Classifying Arguments by Scheme

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Classifying Arguments by Scheme Classifying Arguments by Scheme Vanessa Wei Feng Graeme Hirst Department of Computer Science Department of Computer Science University of Toronto University of Toronto Toronto, ON, M5S 3G4, Canada Toronto, ON, M5S 3G4, Canada [email protected] [email protected] Abstract Another premise is left implicit — “Adhering to those treaties and covenants is a means of realizing Argumentation schemes are structures or tem- survival of the entire world”. This proposition is an plates for various kinds of arguments. Given enthymeme of this argument. the text of an argument with premises and con- Our ultimate goal is to reconstruct the en- clusion identified, we classify it as an instance thymemes in an argument, because determining of one of five common schemes, using features specific to each scheme. We achieve accura- these unstated assumptions is an integral part of un- cies of 63–91% in one-against-others classifi- derstanding, supporting, or attacking an entire argu- cation and 80–94% in pairwise classification ment. Hence reconstructing enthymemes is an im- (baseline = 50% in both cases). portant problem in argument understanding. We be- lieve that first identifying the particular argumenta- tion scheme that an argument is using will help to 1 Introduction bridge the gap between stated and unstated proposi- tions in the argument, because each argumentation We investigate a new task in the computational anal- scheme is a relatively fixed “template” for arguing. ysis of arguments: the classification of arguments That is, given an argument, we first classify its ar- by the argumentation schemes that they use. An ar- gumentation scheme; then we fit the stated proposi- gumentation scheme, informally, is a framework or tions into the corresponding template; and from this structure for a (possibly defeasible) argument; we we infer the enthymemes. will give a more-formal definition and examples in Section 3. Our work is motivated by the need to de- In this paper, we present an argument scheme termine the unstated (or implicitly stated) premises classification system as a stage following argument that arguments written in natural language normally detection and proposition classification. First in Sec- draw on. Such premises are called enthymemes. tion 2 and Section 3, we introduce the background to our work, including related work in this field, For instance, the argument in Example 1 consists the two core concepts of argumentation schemes and of one explicit premise (the first sentence) and a con- scheme-sets, and the Araucaria dataset. In Section 4 clusion (the second sentence): and Section 5 we present our classification system, Example 1 [Premise:] The survival of the entire including the overall framework, data preprocessing, world is at stake. feature selection, and the experimental setups. In [Conclusion:] The treaties and covenants aiming the remaining section, we present the essential ap- for a world free of nuclear arsenals and other con- proaches to solve the leftover problems of this paper ventional and biological weapons of mass destruc- which we will study in our future work, and discuss tion should be adhered to scrupulously by all na- the experimental results, and potential directions for tions. future work. 987 Proceedings of the 49th Annual Meeting of the Association for Computational Linguistics, pages 987–996, Portland, Oregon, June 19-24, 2011. c 2011 Association for Computational Linguistics 2 Related work determine how the pieces fit together as an instance of an argumentation scheme. Argumentation has not received a great deal of at- tention in computational linguistics, although it has 3 Argumentation schemes, scheme-sets, been a topic of interest for many years. Cohen and annotation (1987) presented a computational model of argu- mentative discourse. Dick (1987; 1991a; 1991b) de- 3.1 Definition and examples veloped a representation for retrieval of judicial de- Argumentation schemes are structures or templates cisions by the structure of their legal argument — a for forms of arguments. The arguments need not be necessity for finding legal precedents independent of deductive or inductive; on the contrary, most argu- their domain. However, at that time no corpus of ar- mentation schemes are for presumptive or defeasible guments was available, so Dick’s system was purely arguments (Walton and Reed, 2002). For example, theoretical. Recently, the Araucaria project at Uni- argument from cause to effect is a commonly used versity of Dundee has developed a software tool for scheme in everyday arguments. A list of such argu- manual argument analysis, with a point-and-click in- mentation schemes is called a scheme-set. terface for users to reconstruct and diagram an ar- It has been shown that argumentation schemes gument (Reed and Rowe, 2004; Rowe and Reed, are useful in evaluating common arguments as falla- 2008). The project also maintains an online repos- cious or not (van Eemeren and Grootendorst, 1992). itory, called AraucariaDB, of marked-up naturally In order to judge the weakness of an argument, a set occurring arguments collected by annotators world- of critical questions are asked according to the par- wide, which can be used as an experimental corpus ticular scheme that the argument is using, and the for automatic argumentation analysis (for details see argument is regarded as valid if it matches all the Section 3.2). requirements imposed by the scheme. Recent work on argument interpretation includes Walton’s set of 65 argumentation schemes (Wal- that of George, Zukerman, and Nieman (2007), who ton et al., 2008) is one of the best-developed scheme- interpret constructed-example arguments (not natu- sets in argumentation theory. The five schemes de- rally occurring text) as Bayesian networks. Other fined in Table 1 are the most commonly used ones, contemporary research has looked at the automatic and they are the focus of the scheme classification detection of arguments in text and the classification system that we will describe in this paper. of premises and conclusions. The work closest to ours is perhaps that of Mochales and Moens (2007; 3.2 Araucaria dataset 2008; 2009a; 2009b). In their early work, they fo- One of the challenges for automatic argumentation cused on automatic detection of arguments in legal analysis is that suitable annotated corpora are still texts. With each sentence represented as a vector of very rare, in spite of work by many researchers. shallow features, they trained a multinomial na¨ıve In the work described here, we use the Araucaria Bayes classifier and a maximum entropy model on database1, an online repository of arguments, as our the Araucaria corpus, and obtained a best average experimental dataset. Araucaria includes approxi- accuracy of 73.75%. In their follow-up work, they mately 660 manually annotated arguments from var- trained a support vector machine to further classify ious sources, such as newspapers and court cases, each argumentative clause into a premise or a con- and keeps growing. Although Araucaria has sev- clusion, with an F1 measure of 68.12% and 74.07% eral limitations, such as rather small size and low respectively. In addition, their context-free grammar agreement among annotators2, it is nonetheless one for argumentation structure parsing obtained around of the best argumentative corpora available to date. 60% accuracy. Our work is “downstream” from that of Mochales 1http://araucaria.computing.dundee.ac.uk/doku.php# and Moens. Assuming the eventual success of their, araucaria argumentation corpus 2The developers of Araucaria did not report on inter- or others’, research program on detecting and clas- annotator agreement, probably because some arguments are an- sifying the components of an argument, we seek to notated by only one commentator. 988 Argument from example are annotated as “missing = yes”. Premise: In this particular case, the individual a Example 2 Example of argument markup from has property F and also property G. Araucaria Conclusion: Therefore, generally, if x has prop- <TEXT>If we stop the free creation of art, we will stop erty F, then it also has property G. the free viewing of art.</TEXT> <AU> Argument from cause to effect <PROP identifier="C" missing="yes"> Major premise: Generally, if A occurs, then B will <PROPTEXT offset="-1"> The prohibition of the free creation of art should (might) occur. not be brought about.</PROPTEXT> Minor premise: In this case, A occurs (might oc- <INSCHEME scheme="Argument from Consequences" cur). schid="0" /> </PROP> Conclusion: Therefore, in this case, B will <LA> (might) occur. <AU> <PROP identifier="A" missing="no"> Practical reasoning <PROPTEXT offset="0"> If we stop the free creation of art, we will Major premise: I have a goal G. stop the free viewing of art.</PROPTEXT> Minor premise: Carrying out action A is a means <INSCHEME scheme="Argument from Consequences" schid="0" /> to realize G. </PROP> Conclusion: Therefore, I ought (practically </AU> speaking) to carry out this action A. <AU> <PROP identifier="B" missing="yes"> Argument from consequences <PROPTEXT offset="-1"> The prohibition of free viewing of art is not Premise: If A is (is not) brought about, good (bad) acceptable.</PROPTEXT> consequences will (will not) plausibly occur. <INSCHEME scheme="Argument from Consequences" schid="0" /> Conclusion: Therefore, A should (should not) be </PROP> brought about. </AU> </LA> Argument from verbal classification </AU> Individual premise: a has a particular property F. There are three scheme-sets used in the anno- Classification premise: For all x, if x has property tations in Araucaria: Walton’s scheme-set, Katzav F, then x can be classified as having property and Reed’s (2004) scheme-set, and Pollock’s (1995) G. scheme-set. Each of these has a different set of Conclusion: Therefore, a has property G. schemes; and most arguments in Araucaria are marked up according to only one of them. Our Table 1: The five most frequent schemes and their defini- experimental dataset is composed of only those tions in Walton’s scheme-set.
Recommended publications
  • 299 Abelson, RP, 66 Abductive Argument Argumentation Scheme For
    Cambridge University Press 978-1-107-03930-8 - Methods of Argumentation Douglas Walton Index More information Index Abelson, R.P., 66 Anchored narrative, 137 , 163 Abductive argument Appeal to authority, 216–17 argumentation scheme for, 162 Appeal to expert opinion, 216 , 221 critical questions for, 162 Appeal to the people, see Fallacy of Abductive reasoning, 111 , 160 , 187–88 argument from popular opinion argumentation scheme for, 84 , 206 Araucaria, 15 , 16 , 99 critical questions for, 84 compared, 19–20 modeling with, 160–61 described, 12–13 Abortion case, 143–44 , 148 ArguMed, 16 , 17 Abstract argumentation framework, comparison, 20 35–36 Argument defi ned, 33 attack, 27 , 42 , 53 , 55 , 78 Action-based alternating transition back and forth exchange, 92 system, 156 composition, 46 , 48 , 90 ACTOS example, 1 , 20 defi nition, 48 , 88 , 89 critical questions, 15–16 defeasible, 7 , 30 , 227 , 229 , 246–47 explained, 14 open-ended, 238 Ad hominem argument, 50 , 159 , 234 evaluated, 33 defi ned, 96 identifying, 94–97 requirements of, 97 requirements for identifying, 89–90 types of, 118 Argument diagram, 72 , 255–56 , 259 Ad hominem attack, 235 composition of, 10 Ad verecundiam fallacy, 274 Argument from analogy, 42 , 114 , 139 , Affi davit example, 44–45 143 , 146 Agent argumentation scheme for, 122 , 145 described, 101 core, 126 , 130–31 , 149 desires and beliefs, 5 derived scheme, 130–31 Aiken, S., 281 simplest, 126 , 147–49 , 151–52 Airline fl ight schedule, 244 single respect scheme, 128 , 149–50 Ali, S., 104 version 1 , 141 , 142
    [Show full text]
  • Understanding Students' Reasoning
    Understanding Students’ Reasoning: Argumentation Schemes as an Interpretation Method in Science Education Aikaterini Konstantinidou & Fabrizio Macagno Science & Education Contributions from History, Philosophy and Sociology of Science and Mathematics ISSN 0926-7220 Sci & Educ DOI 10.1007/s11191-012-9564-3 1 23 Your article is protected by copyright and all rights are held exclusively by Springer Science +Business Media Dordrecht. This e-offprint is for personal use only and shall not be self- archived in electronic repositories. If you wish to self-archive your work, please use the accepted author’s version for posting to your own website or your institution’s repository. You may further deposit the accepted author’s version on a funder’s repository at a funder’s request, provided it is not made publicly available until 12 months after publication. 1 23 Author's personal copy Sci & Educ DOI 10.1007/s11191-012-9564-3 Understanding Students’ Reasoning: Argumentation Schemes as an Interpretation Method in Science Education Aikaterini Konstantinidou • Fabrizio Macagno Ó Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2012 Abstract The purpose of this paper is to investigate the argumentative structure of students’ arguments using argumentation schemes as an instrument for reconstructing the missing premises underlying their reasoning. Building on the recent literature in science education, in order for an explanation to be persuasive and achieve a conceptual change it needs to proceed from the interlocutor’s background knowledge to the analysis of the unknown or wrongly interpreted phenomena. Argumentation schemes represent the abstract forms of the most used and common forms of human reasoning, combining logical principles with semantic concepts.
    [Show full text]
  • 1 Argumentation in the Framework of Deliberation
    1 ARGUMENTATION IN THE FRAMEWORK OF DELIBERATION DIALOGUE Douglas Walton, Katie Atkinson, Trevor Bench-Capon, Adam Wyner and Dan Cartwright According to argumentation theory, reasoning takes place in different types of dialogue: persuasion dialogue, negotiation, deliberation, information-seeking dialogue, inquiry, and eristic dialogue. These different dialogue types may be nested within one another. Current research in artificial intelligence is building formal models corresponding to each of these types of dialogue and showing how they can be implemented in, for example, multi-agent communications systems. In this paper, we (1) clarify the distinction between deliberation dialogue and persuasion dialogue, (2) survey some recent research in artificial intelligence studying formal properties of deliberation dialogue, (3) present a model of argumentation in deliberation dialogue that has proved to be useful in electronic democracy, and (4) argue that this model provides an attractive alternative to the dominant cost-benefit model of rational argumentation traditionally accepted in economics and other fields as the basis for evaluating argumentation of the kind used in policy decision making. One of the most important lessons of argumentation theory has been that arguments need to be analyzed and evaluated not only by identifying the logical form of an argument in abstraction from its context of use, but also by paying attention to the purpose for which an argument was supposedly used in a conversational setting. In particular, as we will show in this paper, it is vitally important to distinguish between two different types of conversational frameworks called persuasion dialogue and deliberation dialogue. As we will show, logical fallacies can easily be committed in the most common kinds of everyday reasoning by failing to take this distinction into account.
    [Show full text]
  • Justification of Argumentation Schemes
    Justification of Argumentation Schemes D W U W W,M 3 29, C [email protected] Received by Greg Restall Published July 8, 2005 http://www.philosophy.unimelb.edu.au/ajl/2005 c 2005 Douglas Walton Abstract: Argumentation schemes are forms of argument that capture stereotypical patterns of human reasoning, especially defeasible ones like argument from expert opinion, that have proved troublesome to view deductively or inductively. Much practical work has already been done on argumentation schemes, proving their worth in [19], but more pre- cise investigations are needed to formalize their structures. The problem posed in this paper is what form justification of a given scheme, as hav- ing a certain precise structure of inference, should take. It is argued that defeasible argumentation schemes require both a systematic and a prag- matic justification, of a kind that can only be provided by the case study method of collecting key examples of arguments of the types tradition- ally classified as fallacies, and subjecting them to comparative examina- tion and analysis. By this method, postulated structures for schemes can be formulated as hypotheses to solve three kinds of problems: (1) how to classify such arguments into different types, (2) how to identify their premises and conclusions, and (3) how to formulate the critical questions used to evaluate each type of argument. 1 On September 19, 2004, I gave a lecture on informal logic and argumentation to the graduate students of the Institute of Logic and Cognition at Sun Yat- sen University in Guangzhou, China.1 The subject of the lecture included an account of argumentation schemes representing common forms of argument that are neither deductive nor inductive.
    [Show full text]
  • Applications of Argumentation Schemes Chris Reed University of Dundee
    CORE Metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk Provided by Scholarship at UWindsor University of Windsor Scholarship at UWindsor OSSA Conference Archive OSSA 4 May 17th, 9:00 AM - May 19th, 5:00 PM Applications of Argumentation Schemes Chris Reed University of Dundee Doug Walton University of Winnipeg Follow this and additional works at: http://scholar.uwindsor.ca/ossaarchive Part of the Philosophy Commons Reed, Chris and Walton, Doug, "Applications of Argumentation Schemes" (2001). OSSA Conference Archive. 97. http://scholar.uwindsor.ca/ossaarchive/OSSA4/papersandcommentaries/97 This Paper is brought to you for free and open access by the Faculty of Arts, Humanities and Social Sciences at Scholarship at UWindsor. It has been accepted for inclusion in OSSA Conference Archive by an authorized conference organizer of Scholarship at UWindsor. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Title: Applications of Argumentation Schemes Authors: Chris Reed, and Doug Walton Response to this paper by: Leo Groarke © 2001 Chris Reed, and Doug Walton ABSTRACT. Argumentation schemes capture common, stereotypical patterns of reasoning which are nondeductive and nonmonotonic. As interest in understanding these schemes from a theoretical point of view grows, so too does an awareness within computational work that these schemes might yield powerful techniques in a range of domains. This paper aims to perform two functions. First, to briefly review the literature on argumentation schemes, including the key works by Hastings, Walton and Kienpointner, and to set it in a broader context, adducing concerns from deductivism and presumptive, nonmonotonic reasoning. The second is to consider the various roles argumentation schemes might play in Artificial Intelligence, and in particular to consider (i) how schemes might be characterized as planning operators in domains such as natural language generation, with operationalized schemes representing means of achieving specific (e.g.
    [Show full text]
  • Implementing Argumentation Schemes As Logic Programs
    Proceedings of CMNA 2016 - Floris Bex, Floriana Grasso, Nancy Green (eds) Implementing Argumentation Schemes as Logic Programs Nancy L. Green University of North Carolina Greensboro, Greensboro, NC, USA [email protected] Abstract audience, as well as constraints of the underlying argumentation scheme [Green, 2010]. Furthermore, The dominant approach to argumentation mining has been to treat it as a text explicitly given components may not occur in classification problem. However some contiguity with other components of the same applications to scientific text, such as argument. In fact, the content of two arguments may accurately summarizing argumentation in be interleaved at the text level. research articles, require a deeper Although human-level understanding of natural understanding of the text. This paper language text is currently beyond the state of the art, provides a novel approach in which we contend that an inference-based approach is argumentation schemes are represented as feasible for scientific applications requiring a deeper logic program rules for use in argumentation analysis of argumentation. In support of this position, mining. The logic programs can be used, not this paper demonstrates a novel approach in which only to recognize fully explicit arguments, argumentation schemes are implemented as logic but also arguments with implicit programs. In addition, this paper explains how this conclusions. This paper presents seven inference-based approach fits into an argumentation implemented rules based on analysis of an mining system architecture. open-access biomedical research article. The rules are specializations of general schemes that can apply to other qualitative 2 Representing Biomedical Arguments causal domains in the natural sciences.
    [Show full text]
  • Argumentation Schemes. History, Classifications, and Computational Applications
    Argumentation Schemes. History, Classifications, and Computational Applications Fabrizio Macagno Universidade Nova de Lisboa, Portugal [email protected] Douglas Walton University of Windsor, Canada [email protected] Chris Reed University of Dundee, Scotland [email protected] Abstract Argumentation schemes can be described as abstract structures representing the most generic types of argument, constituting the building blocks of the ones used in everyday reasoning. This paper investigates the structure, classification, and uses of such schemes. Three goals are pursued: 1) to describe the schemes, showing how they evolved and how they have been classified in the traditional and the modern theories; 2) to propose a method for classifying them based on ancient and modern developments; and 3) to outline and show how schemes can be used to describe and analyze or produce real arguments. To this purpose, we will build on the traditional distinctions for building a dichotomic classification of schemes, and we will advance a modular approach to argument analysis, in which different argumentation schemes are combined together in order to represent each step of reasoning on which a complex argument relies. Finally, we will show how schemes are applied to formal systems, focusing on their applications to Artificial Intelligence, AI & Law, argument mining, and formal ontologies. Vol. 4 No. 8 2017 IFCoLog Journal of Logics and Their Applications Macagno, Walton and Reed 1 Introduction The purpose of this paper is threefold: 1) to describe the schemes, showing how they evolved and how they have been classified in the traditional and the modern theories; 2) to propose a method for classifying them based on ancient and modern developments; and 3) to outline and show how schemes are interrelated and can be organized in a modular way to describe natural arguments or produce complex arguments.
    [Show full text]
  • Story Schemes for Argumentation About the Facts of a Crime
    Computational Models of Narrative: Papers from the AAAI Fall Symposium (FS-10-04) Story Schemes for Argumentation about the Facts of a Crime Floris J. Bex1 and Bart Verheij2 1Argumentation Research Group, School of Computing, University of Dundee Dundee DD1 4HN, United Kingdom [email protected] 2Department of Artificial Intelligence, University of Groningen P.O. Box 407, 9700 AK Groningen, The Netherlands [email protected] Abstract In the theoretical literature on reasoning about the facts In the literature on reasoning on the basis of evidence, two of criminal cases, two perspectives are prevalent. The first traditions exist: one argument-based, and one based on goes back to Wigmore's work (Wigmore 1931) and has narratives. Recently, we have proposed a hybrid perspective been the basis for much work in the field of legal theory in which argumentation and narratives are combined. This (Anderson et al. 2005). In this argument-based tradition, formalized hybrid theory has been tested in a sense-making evidence is treated as giving reasons for and against the software prototype for criminal investigators and decision facts of the case. In argumentative reasoning, one performs makers. In the present paper, we elaborate on the role of consecutive reasoning steps from the evidence to the facts commonsense knowledge. We argue that two kinds of in issue, using commonsense knowledge to warrant the knowledge are essential: argumentation schemes and story inference steps. By evaluating the justificatory force of schemes. We discuss some of the research issues that need to be addressed. reasons (which depends on the warranting generalizations) and by resolving conflicts between reasons (e.g.
    [Show full text]
  • Innovation As Argumentation in Closed and Technology-Mediated Open Models
    Innovation as Argumentation in Closed and Technology-mediated Open Models Emmanuel D. Adamides1, Nikos I. Karacapilidis1 and Konstantinos Konstantinopoulos1,2 1Industrial Management and Information Systems Lab, MEAD, University of Patras, 26504 Rio Patras, Greece 2Supply Unique S.A., Coffee Island, 26334 Patras, Greece Keywords: Activity Theory, Open Innovation, Technology-mediated Argumentation, Food & Beverages Sector. Abstract: The paper uses activity theory and Activity Based Analysis (ABA) for understanding the contradictions developing, and the corresponding remedial actions required, in the transition of an organization from the closed to the technology-mediated open mode of innovation production. We use activity theory to develop nested representations of the innovation process in both business models, and concentrate on the argumentation-in-innovation activity and its context. We demonstrate the application of ABA in the analysis of contradictions developing in the argumentation processes of a firm in the food and beverages sector adopting open innovation strategies implemented in the innovation community mode. 1 INTRODUCTION creating activity and can be mediated by the technological means employed for exercising it. In a process view, innovation is the result of a series Specific forms of argument exercised frequently, or of coarse-grain interlinked activities (idea by powerful actors, become dominant schemes, generation, selection and conceptualization of characteristics of the organisational discourse (Potter product/service/process, technical development, and Wetherell, 1987), in general, and of innovation launch, value appropriation, etc. (Tidd and Bessant, processes in particular. 2014)), in which “knowledgeable and creative The aim of this paper is to investigate how such people and organizational units frame problems and dominant argumentation schemes influence the select, integrate, and augment information to create general context of the innovation production understanding and answers” (Teece, 2001).
    [Show full text]
  • Peirce Knew Why Abduction Isn't IBE—A Scheme and Critical Questions
    Argumentation https://doi.org/10.1007/s10503-017-9443-9 Peirce Knew Why Abduction Isn’t IBE—A Scheme and Critical Questions for Abductive Argument 1 1,2,3,4 Shiyang Yu • Frank Zenker Ó The Author(s) 2017. This article is an open access publication Abstract Whether abduction is treated as an argument or as an inference, the main- stream view presupposes a tight connection between abduction and inference to the best explanation (IBE). This paper critically evaluates this link and supports a nar- rower view on abduction. Our main thesis is that merely the hypothesis-generative aspect, but not the evaluative aspect, is properly abductive in the sense introduced by C. S. Peirce. We show why equating abduction with IBE (or understanding them as inseparable parts) unnecessarily complicates argument evaluation by levelling the status of abduction as a third reasoning mode (besides deduction and induction). We also propose a scheme for abductive argument along with critical questions, and suggest retaining abduction alongside IBE as related but distinct categories. Keywords Abduction Á Abductive argument Á Critical questions Á Inference to the best explanation Á Peirce Á Scheme 1 Introduction Introduced by Charles Sanders Peirce (1839–1914), ‘abduction’ refers to the creative generation of explanatory hypotheses. The term denotes an inference that is ‘‘frequently employed, in some form or other, both in everyday and in scientific & Frank Zenker frank.zenker@fil.lu.se 1 Department of Philosophy, Institute of Logic and Cognition, Sun Yat-sen University, 135 Xingang Road West, Guangzhou, People’s Republic of China 2 Philosophy and Cognitive Science, Lund University, 221 00 Lund, Sweden 3 Institute of Philosophy, SAS, Klemensova 19, 813 64 Bratislava, Slovakia 4 Department of Philosophy, Konstanz University, Postfach, D9, 78457 Constance, Germany 123 S.
    [Show full text]
  • Teaching As Abductive Reasoning: the Role of Argumentation Chrysi Rapanta
    Document généré le 30 sept. 2021 03:38 Informal Logic Teaching as Abductive Reasoning: The Role of Argumentation Chrysi Rapanta Volume 38, numéro 2, 2018 Résumé de l'article L'idée que l'argumentation est une pratique de raisonnement souhaitée en URI : https://id.erudit.org/iderudit/1057041ar classe est bien documentée dans la littérature. Néanmoins, il n'est toujours pas DOI : https://doi.org/10.22329/il.v38i2.4849 clair quel type de raisonnement soutient l'argumentation en classe. Dans cet article on discute du raisonnement abductif comme étant le plus adéquat pour Aller au sommaire du numéro que les arguments des élèves émergent dans une discussion en classe. Le raisonnement abductif emploie l'idée de plausibilité et de la révocabilité des prémisses et de la conclusion. En tant que tel, le rôle des enseignants consiste à Éditeur(s) guider les élèves à formuler des hypothèses pertinentes et à sélectionner le plus plausible selon des critères. Les schèmes d'argumentation sont proposés Informal Logic comme des outils utiles dans ce processus. ISSN 0824-2577 (imprimé) 2293-734X (numérique) Découvrir la revue Citer cet article Rapanta, C. (2018). Teaching as Abductive Reasoning: The Role of Argumentation. Informal Logic, 38(2), 293–311. https://doi.org/10.22329/il.v38i2.4849 Copyright (c), 2018 Chrysi Rapanta Ce document est protégé par la loi sur le droit d’auteur. L’utilisation des services d’Érudit (y compris la reproduction) est assujettie à sa politique d’utilisation que vous pouvez consulter en ligne. https://apropos.erudit.org/fr/usagers/politique-dutilisation/ Cet article est diffusé et préservé par Érudit.
    [Show full text]
  • My Continuing Journey from Logic to Computational Argumentation
    Felsefe Arkivi Archives of Philosophy Felsefe Arkivi - Archives of Philosophy, Sayı/Issue: 51, 2019 DOI: 10.26650/arcp2019-5123 Deneme / Essay My Continuing Journey from Logic to Computational Argumentation Douglas Walton1 ABSTRACT This paper begins with a brief account of how I started out as a young logician studying modal logic with the hope that it would be useful when applied to evaluating real examples of arguments found in natural language texts. The exposition moves on to relate how my interests shifted to the study of argumentation 1Prof. Dr., Institution, Faculty and/or in informal logic, and from there to computational systems combining defeasible Department, argumentation schemes with argument mapping (diagramming). The story ends City-Country, Centre for Research in Reasoning, Argumentation and Rhetoric, by leading to recent collaborations with three young logicians and computer University of Windsor, Canada scientists who are continuing on the path of my journey. Keywords: Argumentation, informal logic, history of logic, future of logic ORCID: D.W. 0000-0003-0728-1370 Sorumlu yazar/Corresponding author: Douglas Walton, Centre for Research in Reasoning, Argumentation and Rhetoric, University of Windsor, Canada E-mail/E-posta: [email protected] Başvuru/Submitted: 23.11.2019 Kabul/Accepted: 02.12.2019 Atıf/Citation: Walton, Douglas. (2019). “My Continuing Journey from Logic to Computational Argumentation” Felsefe Arkivi- Archives of Philosophy, 51: 321-330. https://doi.org/10.26650/arcp2019-5123 Introduction This paper begins in section 2 with a very brief account of how I started out as a young logician studying modal logic and was corrupted from this pure abstract pursuit by falling in with informal logicians, argumentation scholars and computer scientists who wanted to make logic into a partly practical discipline.
    [Show full text]