific methodology. It is argued that Peir ce's scholastic realism not only presents a more nuanced ontology (distinguishing the existent front the real) but also provides more of a sense of why realism should be a position worth fighting for. ... a realist is simply one who knows no more recondite reality than that which is represented in a true representation. C.S. Peirce Like many other philosophical problems, the grandly-named 'Problem of Universals' is difficult to define without begging the question that it raises. Laurence Goldstein, however, provides a helpful hands-off denotation of the problem by noting that it proceeds from what he calls The Trivial Obseruation:2 The observation is the seemingly incontrovertible claim that, 'sometimes some things have something in common'. The 1 Philosophical Writings of Peirce, ed. Justus Buehler (New York: Dover Publications, 1955), 248. 2 Laurence Goldstein, 'Scientific Scotism – The Emperor's New Trousers or Has Armstrong Made Some Real Strides?', Australasian Journal of Philosophy, vol 61, No. 1 (March 1983), 40.
    [Show full text]
  • Some Ways of Being in Plato
    Binghamton University The Open Repository @ Binghamton (The ORB) The Society for Ancient Greek Philosophy Newsletter 12-1991 Some Ways of Being in Plato Allan Silverman The Ohio State University, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://orb.binghamton.edu/sagp Part of the Ancient History, Greek and Roman through Late Antiquity Commons, Ancient Philosophy Commons, and the History of Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Silverman, Allan, "Some Ways of Being in Plato" (1991). The Society for Ancient Greek Philosophy Newsletter. 200. https://orb.binghamton.edu/sagp/200 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by The Open Repository @ Binghamton (The ORB). It has been accepted for inclusion in The Society for Ancient Greek Philosophy Newsletter by an authorized administrator of The Open Repository @ Binghamton (The ORB). For more information, please contact [email protected]. DRAFT: SOIVÍE W AYS O F BEING IN PLATO, BY ALLAN SILVERM AN; SAGP, NYC/91 A proper assay of Plato's ontology would treat of all the different kinds of things which, according to Plato, are said to be. It would divide those kinds into the primitive and, if there are any, the derived, and then show, where possible, how the latter kind of beings arise from the former. In addition, it might try to explain why Plato stkrts horn the primitives he does, that is, why he thinks them the bestarxai. Finally, perhaps, it would isolate and discuss any meta-principle which Plato relies on, and the very categories of the ontological theory, with the aim of showing how they are to be assimilated to the theory itself.
    [Show full text]
  • Isolated Experiences: Gilles Deleuze and the Solitudes of Reversed Platonism
    Isolated Experiences: Gilles Deleuze and the Solitudes of Reversed Platonism James Brusseau Facultad de Filosofia y Letras Universidad Nacional Autonoma de Mexico Acknowledgement I acknowledge Professor Alphonso Lingis for his contributions to this work. The task of contemporary philosophy has been defined: the reversal of Platonism. --Gilles Deleuze, 1968 Difference and Repetition Contents Introduction..............................................1 I Difference............................................ 1. Difference As Production And Limitation............... 2. The Eternal Return Does Difference: Production........ 3. See With My Own Eyes: Limitation...................... II Possession............................................ 4. Verbs And Nouns....................................... 5. Emily, The Patient, Bliss, Deleuze.................... 6. Desire, Not Want...................................... 7. Invitation To Possession.............................. III Alienation............................................ 8. Distance Without Measure.............................. 9. Rank Weeds And Fair Appearances....................... 10. Love Is For Other People.............................. Endnotes................................................... Introduction Experiences can be incestuous. They develop away from the general population; their genetic structures restlessly curve back into their own private histories. If they are going to be explained, they will have to explain themselves. Like sideshows at the travelling fair, it is not
    [Show full text]
  • The Nature of Predication
    THE NATURE OF PREDICATION A Dissertation Presented to the Faculty of the Graduate School of Cornell University in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy by David Liebesman August 2009 c 2009 David Liebesman ALL RIGHTS RESERVED THE NATURE OF PREDICATION David Liebesman, Ph.D. Cornell University 2009 I articulate and defend a necessary and sufficient condition for an occurrence of a term to function semantically as a predicate. The condition is that the term occurrence stands in the relation of ascription to its denotation, ascription being a fundamental semantic relation that differs from reference. This view on pred- ication has dramatically different semantic consequences from its alternatives. After outlining the alternatives, I draw out these consequences and show how they favor the ascription view. I then develop the ascription view and elicit a number of its virtues. BIOGRAPHICAL SKETCH David Liebesman received his B.A. in philosophy from Brandeis University in 2002, and his M.A. from University of Colorado in 2005. His primary areas of philosophical interest are philosophy of language and metaphysics. He begins his assistant professorship at Boston University in the fall of 2009. iii To my parents. iv ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS The work in this dissertation has benefited from conversations I’ve had with Karen Bennett, Richard Boyd, Brendan Jackson, Theo Korzukhin, Christian Lee, Tom McKay, Colin McLear, Andrew McGonigal, Nathan Salmon, and Robbie Williams. My dissertation committee has been absolutely wonderful. Sally McConnell-Ginet, Harold Hodes, and Brian Weatherson provided con- stant feedback and support. My greatest debt is to my dissertation advisor, Matti Eklund.
    [Show full text]