Testing Contextuality on Quantum Ensembles with One Clean Qubit

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Testing Contextuality on Quantum Ensembles with One Clean Qubit Testing Contextuality on Quantum Ensembles with One Clean Qubit The MIT Faculty has made this article openly available. Please share how this access benefits you. Your story matters. Citation Moussa, Osama et al. “Testing Contextuality on Quantum Ensembles with One Clean Qubit.” Physical Review Letters 104.16 (2010): 160501. © 2010 The American Physical Society. As Published http://dx.doi.org/10.1103/PhysRevLett.104.160501 Publisher American Physical Society Version Final published version Citable link http://hdl.handle.net/1721.1/58715 Terms of Use Article is made available in accordance with the publisher's policy and may be subject to US copyright law. Please refer to the publisher's site for terms of use. week ending PRL 104, 160501 (2010) PHYSICAL REVIEW LETTERS 23 APRIL 2010 Testing Contextuality on Quantum Ensembles with One Clean Qubit Osama Moussa,1,* Colm A. Ryan,1 David G. Cory,2,3 and Raymond Laflamme1,3 1Institute for Quantum Computing and Department of Physics and Astronomy, University of Waterloo, Waterloo, Ontario, N2L3G1, Canada 2Department of Nuclear Science and Engineering, MIT, Cambridge, Massachusetts 02139, USA 3Perimeter Institute for Theoretical Physics, Waterloo, Ontario, N2J2W9, Canada (Received 10 December 2009; published 23 April 2010) We present a protocol to evaluate the expectation value of the correlations of measurement outcomes for ensembles of quantum systems, and use it to experimentally demonstrate—under an assumption of fair sampling—the violation of an inequality that is satisfied by any noncontextual hidden-variables theory. The experiment is performed on an ensemble of molecular nuclear spins in the solid state, using established nuclear magnetic resonance techniques for quantum-information processing. DOI: 10.1103/PhysRevLett.104.160501 PACS numbers: 03.65.Ud, 03.65.Ta, 76.60.Àk Y Y The Bell-Kochen-Specker theorem [1–4] states that no S S ; fSkg ¼ ð kÞ¼ k (1) noncontextual hidden-variables (NCHV) theory can re- k k produce the predictions of quantum mechanics for corre- lations between measurement outcomes of some sets of irrespective of the product ordering. Repeating the prepa- observables. Any such set of observables constitutes a ration and measurement many times, and averaging over proof of the theorem. Recently, Cabello [5] and others the outcomes, one obtains an estimateQ of the ensemble S [6] used Bell-Kochen-Specker proofs to derive a set of average of the correlation h fSkgi ¼h k ð kÞi. inequalities that are satisfied by any NCHV theory but For the case where the coobservables fSkg are also are violated by quantum mechanics for any quantum state. dichotomic, with possible outcomes fðSkÞ¼1g, the These inequalities bound certain linear combinations of correlation (1) also takes on the possible values Æ1, and 1 1 ensemble averages of correlations between measure- the ensemble average satisfies À h fSkgi þ . Note, ment outcomes of compatible observables, thus creating that in this case, these operators are Hermitian and unitary a separation between the predicted outcomes of quantum (also known as quantum Boolean functions). mechanics, and the bound that is satisfied by NCHV Consider any set of observables with possible outcomes theories. Æ1 arranged in a 3  3 table such that the observables in This provides an opportunity to test noncontextuality each column and each row are coobservable. It has been with finite-precision experiments—which has been the shown [5] that, for any NCHV theory, subject of contention for many years [7–9]—and without 4; the need for the creation of special quantum states [10–12]. ¼h r1 iþh r2 iþh r3 iþh c1 iþh c2 ih c3 i Already, two experiments, on a pair of trapped 40Caþ ions (2) [13], and with single photons [14], have demonstrated this where hr i is the ensemble average of the correlation state-independent conflict with noncontextuality. In this 1 Letter, we examine testing contextuality on quantum between outcomes of the observables listed in the first ensembles. row, and so forth. The above inequality is independent of This Letter is organized as follows. First, we sketch the the preparation of the ensemble, provided all terms are estimated for the same preparation. arguments leading to one of the inequalities derived in [5]. 1 Then we present an algorithm to estimate the expectation Now, consider a two-qubit system (e.g., 2 spin- 2 parti- value of the correlations of measurement outcomes for cles), and the set of observables listed in Table I. For any ensembles of quantum systems. And lastly, we report and NCHV theory, the inequality (2) holds for the correlations discuss the result of experimentally implementing the al- between measurement outcomes of the coobservables gorithm on a three-qubit ensemble of molecular nuclear listed in each row and column, where, e.g., h r1 i¼ Z1 1Z ZZ spins in the solid state. h fZ1;1Z;ZZgi¼h Á Á i, and so forth. Inequality.—For a quantum system prepared according On the other hand, according to quantumQ mechanics, the tr S to some state, , one can assign simultaneous outcomes ensemble average h fSkgi is given by ð k kÞ. Thus, for fðSkÞg of measurements of a set fSkg of coobservables a set of coobservables whose product is proportional to the (i.e., comeasureable; mutually compatible; commuting). In unit operator—as is the case for all rows and columns of this case, the correlation between the measurement out- Table I—the quantum mechanical prediction of the en- comes is given by semble average of the correlation is equal to the propor- 0031-9007=10=104(16)=160501(4) 160501-1 Ó 2010 The American Physical Society week ending PRL 104, 160501 (2010) PHYSICAL REVIEW LETTERS 23 APRIL 2010 TABLE I. List of the two-qubit observables used to show that As shown in Fig. 1, one then applies the unitaries Sk in quantum mechanics violates inequality (2). This list has been succession to the system, controlled on the state of the used by Peres [15] and Mermin [16] as a Bell-Kochen-Specker probe qubit. Since, by definition, all Sk mutually commute, f1;X;Z;Yg proof for four-dimensional systems. are the single- then the order of their application has no bearing on the qubit Pauli operators, and, e.g., ZX :¼ Z X indicates a mea- surement of the Pauli Z operator on the first qubit and Pauli X measurement outcome. Repeating this procedure, and operator on the second. averaging the outcome of the measurement on the probe Q system, produces the correlation between this set of ob- c1 c2 c3 servables. Alternatively, one could prepare an ensemble of U r1 Z11ZZZþ1 systems according to , apply the transformations S in r2 1XX1 XX þ1 parallel to each member of the ensemble, and perform a r ZX XZ YY 1 bulk ensemble measurement to estimate h S i. This Q3 þ f kg þ1 þ1 À1 alleviates the need for isolation of single quantum systems, and the repeated application of single shot, projective measurement. tionality constant, independent of the initial preparation of Since inequality (2) is valid for any preparation , then the system. Hence, the quantum mechanical prediction for one is free to choose to prepare the system according to the is 6, which violates inequality (2). maximally mixed state. In which case, only one qubit—the Algorithm.—To measure the correlation between a set of probe system—is not maximally mixed. This corresponds coobservables, consider introducing an ancillary (probe) to the model of computation known as deterministic quan- U tum computation with one clean qubit (DQC1) [18]. qubit, and applying a transformation Sk to the composite system for each observable Sk, in a manner reminiscent of Two models.—Suppose the measurement process on the coherent syndrome measurement in quantum error correc- probe qubit was -efficient, i.e., returning a faithful answer tion [17]. For an observable S with the spectral decom- fraction of the time, and otherwise a uniformly distrib- uted random outcome. The probabilities pð1Þ of obtain- position S ¼ Pþ À PÀ, where Pþ and PÀ are the projectors on the þ1 and À1 eigenspaces of S, the trans- ing outcomes Æ1 will be modified to pð1Þ¼ 1À þ trs½P , and the ensemble average to hX 1di¼ formation US is defined as US ¼ 12 Pþ þ Z PÀ. That 2 Æ is to say, if the system is in a À1 eigenstate of S, apply a hSi. One can then estimate the expectation value hSi phase flip (Pauli Z operator) to the probe qubit, and if it is under an assumption of fair sampling and knowing the in a þ1 eigenstate, do nothing. This transformation can value of , which can be established from h1i. This also be expressed as a controlled operation dependent on model is equivalent to one where the probe system is 12 the state of the probe qubit, initially in the mixed state ð1 À Þ 2 þ jþihþj, provided the reduced dynamics on the probe qubit from preparation US ¼ 12 Pþ þ Z PÀ to measurement is represented by a unital map, i.e., a map 1 1 Z P P 1 1 Z P P ¼ 2ð 2 þ Þð þ þ ÀÞþ2ð 2 À Þð þ À ÀÞ that preserves the totally mixed state. To see this, suppose we prepare the probe qubit in some state a and then apply ¼j0ih0j1d þj1ih1jS; some transformation to the composite system, whose re- which is unitary for S unitary. If the system, denoted by s, duced dynamics on the probe qubit is described by a unital is initially prepared according to , and the probe qubit, a, linear map Ã.An-efficient measurement of X ¼ jþi  1 X 1 is in the þpffiffiffieigenstate of the Pauli operator, jþi ¼ hþj À jihj has two possible outcomes Æ with proba- ðj0iþj1iÞ= 2, the possible outcomes of Pauli X measure- bilities ment on the probe qubit is Æ1, with probabilities pð1Þ given by y pð1Þ¼traþs½USðjþihþj ÞUS ðjihj 1dÞ ¼ trs½hjð12 Pþ þ Z PÀÞðjþihþj Þ ð...Þyji ¼ trs½PÆ; FIG.
Recommended publications
  • Memory Cost of Quantum Contextuality
    Master of Science Thesis in Physics Department of Electrical Engineering, Linköping University, 2016 Memory Cost of Quantum Contextuality Patrik Harrysson Master of Science Thesis in Physics Memory Cost of Quantum Contextuality Patrik Harrysson LiTH-ISY-EX--16/4967--SE Supervisor: Jan-Åke Larsson isy, Linköpings universitet Examiner: Jan-Åke Larsson isy, Linköpings universitet Division of Information Coding Department of Electrical Engineering Linköping University SE-581 83 Linköping, Sweden Copyright © 2016 Patrik Harrysson Abstract This is a study taking an information theoretic approach toward quantum contex- tuality. The approach is that of using the memory complexity of finite-state ma- chines to quantify quantum contextuality. These machines simulate the outcome behaviour of sequential measurements on systems of quantum bits as predicted by quantum mechanics. Of interest is the question of whether or not classical representations by finite-state machines are able to effectively represent the state- independent contextual outcome behaviour. Here we consider spatial efficiency, rather than temporal efficiency as considered by D. Gottesmana, for the partic- ular measurement dynamics in systems of quantum bits. Extensions of cases found in the adjacent study of Kleinmann et al.b are established by which upper bounds on memory complexity for particular scenarios are found. Furthermore, an optimal machine structure for simulating any n-partite system of quantum bits is found, by which a lower bound for the memory complexity is found for each n N. Within this finite-state machine approach questions of foundational concerns2 on quantum mechanics were sought to be addressed. Alas, nothing of novel thought on such concerns is here reported on.
    [Show full text]
  • Lecture 8 Measurement-Based Quantum Computing
    Introduction to quantum computation and simulability Ernesto F. Galvão Instituto de Física, Universidade Federal Fluminense (Niterói, Brazil) 1−ε 0 + ε 1 q = ε p 0 p 0 U ! 0 ICTP-SAIFR – IFT/UNESP , October 15th-19th, 2018 Introduction to quantum computation and simulability Lecture 8 : Measurement-based QC (MBQC) II Outline: • Applications of MBQC: • models for quantum spacetime • blind quantum computation • Time-ordering in MBQC • MBQC without adaptativity: • Clifford circuits • IQP circuits • Introduction to quantum contextuality • Contextuality as a computational resource • in magic state distillation • in MBQC • For slides and links to related material, see Application: blind quantum computation • Classical/quantum separation in MBQC allow for implementation of novel protocols – such as blind quantum computation • Here, client has limited quantum capabilities, and uses a server to do computation for her. • Blind = server doesn’t know what’s being computed. Broadbent, Fitzsimons, Kashefi, axiv:0807.4154 [quant-ph] Application: model for quantum spacetime • MBQC can serve as a discrete toy model for quantum spacetime: quantum space-time MBQC quantum substrate graph states events measurements principle establishing global determinism requirement space-time structure for computations [Raussendorf et al., arxiv:1108.5774] • Even closed timelike curves (= time travel) have analogues in MBQC! [Dias da Silva, Kashefi, Galvão PRA 83, 012316 (2011)] Time-ordering in MBQC from: Proc. Int. School of Physics "Enrico Fermi" on "Quantum Computers,
    [Show full text]
  • On Graph Approaches to Contextuality and Their Role in Quantum Theory
    SPRINGER BRIEFS IN MATHEMATICS Barbara Amaral · Marcelo Terra Cunha On Graph Approaches to Contextuality and their Role in Quantum Theory 123 SpringerBriefs in Mathematics Series editors Nicola Bellomo Michele Benzi Palle Jorgensen Tatsien Li Roderick Melnik Otmar Scherzer Benjamin Steinberg Lothar Reichel Yuri Tschinkel George Yin Ping Zhang SpringerBriefs in Mathematics showcases expositions in all areas of mathematics and applied mathematics. Manuscripts presenting new results or a single new result in a classical field, new field, or an emerging topic, applications, or bridges between new results and already published works, are encouraged. The series is intended for mathematicians and applied mathematicians. More information about this series at http://www.springer.com/series/10030 SBMAC SpringerBriefs Editorial Board Carlile Lavor University of Campinas (UNICAMP) Institute of Mathematics, Statistics and Scientific Computing Department of Applied Mathematics Campinas, Brazil Luiz Mariano Carvalho Rio de Janeiro State University (UERJ) Department of Applied Mathematics Graduate Program in Mechanical Engineering Rio de Janeiro, Brazil The SBMAC SpringerBriefs series publishes relevant contributions in the fields of applied and computational mathematics, mathematics, scientific computing, and related areas. Featuring compact volumes of 50 to 125 pages, the series covers a range of content from professional to academic. The Sociedade Brasileira de Matemática Aplicada e Computacional (Brazilian Society of Computational and Applied Mathematics,
    [Show full text]
  • Non-Deterministic Semantics for Quantum States
    entropy Article Non-Deterministic Semantics for Quantum States Juan Pablo Jorge 1 and Federico Holik 2,* 1 Physics Department, University of Buenos Aires, Buenos Aires 1428, Argentina; [email protected] 2 Instituto de Física La Plata, UNLP, CONICET, Facultad de Ciencias Exactas, 1900 La Plata, Argentina * Correspondence: [email protected] Received: 16 October 2019; Accepted: 27 January 2020; Published: 28 January 2020 Abstract: In this work, we discuss the failure of the principle of truth functionality in the quantum formalism. By exploiting this failure, we import the formalism of N-matrix theory and non-deterministic semantics to the foundations of quantum mechanics. This is done by describing quantum states as particular valuations associated with infinite non-deterministic truth tables. This allows us to introduce a natural interpretation of quantum states in terms of a non-deterministic semantics. We also provide a similar construction for arbitrary probabilistic theories based in orthomodular lattices, allowing to study post-quantum models using logical techniques. Keywords: quantum states; non-deterministic semantics; truth functionality 1. Introduction According to the principle of truth-functionality or composability (TFP), the truth-value of a complex formula is uniquely determined by the truth-values of its subformulas. It is a basic principle of logic. However, as explained in [1], many real-world situations involve dealing with information that is incomplete, vague or uncertain. This is especially true for quantum phenomena, where only probabilistic assertions about possible events can be tested in the lab. These situations pose a threat to the application of logical systems obeying the principle of truth-functionality in those problems.
    [Show full text]
  • Continuous Variable Nonloclality and Contextuality
    Continuous-variable nonlocality and contextuality Rui Soares Barbosa Tom Douce Department of Computer Science Laboratoire d’Informatique de Paris 6 University of Oxford CNRS and Sorbonne Universite´ [email protected] School of Informatics University of Edinburgh [email protected] Pierre-Emmanuel Emeriau Elham Kashefi Shane Mansfield Laboratoire d’Informatique de Paris 6 Laboratoire d’Informatique de Paris 6 Laboratoire d’Informatique de Paris 6 CNRS and Sorbonne Universite´ CNRS and Sorbonne Universite´ CNRS and Sorbonne Universite´ [email protected] School of Informatics [email protected] University of Edinburgh [email protected] Contextuality is a non-classical behaviour that can be exhibited by quantum systems. It is increas- ingly studied for its relationship to quantum-over-classical advantages in informatic tasks. To date, it has largely been studied in discrete variable scenarios, where observables take values in discrete and usually finite sets. Practically, on the other hand, continuous-variable scenarios offer some of the most promising candidates for implementing quantum computations and informatic protocols. Here we set out a framework for treating contextuality in continuous-variable scenarios. It is shown that the Fine–Abramsky–Brandenburger theorem extends to this setting, an important consequence of which is that nonlocality can be viewed as a special case of contextuality, as in the discrete case. The contextual fraction, a quantifiable measure of contextuality that bears a precise relationship to Bell inequality violations and quantum advantages, can also be defined in this setting. It is shown to be a non-increasing monotone with respect to classical operations that include binning to discretise data.
    [Show full text]
  • Arxiv:1904.05306V3 [Quant-Ph] 30 May 2021 Fax: +34-954-556672 E-Mail: [email protected] 2 Ad´Ancabello
    Noname manuscript No. (will be inserted by the editor) Bell non-locality and Kochen-Specker contextuality: How are they connected? Ad´anCabello Received: July 4, 2020/ Accepted: July 3, 2020 Abstract Bell non-locality and Kochen-Specker (KS) contextuality are logi- cally independent concepts, fuel different protocols with quantum vs classical advantage, and have distinct classical simulation costs. A natural question is what are the relations between these concepts, advantages, and costs. To ad- dress this question, it is useful to have a map that captures all the connections between Bell non-locality and KS contextuality in quantum theory. The aim of this work is to introduce such a map. After defining the theory-independent notions of Bell non-locality and KS contextuality for ideal measurements, we show that, in quantum theory, due to Neumark's dilation theorem, every quan- tum Bell non-local behavior can be mapped to a formally identical KS contex- tual behavior produced in a scenario with identical relations of compatibility but where measurements are ideal and no space-like separation is required. A more difficult problem is identifying connections in the opposite direction. We show that there are \one-to-one" and partial connections between KS contex- tual behaviors and Bell non-local behaviors for some KS scenarios, but not for all of them. However, there is also a method that transforms any KS contextual behavior for quantum systems of dimension d into a Bell non-local behavior between two quantum subsystems each of them of dimension d. We collect all these connections in map and list some problems which can benefit from this map.
    [Show full text]
  • Arxiv:2102.13036V2 [Quant-Ph] 12 Mar 2021 2
    Quantum Contextuality Costantino Budroni,1, 2 Ad´anCabello,3, 4 Otfried G¨uhne,5 Matthias Kleinmann,5 and Jan-Ake˚ Larsson6 1Faculty of Physics, University of Vienna, Boltzmanngasse 5, 1090 Vienna, Austria 2Institute for Quantum Optics and Quantum Information (IQOQI), Austrian Academy of Sciences, Boltzmanngasse 3, 1090 Vienna, Austria 3 Departamento de F´ısicaAplicada II, Universidad de Sevilla, 41012 Sevilla, Spain 4 Instituto Carlos I de F´ısicaTe´oricay Computacional, Universidad de Sevilla, 41012 Sevilla, Spain 5 Naturwissenschaftlich-Technische Fakult¨at,Universit¨at Siegen, Walter-Flex-Straße 3, 57068 Siegen, Germany 6 Institutionen f¨orSystemteknik och Matematiska Institutionen, Link¨opingsUniversitet, 58183 Link¨oping, Sweden (Dated: March 15, 2021) A central result in the foundations of quantum mechanics is the Kochen-Specker theorem. In short, it states that quantum mechanics is in conflict with classical models in which the result of a measurement does not depend on which other compatible measurements are jointly performed. Here, compatible measurements are those that can be performed simultaneously or in any order without disturbance. This conflict is generically called quantum contextuality. In this article, we present an introduction to this subject and its current status. We review several proofs of the Kochen-Specker theorem and different notions of contextuality. We explain how to experimentally test some of these notions and discuss connections between contextuality and nonlocality or graph theory. Finally, we review some applications of contextuality in quantum information processing. Contents 5. Final considerations on KS contextuality experiments 25 I. Introduction 2 E. A different notion of contextuality: Spekkens' approach 26 II. Quantum contextuality in a nutshell 2 1.
    [Show full text]
  • Violation of the Bell's Type Inequalities As a Local Expression Of
    Violation of the Bell’s type inequalities as a local expression of incompatibility Andrei Khrennikov Linnaeus University, International Center for Mathematical Modeling in Physics and Cognitive Sciences V¨axj¨o, SE-351 95, Sweden February 20, 2019 Abstract By filtering out the philosophic component we can be said that the EPR-paper was directed against the straightforward interpreta- tion of the Heisenberg’s uncertainty principle or more generally the Bohr’s complementarity principle. The latter expresses contextuality of quantum measurements: dependence of measurement’s output on the complete experimental arrangement. However, Bell restructured the EPR-argument against complementarity to justify nonlocal theo- ries with hidden variables of the Bohmian mechanics’ type. Then this Bell’s kind of nonlocality - subquantum nonlocality - was lifted to the level of quantum theory - up to the terminology “quantum nonlocal- ity”. The aim of this short note is to explain that Bell’s test is simply a special test of local incompatibility of quantum observables, similar to interference experiments, e.g., the two-slit experiment. 1 Introduction In this note I repeat the message presented in papers [1]-[3]. This arXiv:1902.07070v1 [quant-ph] 19 Feb 2019 note was motivated by the recent INTERNET discussion on the Bell inequality. This discussion involved both sides: those who support the conventional interpretation of a violation of the Bell type inequalities and those who present a variety of non-conventional positions. As always happens in such discussions on the Bell inequality, the diversity of for and against arguments was really amazing, chaotic, and mainly misleading.1 My attempt to clarify the situation by replying R.
    [Show full text]
  • Classical and Quantum Memory in Contextuality Scenarios
    Universidade Federal de Minas Gerais Departamento de F´ısica Instituto de Ci^enciasExatas | ICEx Classical and Quantum Memory in Contextuality Scenarios Gabriel Fagundes PhD Thesis Presented to the Graduate Program in Physics of Federal University of Minas Gerais, as a partial requirement to obtain the title of Doctor in Physics. Abstract Quantum theory can be described as a framework for calculating probabilities of mea- surement outcomes. A great part of its deep foundational questions comes from the fact that these probabilities may disagree with classical calculations, under reasonable premises. The classical notion in which the observables are frequently assumed as predefined before their measurement motivates the assumption of noncontextuality, i.e. that all the observables have preassigned values before the interaction with the experimental apparatus, independently on which other observables are jointly measured with it. It is known that this classical view is inconsistent with quantum predictions. The main question of this thesis can be phrased as: can we use memory to classically obtain results in agreement with quantum theory applied to se- quential measurements? If so, how to quantify the amount of memory needed? These questions are addressed in a specific contextuality scenario: the Peres-Mermin square. Previous results are extended by using a comprehensive scheme, which shows that the same bound of a three- internal-state automaton is sufficient, even when all probabilistic predictions are considered. Trying to use a lower dimensional quantum resource, i.e. the qubit, to reduce the memory cost in this scenario led us to another question of whether or not there is contextuality for this type of system.
    [Show full text]
  • Hypergraph Contextuality
    entropy Article Hypergraph Contextuality Mladen Paviˇci´c Center of Excellence for Advanced Materials and Sensors, Research Unit Photonics and Quantum Optics, Institute Ruder Boškovi´c,Zagreb 10000, Croatia; [email protected] Received: 14 October 2019 ; Accepted: 10 November 2019; Published: 12 November 2019 Abstract: Quantum contextuality is a source of quantum computational power and a theoretical delimiter between classical and quantum structures. It has been substantiated by numerous experiments and prompted generation of state independent contextual sets, that is, sets of quantum observables capable of revealing quantum contextuality for any quantum state of a given dimension. There are two major classes of state-independent contextual sets—the Kochen-Specker ones and the operator-based ones. In this paper, we present a third, hypergraph-based class of contextual sets. Hypergraph inequalities serve as a measure of contextuality. We limit ourselves to qutrits and obtain thousands of 3-dim contextual sets. The simplest of them involves only 5 quantum observables, thus enabling a straightforward implementation. They also enable establishing new entropic contextualities. Keywords: quantum contextuality; hypergraph contextuality; MMP hypergraphs; operator contextuality; qutrits; Yu-Oh contextuality; Bengtsson-Blanchfield-Cabello contextuality; Xu-Chen-Su contextuality; entropic contextuality 1. Introduction Recently, quantum contextuality found applications in quantum communication [1,2], quantum computation [3,4], quantum nonlocality [5] and lattice theory [6,7]. This has prompted experimental implementation with photons [8–19], classical light [20–23], neutrons [24–26], trapped ions [27], solid state molecular nuclear spins [28] and superconducting quantum systems [29]. Quantum contextuality, which the aforementioned citations refer to, precludes assignments of predetermined values to dense sets of projection operators, and in our approach we shall keep to this feature of the considered contextual sets.
    [Show full text]
  • Experimentally Testable Noncontextuality Inequalities Via Fourier-Motzkin Elimination
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by University of Waterloo's Institutional Repository Experimentally Testable Noncontextuality Inequalities Via Fourier-Motzkin Elimination by Anirudh Krishna A thesis presented to the University of Waterloo in fulfillment of the thesis requirement for the degree of Master of Science in Physics - Quantum Information Waterloo, Ontario, Canada, 2015 ©Anirudh Krishna 2015 Declaration I hereby declare that I am the sole author of this thesis. This is a true copy of the thesis, including any required final revisions, as accepted by my examiners. I understand that my thesis may be made electronically available to the public. ii Abstract Generalized noncontextuality as defined by Spekkens is an attempt to make precise the distinction between classical and quantum theories. It is a restriction on models used to reproduce the predictions of quantum mechanics. There has been considerable progress recently in deriving experimentally robust noncontextuality inequalities. The violation of these inequalities is a sufficient condition for an experiment to not admit a generalized noncontextual model. In this thesis, we present an algorithm to automate the derivation of noncontextuality inequalities. At the heart of this algorithm is a technique called Fourier Motzkin elimination (abbrev. FM elimination). After a brief overview of the generalized notion of contextuality and FM elimination, we proceed to demon- strate how this algorithm works by using it to derive noncontextuality inequalities for a number of examples. Belinfante’s construction, presented first for the sake of pedagogy, is based on a simple proof by Belinfante to demonstrate the invalidity of von Neumann’s notion of noncontextuality.
    [Show full text]
  • Contextuality and the Kochen-Specker Theorem
    Grundlagen der modernen Quantenphysik – Seminar WS 2007/08 Contextuality and the Kochen-Specker Theorem (Interpretations of Quantum Mechanics) by Christoph Saulder (0400944) 19. 12. 2007 Contextuality and the Kochen-Specker Theorem ABSTRACT Since local hidden variables are forbidden by Bell’s theorem, the Kochen-Specker theorem forces a theory for quantum mechanics based on hidden variables to be contextual. Several experiments have been performed to proof this powerful theorem. I will review the consequences of the Kochen-Specker theorem and contextuality on the interpretation of quantum mechanics. TABEL OF CONTENTS ABSTRACT............................................................................................................................... 1 TABEL OF CONTENTS........................................................................................................... 1 INTRODUCTION...................................................................................................................... 2 INTERPRETATIONS OF QUANTUM MECHANICS............................................................ 2 Copenhagen Interpretation ..................................................................................................... 2 Hidden-Variable Theories...................................................................................................... 2 Other Interpretations .............................................................................................................. 3 Comparison ...........................................................................................................................
    [Show full text]