11429083 Lprob 1.Pdf

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Load more

LEIBNIZ AND THE ENGLISH-SPEAKING WORLD The New Synthese Historical Library Texts and Studies in the History of Philosophy VOLUME 62 Managing Editor: Simo Knuuttila, University of Helsinki Associate Editors: Daniel Elliot Garber, Princeton University Richard Sorabji, University of London Editorial Consultants: Jan A. Aertsen, Thomas-Institut, Universität zu Köln Roger Ariew, Virginia Polytechnic Institute E. Jennifer Ashworth, University of Waterloo Michael Ayers, Wadham College, Oxford Gail Fine, Cornell University R. J. Hankinson, University of Texas Jaakko Hintikka, Boston University Paul Hoffman, University of California, Riverside David Konstan, Brown University Richard H. Kraut, Northwestern University, Evanston Alain de Libera, Université de Genève John E. Murdoch, Harvard University David Fate Norton, McGill University Luca Obertello, Università degli Studi di Genova Eleonore Stump, St. Louis University Allen Wood, Stanford University The titles published in this series are listed at the end of this volume. LEIBNIZ AND THE ENGLISH-SPEAKING WORLD Edited by PAULINE PHEMISTER University of Edinburgh, Scotland, UK and STUART BROWN The Open University, Milton Keynes, UK A C.I.P. Catalogue record for this book is available from the Library of Congress. ISBN 978-1-4020-5242-2 (HB) ISBN 978-1-4020-5243-9 (e-book) Published by Springer, P.O. Box 17, 3300 AA Dordrecht, The Netherlands. www.springer.com Printed on acid-free paper All Rights Reserved © 2007 Springer No part of this work may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, microfilming, recording or otherwise, without written permission from the Publisher, with the exception of any material supplied specifically for the purpose of being entered and executed on a computer system, for exclusive use by the purchaser of the work. TABLE OF CONTENTS Contributors vii Abbreviations ix Preface xv 1. Leibniz and the English-Speaking World: An Introductory Overview 1 Stuart Brown and Pauline Phemister 2. Leibniz’s Debt to Hobbes 19 George MacDonald Ross 3. Two Opponents of Material Atomism: Cavendish and Leibniz 35 Catherine Wilson 4. Dalgarno, Wilkins, Leibniz and the Descriptive Nature of Metaphysical Concepts 51 Andreas Blank 5. “Un de mes amis.”: On Leibniz’s Relation to the English Mathematician and Theologian John Wallis 63 Philip Beeley 6. Leibniz and Robert Boyle: Reason and Faith: Rationalism and Voluntarism 83 Stuart Brown 7. Leibniz and the Cambridge Platonists: The Debate over Plastic Natures 95 Justin E. H. Smith and Pauline Phemister 8. Leibniz’s Nouveaux Essais: A Contest by Dialogue 111 Martha Brandt Bolton 9. Leibniz, Locke, and the Epistemology of Toleration 133 Nicholas Jolley v vi TABLE OF CONTENTS 10. “Is the Logic in London Different from the Logic in Hanover?”: Some Methodological Issues in Leibniz’s Dispute with the Newtonians over the Cause of Gravity 145 Gregory Brown 11. The Harmony of the Leibniz-Berkeley Juxtaposition 163 Stephen H. Daniel 12. Synechism and Monadology: Charles Sanders Peirce’s Reading of Leibniz 181 Evelyn Vargas 13. How did Bertrand Russell make Leibniz into a “Fellow Spirit”? 195 Norma B. Goethe 14. Leibniz and Russell: The Number of All Numbers and the Set of All Sets 207 Ohad Nachtomy 15. Leibniz and the Personalism of L. E. Loemker 219 Robert J. Mulvaney References 231 Index 241 CONTRIBUTORS Philip Beeley lectures in History of Science at the University of Hamburg and is editor of Leibniz’s philosophical writings and correspondence at the University of Münster. Andreas Blank is Visiting Fellow at the Cohn Institute for the History of Philosophy of Science and Ideas at Tel Aviv University, Israel. Martha Brandt Bolton is Professor of Philosophy at Rutgers University. Gregory Brown is Professor of Philosophy at the University of Houston, Texas. Stuart Brown is Emeritus Professor of Philosophy at the Open University. Stephen H. Daniel is Professor of Philosophy at TexasA&MUniversity. Norma B. Goethe is Professor of Philosophy at the School of Philosophy, National University of Cordoba, Argentina. Nicholas Jolley is Professor of Philosophy and Chair of the Philosophy Department at the University of California, Irvine. Robert J. Mulvaney is Distinguished Emeritus Professor of Philosophy at the University of South California. Ohad Nachtomy is Assistant Professor at Bar – Ilan University, Israel. Pauline Phemister is Lecturer in Philosophy at the University of Edinburgh. George MacDonald Ross is Senior Lecturer at the University of Leeds and Director of the Subject Centre for Philosophical and Religious Studies at the Higher Education Academy. Justin E. H. Smith is Associate Professor of Philosophy at Concordia University, Canada. vii viii CONTRIBUTORS Evelyn Vargas teaches in the Department of Philosophy, Universidad de La Plata, Argentina and is Adjunct Researcher for CONICET (Consejo Nacional de Investi- gaciones Cientificas y Tecnológicas). Catherine Wilson is Professor of Philosophy at the City University of New York and teaches in the Graduate Centre. ABBREVIATIONS A G. W. Leibniz: Sämtliche Schriften und Briefe. Berlin: Akademie Verlag, 1923–. Referred to by series, volume and page number. AA Kant’s Gesammelte Schriften. Göttingen: Akademie der Wissenschaften, 1902–. Referred to by volume and page number. AF David Hume: Writings on Religion. Ed. by A. Flew. La Salle, IL: Open Court 1992. AG G. W. Leibniz: Philosophical Essays. Ed. and trans. by R. Ariew and D. Garber. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett 1989. AS G. Dalgarno. Ars Signorum, Vulgo Character Universalis et Lingua Philo- sophica. London: J. Hayes 1661. AT Oeuvres de Descartes. Ed. by C. Adam and P. Tannery. Paris: J. Vrin 1964–74. Referred to by volume and page number. BB Die Briefwechsel des Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz in der Königlichen Öffentlichen Bibliothek zu Hannover. Ed. by E. Bodemann. Hannover: Hahn 1895. Reprinted Hildesheim: Olms 1966. BH Die Leibniz-Handschriften der Königlichen Öffentlichen Bibliothek zu Hannover. Ed. by E. Bodemann. Hannover: Hahn 1895. Reprinted Hildesheim: Olms 1966. C Opuscules et fragments inédits de Leibniz. Ed. by L. Couturat. Paris: Alcan 1903. Reprinted Hildesheim: Olms 1961. CL C. S. Peirce. Reasoning and the Logic of Things. The Cambridge Conferences of 1898. Ed. by K. L. Ketner and H. Putnam. Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press 1992. CN Charles Sanders Peirce. Contributions to “The Nation”. Ed. by K. L. Ketner and J. E. Cook. 4 vols. Lubbock: Texas Tech University Press 1975–87. ix x ABBREVIATIONS CP Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce. Ed. by C. Hartshorne, P. Weiss (vols 1–6), and A. Burks (vols 7–8). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press 1931–58. CSM The Philosophical Writings of Descartes. Ed. and trans. by J. Cottingham, R. Stoothoff, and D. Murdoch. 2 vols. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press 1984–85. Referred to by volume and page number. CW I. Newton. The Principia: Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy. Trans. by I. B. Cohen and A. Whitman. Los Angeles: University of California Press 1999. D G. W. Leibniz. Opera Omnia. Ed. by L. L. Dutens. 6 vols. Geneva 1768. Reprinted Hildesheim: Olms 1989. Referred to by volume and page number. DB George Berkeley: Alciphron, or the Minute Philosopher: In focus. Ed. by D. Berman. London and New York: Routledge 1993. E G. W. Leibniz. Opera Philosophica. Ed. by J. E. Erdmann. Berlin: Eichler 1840. EP The Essential Peirce. Selected Philosophical Writings. Ed. by N. Houser and C. J. W. Kloesel. 2 vols. Bloomington: Indiana University Press 1992–98. Referred to by volume and page number. ERC J. Wilkins. An Essay Towards a Real Character: And a Philosophical Language. London: S. Gellibrand 1668. Cited by part, chapter, section and page. Essay J. Locke. An Essay Concerning Human Understanding. Ed. by P. H. Nidditch. Oxford: Clarendon Press 1975. Referred to by book, chapter, and section. F The Works of George Berkeley. Ed. by A. C. Fraser. 4 vols. Oxford: Clarendon Press 1901. Cited by volume and page number. FC Nouvelles lettres et opuscules inédits de Leibniz. Ed. by A. Foucher de Careil. Paris: Durand 1857. Reprinted Hildesheim: Olms 1971. FCO Oeuvres de Leibniz. Ed. by A. Foucher de Careil. 7 vols. Paris: Firmin Didot Frères 1859–75. Referred to by volume and page number. ABBREVIATIONS xi GG J. Toland. Letters to Serena [1704]. Ed. by G. Gawlick. Stuttgart-Bad Cannstatt: Friedrich Frommann 1964. GK J. Locke. Epistola de Tolerantia/ A Letter on Toleration. Ed. by J. W. Gough and R. Klibansky. Oxford: Clarendon Press 1968. GM Leibnizens Mathematische Schriften. Ed. by C. I. Gerhardt. 7 vols. Berlin: A. Asher and Halle: H. W. Schmidt 1849–63. Reprinted Hildesheim: Olms 1965. Referred to by volume and page number. GP Die Philosophischen Schriften von Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz. Ed. by C. I. Gerhardt. 7 vols. Berlin: Weidmann 1875–90. Reprinted Hildesheim: Olms 1965. Referred to by volume and page number. Gr G. W. Leibniz: Textes inédits d’après les manuscrits de la Biblio- thèque provinciale d’Hanovre. Ed. by G. Grua. 2 vols. Paris: Presses Universitaires de France 1948. Referred to by volume and page number. GW Briefwechsel zwischen Leibniz und Christian Wolff. Ed. by C. I. Gerhardt. Halle: Schmidt 1860. Reprinted Hildesheim: Olms 1963. HD The Works of Robert Boyle. Ed. by M. Hunter and E. B. Davis. 14 vols. London: Pickering and Chatto 1999–2000. Referred to by volume and page number. HF G. W. Leibniz. Theodicy: Essays on the Goodness of God, the Freedom of Man and the Origin of Evil. Ed. by A Farrer. Trans. by E. M. Huggard. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul 1951. Re-published Peru, IL: Open Court 1985. HGA The Leibniz-Clarke Correspondence. Ed. and trans. by H. G. Alexander. Manchester, UK: Manchester University Press 1956. HH The Correspondence of Henry Oldenburg. Ed. by A. R. Hall and M. B. Hall. 13 vols. Madison: University of Wisconsin Press; London: Mansell; London and Philadelphia: Taylor and Francis, 1965–86 Referred to by volume and page number.
Recommended publications
  • A Prologue to Charles Sanders Peirce's Theory of Signs

    A Prologue to Charles Sanders Peirce's Theory of Signs

    In Lieu of Saussure: A Prologue to Charles Sanders Peirce’s Theory of Signs E. San Juan, Jr. Language is as old as consciousness, language is practical consciousness that exists also for other men, and for that reason alone it really exists for me personally as well; language, like consciousness, only arises from the need, the necessity, of intercourse with other men. – Karl Marx, The German Ideology (1845-46) General principles are really operative in nature. Words [such as Patrick Henry’s on liberty] then do produce physical effects. It is madness to deny it. The very denial of it involves a belief in it. – C.S. Peirce, Harvard Lectures on Pragmatism (1903) The era of Saussure is dying, the epoch of Peirce is just struggling to be born. Although pragmatism has been experiencing a renaissance in philosophy in general in the last few decades, Charles Sanders Peirce, the “inventor” of this anti-Cartesian, scientific- realist method of clarifying meaning, still remains unacknowledged as a seminal genius, a polymath master-thinker. William James’s vulgarized version has overshadowed Peirce’s highly original theory of “pragmaticism” grounded on a singular conception of semiotics. Now recognized as more comprehensive and heuristically fertile than Saussure’s binary semiology (the foundation of post-structuralist textualisms) which Cold War politics endorsed and popularized, Peirce’s “semeiotics” (his preferred rubric) is bound to exert a profound revolutionary influence. Peirce’s triadic sign-theory operates within a critical- realist framework opposed to nominalism and relativist nihilism (Liszka 1996). I endeavor to outline here a general schema of Peirce’s semeiotics and initiate a hypothetical frame for interpreting Michael Ondaatje’s Anil’s’ Ghost, an exploratory or Copyright © 2012 by E.
  • A Philosophical Commentary on Cs Peirce's “On a New List

    A Philosophical Commentary on Cs Peirce's “On a New List

    The Pennsylvania State University The Graduate School College of the Liberal Arts A PHILOSOPHICAL COMMENTARY ON C. S. PEIRCE'S \ON A NEW LIST OF CATEGORIES": EXHIBITING LOGICAL STRUCTURE AND ABIDING RELEVANCE A Dissertation in Philosophy by Masato Ishida °c 2009 Masato Ishida Submitted in Partial Ful¯lment of the Requirements for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy August 2009 The dissertation of Masato Ishida was reviewed and approved¤ by the following: Vincent M. Colapietro Professor of Philosophy Dissertation Advisor Chair of Committee Dennis Schmidt Professor of Philosophy Christopher P. Long Associate Professor of Philosophy Director of Graduate Studies for the Department of Philosophy Stephen G. Simpson Professor of Mathematics ¤ Signatures are on ¯le in the Graduate School. ii ABSTRACT This dissertation focuses on C. S. Peirce's relatively early paper \On a New List of Categories"(1867). The entire dissertation is devoted to an extensive and in-depth analysis of this single paper in the form of commentary. All ¯fteen sections of the New List are examined. Rather than considering the textual genesis of the New List, or situating the work narrowly in the early philosophy of Peirce, as previous scholarship has done, this work pursues the genuine philosophical content of the New List, while paying attention to the later philosophy of Peirce as well. Immanuel Kant's Critique of Pure Reason is also taken into serious account, to which Peirce contrasted his new theory of categories. iii Table of Contents List of Figures . ix Acknowledgements . xi General Introduction 1 The Subject of the Dissertation . 1 Features of the Dissertation .
  • Peirce for Whitehead Handbook

    Peirce for Whitehead Handbook

    For M. Weber (ed.): Handbook of Whiteheadian Process Thought Ontos Verlag, Frankfurt, 2008, vol. 2, 481-487 Charles S. Peirce (1839-1914) By Jaime Nubiola1 1. Brief Vita Charles Sanders Peirce [pronounced "purse"], was born on 10 September 1839 in Cambridge, Massachusetts, to Sarah and Benjamin Peirce. His family was already academically distinguished, his father being a professor of astronomy and mathematics at Harvard. Though Charles himself received a graduate degree in chemistry from Harvard University, he never succeeded in obtaining a tenured academic position. Peirce's academic ambitions were frustrated in part by his difficult —perhaps manic-depressive— personality, combined with the scandal surrounding his second marriage, which he contracted soon after his divorce from Harriet Melusina Fay. He undertook a career as a scientist for the United States Coast Survey (1859- 1891), working especially in geodesy and in pendulum determinations. From 1879 through 1884, he was a part-time lecturer in Logic at Johns Hopkins University. In 1887, Peirce moved with his second wife, Juliette Froissy, to Milford, Pennsylvania, where in 1914, after 26 years of prolific and intense writing, he died of cancer. He had no children. Peirce published two books, Photometric Researches (1878) and Studies in Logic (1883), and a large number of papers in journals in widely differing areas. His manuscripts, a great many of which remain unpublished, run to some 100,000 pages. In 1931-58, a selection of his writings was arranged thematically and published in eight volumes as the Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce. Beginning in 1982, a number of volumes have been published in the series A Chronological Edition, which will ultimately consist of thirty volumes.
  • Peirce, Pragmatism, and the Right Way of Thinking

    Peirce, Pragmatism, and the Right Way of Thinking

    SANDIA REPORT SAND2011-5583 Unlimited Release Printed August 2011 Peirce, Pragmatism, and The Right Way of Thinking Philip L. Campbell Prepared by Sandia National Laboratories Albuquerque, New Mexico 87185 and Livermore, California 94550 Sandia National Laboratories is a multi-program laboratory managed and operated by Sandia Corporation, a wholly owned subsidiary of Lockheed Martin Corporation, for the U.S. Department of Energy’s National Nuclear Security Administration under Contract DE-AC04-94AL85000.. Approved for public release; further dissemination unlimited. Issued by Sandia National Laboratories, operated for the United States Department of Energy by Sandia Corporation. NOTICE: This report was prepared as an account of work sponsored by an agency of the United States Government. Neither the United States Government, nor any agency thereof, nor any of their employees, nor any of their contractors, subcontractors, or their employees, make any warranty, express or implied, or assume any legal liability or responsibility for the accuracy, completeness, or usefulness of any information, apparatus, product, or process disclosed, or represent that its use would not infringe privately owned rights. Reference herein to any specific commercial product, process, or service by trade name, trademark, manufacturer, or otherwise, does not necessarily con- stitute or imply its endorsement, recommendation, or favoring by the United States Government, any agency thereof, or any of their contractors or subcontractors. The views and opinions expressed herein do not necessarily state or reflect those of the United States Government, any agency thereof, or any of their contractors. Printed in the United States of America. This report has been reproduced directly from the best available copy.
  • Charles S. Peirce's Conservative Progressivism

    Charles S. Peirce's Conservative Progressivism

    Charles S. Peirce's Conservative Progressivism Author: Yael Levin Hungerford Persistent link: http://hdl.handle.net/2345/bc-ir:107167 This work is posted on eScholarship@BC, Boston College University Libraries. Boston College Electronic Thesis or Dissertation, 2016 Copyright is held by the author, with all rights reserved, unless otherwise noted. Charles S. Peirce’s Conservative Progressivism Yael Levin Hungerford A dissertation submitted to the Faculty of the department of Political Science in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy Boston College Morrissey College of Arts and Sciences Graduate School June 2016 © copyright 2016 Yael Levin Hungerford CHARLES S. PEIRCE’S CONSERVATIVE PROGRESSIVISM Yael Levin Hungerford Advisor: Nasser Behnegar My dissertation explores the epistemological and political thought of Charles S. Peirce, the founder of American pragmatism. In contrast to the pragmatists who followed, Peirce defends a realist notion of truth. He seeks to provide a framework for understanding the nature of knowledge that does justice to our commonsense experience of things. Similarly in contrast to his fellow pragmatists, Peirce has a conservative practical teaching: he warns against combining theory and practice out of concern that each will corrupt the other. The first three chapters of this dissertation examine Peirce’s pragmatism and related features of his thought: his Critical Common-Sensism, Scholastic Realism, semeiotics, and a part of his metaphysical or cosmological musings. The fourth chapter explores Peirce’s warning that theory and practice ought to be kept separate. The fifth chapter aims to shed light on Peirce’s practical conservatism by exploring the liberal arts education he recommends for educating future statesmen.
  • Charles Sanders Peirce - Wikipedia, the Free Encyclopedia 9/2/10 4:55 PM

    Charles Sanders Peirce - Wikipedia, the Free Encyclopedia 9/2/10 4:55 PM

    Charles Sanders Peirce - Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia 9/2/10 4:55 PM Charles Sanders Peirce From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia Charles Sanders Peirce (pronounced /ˈpɜrs/ purse[1]) Charles Sanders Peirce (September 10, 1839 – April 19, 1914) was an American philosopher, logician, mathematician, and scientist, born in Cambridge, Massachusetts. Peirce was educated as a chemist and employed as a scientist for 30 years. It is largely his contributions to logic, mathematics, philosophy, and semiotics (and his founding of pragmatism) that are appreciated today. In 1934, the philosopher Paul Weiss called Peirce "the most original and versatile of American philosophers and America's greatest logician".[2] An innovator in many fields (including philosophy of science, epistemology, metaphysics, mathematics, statistics, research methodology, and the design of experiments in astronomy, geophysics, and psychology) Peirce considered himself a logician first and foremost. He made major contributions to logic, but logic for him encompassed much of that which is now called epistemology and philosophy of science. He saw logic as the Charles Sanders Peirce formal branch of semiotics, of which he is a founder. As early as 1886 he saw that logical operations could be carried out by Born September 10, 1839 electrical switching circuits, an idea used decades later to Cambridge, Massachusetts produce digital computers.[3] Died April 19, 1914 (aged 74) Milford, Pennsylvania Contents Nationality American 1 Life Fields Logic, Mathematics, 1.1 United States Coast Survey Statistics, Philosophy, 1.2 Johns Hopkins University Metrology, Chemistry 1.3 Poverty Religious Episcopal but 2 Reception 3 Works stance unconventional 4 Mathematics 4.1 Mathematics of logic C.
  • Peirce on the Medievals: Realism, Power and Form Peirce Acerca Dos Medievais: Realismo, Poder E Forma

    Peirce on the Medievals: Realism, Power and Form Peirce Acerca Dos Medievais: Realismo, Poder E Forma

    Peirce on the Medievals: Realism, Power and Form Peirce acerca dos Medievais: Realismo, Poder e Forma John Boler University of Washington [email protected] Abstract: In the first section, I discuss Peirce’s ambivalence attitude towards medieval thinkers – some high praise, some harsh criticism. In the second, I consider three criticisms Max Fisch mde of my book Charles Peirce and Scholastic Realism. My book had presented Peirce’s realism as if it were a single position from first to last. And I want to adjust that in the light of Fisch’s points. I now want to distinguish his scholastic realism from his on- going development of realism. To this end, I offer a more restricted and precise meaning to “scholastic realism” – roughly an anti-platonism in which the common nature is found as an element in things. That meaning does, I think, remain constant for Peirce; though I agree with Fisch that this is only a part of his developing realism. In the third section, I bring out the connection between the scholastic notion of potentiality and Peirce’s “would- be’s.” Interestingly enough (to me), this is not an influence that Peirce himself acknowledges. I also point out there that Peirce is rather dismissive of the scholastic notion of form, which he thinks is a perversion of Aristotle’s more useful (if vague) position. Keywords: Realism. Potentiality. Form. Matter. Resumo: Na primeira seção, discuto a atitude ambivalente de Peirce para com os pensadores medievais – algumas avaliações elogiosas, algumas críticas duras. Na segunda parte, considero três críticas feitas por Max Fisch ao meu livro Charles Peirce and Scholastic Realism.
  • Was Peirce An" Educational" Philosopher?

    Was Peirce An" Educational" Philosopher?

    DOCUMENT RESUME ED 054 726 HE 002 519 AUTHOR McCarthy, Joseph M. TITLE Was Peirce an "Educati nal" Phi_osopher? PUB DATE 3 Jun 71 NOTE 16p.; Paper presented at the annual meetingof the New England Educational Research Organization,June 3,1971 EDRS PRICE ME-$0,65 HC-$3.29 DESCRIPTORS *Educational History; *EducationalPhilosophy; *Higher Education; *Institutional Role; *Teachin IDENTIFIERS *Peirce (Charles Sanders) ABSTRACT Charles Sanders Peirce, the progenitorof an entire school of philosophy, profoundly influencedour educational system, yet was curiously silenton educational questions. This paper discusses his early upbringing and schooling,and his involvement in education as a lecturer and professor.The major focus is on Peir-e's written thoughts on education, whichwere sparse. The longest of these was in the form ofa letter to Daniel Coit Gilman, written January 13, 1878. It expresses Peirce's thoughtson the organization and administration of an- academic department,as veil as his conviction that in the teaching of science"the professor's object ought to be to let his pupilas much into the interior of scientific thinking as possible, and for thatpurpose he should make his lecture experiments resemble realones as much as possible." He felt that students who intended to be physicistsshould be in a laboratory situation from aboutage 9 to 12 and then return at 18 or 20. Peirce also wrote on mathematical logic andits relation to education, atd on the nature of the university. He alsogave consideration to teaching mathematics. His thoughtson education were systematic and evolved in the li ht of his "pragmatic" principles. (All WAS.PEIRCE AN "EDUCATIONAL" PHILOSOPHER? Joseph Ma McCarthy Paper Presented at the New England Educational Research Organization Convention, 6/3/71 U.S.
  • Metaphysical Problems of Physics Lecture 9: Necessity and Causality

    Metaphysical Problems of Physics Lecture 9: Necessity and Causality

    Metaphysical Problems of Physics Lecture 9: Necessity and Causality Erik Curiel† (date of notes: 29. Jun 2021) Contents 1 Chakravartty’s A Metaphysics for Scientific Realism 2 1.1 Where He’s Coming From: The Intoxicating Thrill of Realism............2 1.2 Causal Realism and Causal Processes..........................5 2 Peirce’s “The Doctrine of Necessity Examined”8 2.1 Where He’s Coming From: The Salubrious Invigoration of Pragmatism.......8 2.2 The Doctrine of Necessity................................9 3 Invitation to a Short Essay9 References 9 Those who make causality one of the original uralt elements in the universe or one of the fundamental categories of thought,—of whom you will find that I am not one,— have one very awkward fact to explain away. It is that men’s conceptions of a Cause are in different stages of scientific culture entirely different and inconsistent. The great principle of causation which we are told, it is absolutely impossible not to believe, has been one proposition at one period of history and an entirely disparate one another and is still a third one for the modern physicist. The only thing about it which has stood, to use my friend Carus’ word, a kt¨ma ἐς ἀεί,—semper eadem—is the name of it. – Peirce Reasoning and the Logic of Things, Lecture 6 †Author’s address: Munich Center for Mathematical Philosophy, Ludwig-Maximilians-Universität; Black Hole Initiative, Harvard University; email: [email protected] 1 Lecture 9: Necessity and Causality 29. Jun 2021 1 Chakravartty’s A Metaphysics for Scientific Realism 1.1 Where He’s Coming From: The Intoxicating Thrill of Realism Background to Realism 1.
  • Some Views of Russell and Russell's Logic by His

    Some Views of Russell and Russell's Logic by His

    SOME VIEWS OF RUSSELL AND RUSSELL’S LOGIC BY HIS CONTEMPORARIES, WITH PARTICULAR REFERENCE TO PEIRCE IRVING H. ANELLIS In the years prior to World War I, it was not yet definitively certain that the new logistic developed and espoused by Frege and Russell was the “wave of the future” of mathematical logic. Ernst Schröder’s Vorlesungen über die Algebra der Logik (1895– 1905) was still new and viewed as the cutting edge of (algebraic—as opposed to Aristote- lian) logic; Giuseppe Peano still proclaimed, in his earliest work on logic, his indebted- ness to George Boole, Charles Peirce, and Ernst Schröder, in the first footnote of his Arithmetices principia nova methodo exposita (1898), while, in a letter to Russell of 19 March 1901,1 Peano told Russell that his paper “Sur la logique des relations avec des ap- plications à la théorie des séries” on the logic of relations (1901) just “fills a gap between the work of Peirce and Schröder on the one hand and” his own “Formulaire on the other;” Alfred North Whitehead’s Treatise on Universal Algebra (1898) also still new, brought together the algebraic logic of Boole with the linear and multilinear algebras of Arthur Cayley, James Joseph Sylvester, William Rowan Hamilton, and Charles Peirce’s father Benjamin Peirce, and the calculus of extension of Hermann Grassmann. In his Treatise, Whitehead (p. x) not only named Hamilton and De Morgan as “the first to ex- press quite clearly the general possibilities of algebraic symbolism,” but continually ex- pressed his indebtedness to Boole, Grassmann, De Morgan, Schröder, and John Venn; and he described his Treatise (p.
  • The Statistics of Causal Inference in the Social Sciences1 Political Science 236A Statistics 239A

    The Statistics of Causal Inference in the Social Sciences1 Political Science 236A Statistics 239A

    The Statistics of Causal Inference in the Social Sciences1 Political Science 236A Statistics 239A Jasjeet S. Sekhon UC Berkeley October 29, 2014 1 c Copyright 2014 1 / 765 Background We are concerned with causal inference in the social • sciences. We discuss the potential outcomes framework of causal • inference in detail. This framework originates with Jerzy Neyman (1894-1981), • the founder of the Berkeley Statistics Department. A key insight of the framework is that causal inference is a • missing data problem. The framework applies regardless of the method used to • estimate causal effects, whether it be quantitative or qualitative. 2 / 765 Background We are concerned with causal inference in the social • sciences. We discuss the potential outcomes framework of causal • inference in detail. This framework originates with Jerzy Neyman (1894-1981), • the founder of the Berkeley Statistics Department. A key insight of the framework is that causal inference is a • missing data problem. The framework applies regardless of the method used to • estimate causal effects, whether it be quantitative or qualitative. 3 / 765 The Problem Many of the great minds of the 18th and 19th centuries • contributed to the development of social statistics: De Moivre, several Bernoullis, Gauss, Laplace, Quetelet, Galton, Pearson, and Yule. They searched for a method of statistical calculus that • would do for social studies what Leibniz’s and Newton’s calculus did for physics. It quickly came apparent this is would be most difficult. • For example: deficits crowding out money versus • chemotherapy 4 / 765 The Problem Many of the great minds of the 18th and 19th centuries • contributed to the development of social statistics: De Moivre, several Bernoullis, Gauss, Laplace, Quetelet, Galton, Pearson, and Yule.
  • C. S. Peirce and Abduction Inference Alex Beckwith Johnson County Community College, Abeckwi1@Stumail.Jccc.Edu

    C. S. Peirce and Abduction Inference Alex Beckwith Johnson County Community College, [email protected]

    JCCC Honors Journal Volume 10 Article 2 Issue 1 Fall 2018 C. S. Peirce and Abduction Inference Alex Beckwith Johnson County Community College, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarspace.jccc.edu/honors_journal Recommended Citation Beckwith, Alex () "C. S. Peirce and Abduction Inference," JCCC Honors Journal: Vol. 10 : Iss. 1 , Article 2. Available at: https://scholarspace.jccc.edu/honors_journal/vol10/iss1/2 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Honors Program at ScholarSpace @ JCCC. It has been accepted for inclusion in JCCC Honors Journal by an authorized editor of ScholarSpace @ JCCC. For more information, please contact [email protected]. C. S. Peirce and Abduction Inference Abstract Charles Sanders Peirce remains a largely forgotten American original thinker, whose interests and accomplishments span various disciplines in philosophy, mathematics, and science. He considered himself, first and foremost, a logician and claimed to have discovered a new logical method of analysis. In addition to the forms of deduction and induction that date back to Aristotle, Peirce’s new method became known as abduction. Never satisfied, he kept changing his terminology and his intentions about what this new method was supposed to do. He tried to demonstrate how abduction worked at least a couple of times, but his explanations were never fully worked out and had problems. Today, abduction is used as a synonym for what philosopher Gilbert Harman called “inference to the best explanation.” My paper draws from both primary and secondary sources to give a high-level overview of abduction for a general reader who has taken an introductory logic class.