ADDITIONAL STUDIES on ANAXIMANDER in These

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

ADDITIONAL STUDIES on ANAXIMANDER in These APPENDIX ADDITIONAL STUDIES ON ANAXIMANDER In these paragraphs we shall briefly discuss studies on Anaximander which became available after our book was completed. In "L'uno-molti naturalismo degli lonici. Prima puntata: Da Talete ad Anassimandro," Sophia, 36 (1968), 56-97, Mirella Carbonara Naddei investigates the texts of the Ionian philosophers in the light of recent interpretations (e.g., Gomperz, Jaeger, Robin, Franchini) on the occasion of the publication of A. Maddalena's Ionici. Testimonianze e frammenti (Firenze: La Nuova Italia, 1963). In place of Maddalena's dualistic inter­ pretation (see pp. 57, 70, 81, 88) and Aristotle's monistic interpretation (see p. 57), Carbonara Naddei opts for a dialectical understanding of the texts (see pp. 57,58,66,67 for mention of Hegel). With reference to Anax­ imander (pp. 75-97), this option allows to apeiron to entail opposing factors simultaneously. The apeiron is by nature indeterminate and yet it actually and organically contains hot and cold and other opposites (see pp. 80-81). It is the material cause of things, as well as their active principle through an internal dynamism (p. 79). It surrounds and governs them all, while simultaneously serving as their substrate. Thus it is at once container and contained (pp. 82-84). It is one and yet many: "L'infinito e uno ed e il principio come momento attivo e divino che circonda e govern a tutte Ie cose, e come cio che tutte Ie contiene, concretamente ed attualmente sede e vita della molteplicita. II problema di questo filosofo di Mileto non si puo risolvere ... [except] accettando la posizione di una unita dinamica che e unita, ma in quanto simultaneita del tutto, e quindi anche molte­ plicita" (p. 83). It dialectically joins simultaneity with succession, passivity with activity, actuality in eternity with potentiality in time (p. 88), im­ mutability with transformation, identity with otherness (p. 90). It harmon­ izes transcendence with immanence. In the guise of Time it serves both as judge and as the place where injustices occur and expiation takes place: one must "intendere il tempo come una realta trascendente e immanente ADDITIONAL STUDIES 181 insieme, trascendente, in quanto e giudice che ordina un'espazione; im­ manente, in quanto sede dell'espiazione stessa e, innanzi tutto, come principio della stessa colpevolezza. II tempo, potremmo dire con termino­ logia moderna, heideggeriana, e la struttura dell'esistenza: colpa, castigo, riscatto non al di sopra della vita, rna nell'ima profundita della vita stessa" (p. 96). All this contrasting alignment is possible because of Carbonara Naddei's dialectical conception of Anaximander. But how valid is it? It is, I would say, an anachronism. Anaximander is not Hegel or Heidegger or, even, Heraclitus. Even so, she could have made her point much more briefly and succinctly. Another study which we became acquainted with only after the manu­ script of our book was at the publisher is Rosario Conti's Cosmogonie orientali e filosofia presocratica (Roma: Editrice Ciranna, n. d.). This volume was triggered by Conti's distress at Western ignorance of the relationship between oriental culture and the occidental philosophical speculation initiated by the Presocratics (p. 4). Parting company with Roth and Gladisch, who exaggerated the debt of the Presocratics to their oriental predecessors, and also with Zeller, who saw no debt at all, Conti takes the middle road. He is convinced that a scientific or philosophic system is not created but develops from primitive sources, which it transcends however (pp. 4-5). Accordingly, the rational method of the Presocratics is a con­ tinuation of the thrust of mythical cosmogonies of the Orient, which nonetheless it enriches and organizes, thus giving the illusion of being an original creation (p. 5: "II me to do razionale dei Presocratici non fara che continuare 10 sforzo delle cosmogonie mitiche delI'Oriente, arricchendole di nuove ricerche e di nuove impostazioni, dando cosi l'illusione di una creazione completamente origin ale e quasi spontanea"). As one would expect his book consists of two parts, the first of which (pp. 9-164) recounts cosmogonical myths from India, Iran, Mesopotamia, Egypt, Israel and Greece. The second (pp. 165-470) takes up the Pre­ socratic philosophers from Thales to the Atomists. The chapter on Anax­ imander is, of course, found there (pp. 193-206) and consists of four sections: "Vita e Opere:' "To Apeiron," "Pluralita di mondi," and "Af­ finita mitiche." Let us concentrate briefly upon some points in the last three. The principle from which all things have originated is the Infinite, a single reality which is not any particular element or any substance inter­ mediate between the elements. Rather, it is a primal, ungenerated, eternal principle which sustains and directs all things and which grounds an in­ exhaustible and perpetual process of generation (p. 196: "l'lnfinito (to 182 ADDITIONAL STUDIES apeiron) una realta che non PUQ essere un elemento particolare, ... ne una so stanza intermedia tra questo e quell'elemento, ma un principio originario, ingenerato, eterno, che sostiene e dirige tutte Ie case, la con­ dizione delle indifettibile perpetuita delle generazioni"). But in what sense is that principle infinite? In size, as qualitatively indeterminate (ibid.; "un infinito per grandezza, che e nello stesso tempo qualitativamente indeter­ minato"), in duration (p. 197: "I'infinita temporale") and as a bottomless resource of existents (ibid.: "la reserva inesauribile del divenire"). It is, then, "una sostanza unica, infinita per grandezza e priva di specificazione, dinamica per tendenza" (ibid.). Moreover, it is the origin of infinite worlds, which co-exist in it but separately and without knowledge of one another (pp. 200-201). As the primordial abyss and unformed matter from which all things come about, the Infinite is like Chaos in oriental and Grecian cosmogonies and, even, in the Orphic tradition, which pictures Chaos as "eternal, limitless, 'ageless and imperishable,' as neither darkness nor light nor wet nor dry nor hot nor cold but all those factors mingled to­ gether in a formless whole" (p. 203). In fact, we need not stop there: factors are also found in Sumerian, Egyptian and Brahmanic cosmogonies which are similar to the Infinite or Chaos (p. 204). Comments. Conti seems to have strayed from the middle of the exegeti­ cal road (see p. 4) by exaggerating the influence of the Orient upon Anax­ imander. Certainly, to apeiron does resemble Chaos and one can easily understand how Hesiod could have influenced the Greek philosopher. But to conclude that the counterparts of the Grecian Chaos in Sumerian, Egyptian and Hindu cosmogonies actually exerted influence on him one needs proof, which is absent because documentation is lacking. The In­ finite could be similar to factors in them without having historically origin­ ated from them. On most occasions Conti seems to have forgotten his own advice that since Anaximander's own treatise is not extant, one should realize that what subsequent writers credit to him is marked by uncertainty, lacunae, and doubts (p. 196). He might well have imitated D. R. Dicks' scepticism on the validity of the doxographicaI accounts (see D. R. Dicks, "Thales," CQ, 9 [1959], 294-309 and "Solstices, Equinoxes, and the Pre­ socratics," IRS, 86 n9661, 26-40), but unfortunately he seems unaware of Dicks' articles. (But see C. H. Kahn, IHS, 90 [1970], 99-116). A third study worthy of mention was actually published before either Naddei's or Conti's but it became available only subsequently: Osvaldo N. Guariglia, "Anaximandro de Mileto Fragmento B 1 (Diels-Kranz)," Anales de Filologia Cldsica. 9 0964-1965), 23-155. As Guariglia explains in the final section of his article (pp. lSI-52), one may attempt to reconstruct a ADDITIONAL STUDIES 183 position in early Greek thought exteriorly. Then one sees it as a historical development from myths and as affected by the cultural, social, economic and political circumstances in ancient Ionia. But reconstruction can also be internal, whereby one reflects upon the extant textual fragments them­ selves of the Greek authors. Then one studies the language and modes of expression which they. as well as their predecessors and contemporaries, used so that he can grasp "coherencia y comprension de la totalidad" (p. 152). This latter method Guariglia himself chose. In an introductory section (pp. 23-30) he discusses the main textual sources of information on Anaximander: Simplicius. Hippolytus. Pseudo-Plutarch, Aetius and Dioge­ nes, all of whom depend upon Theophrastus. In the first part (pp. 31-49) of the main body of the article he investigates all the relevant texts from Aristotle's Physics. Metaphysics and De Generatiane. In the second part (pp. 49-87) he turns to Theophrastus. seeking to distinguish passages in which Theophrastus merely repeats Aristotle from those in which he transmits original information (p. 52). The final part on Anaximander's Fragment (DK B I) is itself subdivided into considerations of the context of the Fragment (pp. 92-102), its extent (pp. 102-117) and its interpretation (pp. 118-52). Guariglia's informative study is valuable for many reasons, not the least of which are his careful analysis of the texts relating to Anaximander and other Greek authors and his thorough awareness of modern and contemporary interpretations from scholars on every continent. But he spends relatively little time on fa apeiran itself-a fact which is not surprising in view of his conviction that Anaximander's own treatise offered little information on the nature of the apeiran (p. 43: for a survey of that scanty data see pp. 43-44. 53-56) and even that information was gravely disfigured by Aristotle and Theophrastus (pp. 56, 85-87). He does give considerable attention to topics textually linked with ta apeiran, though: ta ganimon (pp.
Recommended publications
  • Zeno of Elea: Where Space, Time, Physics, and Philosophy Converge
    Western Kentucky University TopSCHOLAR® Honors College Capstone Experience/Thesis Honors College at WKU Projects Fall 2007 Zeno of Elea: Where Space, Time, Physics, and Philosophy Converge An Everyman’s Introduction to an Unsung Hero of Philosophy William Turner Western Kentucky University Follow this and additional works at: http://digitalcommons.wku.edu/stu_hon_theses Part of the Other Philosophy Commons, Other Physics Commons, and the Philosophy of Science Commons Recommended Citation Turner, William, "Zeno of Elea: Where Space, Time, Physics, and Philosophy Converge An Everyman’s Introduction to an Unsung Hero of Philosophy" (2007). Honors College Capstone Experience/Thesis Projects. Paper 111. http://digitalcommons.wku.edu/stu_hon_theses/111 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by TopSCHOLAR®. It has been accepted for inclusion in Honors College Capstone Experience/ Thesis Projects by an authorized administrator of TopSCHOLAR®. For more information, please contact [email protected]. P │ S─Z─T │ P Zeno of Elea: Where Space, Time, Physics, and Philosophy Converge An Everyman’s Introduction to an Unsung Hero of Philosophy Will Turner Western Kentucky University Abstract Zeno of Elea, despite being among the most important of the Pre-Socratic philosophers, is frequently overlooked by philosophers and scientists alike in modern times. Zeno of Elea’s arguments on have not only been an impetus for the most important scientific and mathematical theories in human history, his arguments still serve as a basis for modern problems and theoretical speculations. This is a study of his arguments on motion, the purpose they have served in the history of science, and modern applications of Zeno of Elea’s arguments on motion.
    [Show full text]
  • Skepticism and Pluralism Ways of Living a Life Of
    SKEPTICISM AND PLURALISM WAYS OF LIVING A LIFE OF AWARENESS AS RECOMMENDED BY THE ZHUANGZI #±r A DISSERTATION SUBMITTED TO THE GRADUATE DIVISION OF THE UNIVERSITY OF HAWAI'I IN PARTIAL FULFILLMENT OF THE REQUIREMENTS FOR THE DEGREE OF DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY IN PHILOSOPHY AUGUST 2004 By John Trowbridge Dissertation Committee: Roger T. Ames, Chairperson Tamara Albertini Chung-ying Cheng James E. Tiles David R. McCraw © Copyright 2004 by John Trowbridge iii Dedicated to my wife, Jill iv ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS In completing this research, I would like to express my appreciation first and foremost to my wife, Jill, and our three children, James, Holly, and Henry for their support during this process. I would also like to express my gratitude to my entire dissertation committee for their insight and understanding ofthe topics at hand. Studying under Roger Ames has been a transformative experience. In particular, his commitment to taking the Chinese tradition on its own terms and avoiding the tendency among Western interpreters to overwrite traditional Chinese thought with the preoccupations ofWestern philosophy has enabled me to broaden my conception ofphilosophy itself. Roger's seminars on Confucianism and Daoism, and especially a seminar on writing a philosophical translation ofthe Zhongyong r:pJm (Achieving Equilibrium in the Everyday), have greatly influenced my own initial attempts to translate and interpret the seminal philosophical texts ofancient China. Tamara Albertini's expertise in ancient Greek philosophy was indispensable to this project, and a seminar I audited with her, comparing early Greek and ancient Chinese philosophy, was part ofthe inspiration for my choice ofresearch topic. I particularly valued the opportunity to study Daoism and the Yijing ~*~ with Chung-ying Cheng g\Gr:p~ and benefited greatly from his theory ofonto-cosmology as a means of understanding classical Chinese philosophy.
    [Show full text]
  • Aristoxenus Elements of Rhythm: Text, Translation, and Commentary with a Translation and Commentary on Poxy 2687
    © 2009 Christopher C. Marchetti ALL RIGHTS RESERVED ARISTOXENUS ELEMENTS OF RHYTHM: TEXT, TRANSLATION, AND COMMENTARY WITH A TRANSLATION AND COMMENTARY ON POXY 2687 by CHRISTOPHER C. MARCHETTI A Dissertation submitted to the Graduate School-New Brunswick Rutgers, The State University of New Jersey in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy Graduate Program in Classics written under the direction of Prof. Thomas Figueira and approved by ________________________ ________________________ ________________________ ________________________ New Brunswick, New Jersey May, 2009 ABSTRACT OF THE DISSERTATION Aristoxenus’ Elements of Rhythm: Text, Translation, and Commentary with a Translation and Commentary on POxy 2687 By Christopher C. Marchetti Dissertation Director: Prof. Thomas Figueira Aristoxenus of Tarentum makes productive use of Aristotelian concepts and methods in developing his theory of musical rhythm in his treatise Elements of Rhythm. He applies the Aristotelian distinction between form and material and the concept of hypothetical necessity to provide an explanation for why musical rhythm is manifested in the syllables of song, the notes of melody, and the steps of dance. He applies the method of formulating differentiae, as described in Aristotle’s Parts of Animals, to codify the formal properties of rhythm. Aristoxenus’ description of the rhythmic foot presents several interpretive challenges. Our text is fragmentary, and we lack Aristoxenus’ definitions of several key terms. This study seeks to establish the meanings of these terms on the basis of a close examination of the structure of Aristoxenus’ argument. Parallel passages in Aristides Quintilianus’ On Music are considered in detail for ii their consistency or lack thereof with Aristoxenian usage.
    [Show full text]
  • Anaximander's Ἄπειρον
    1 Pulished in: Ancient Philosophy Volume 39, Issue 1, Spring 2019 Anaximander’s ἄπειρον: from the Life-world to the Cosmic Event Horizon Norman Sieroka Pages 1-22 https://doi.org/10.5840/ancientphil2019391 1 Current affiliation of author (July 2020): Theoretische Philosophie, Universität Bremen www.uni-bremen.de/theophil/sieroka Abstract Scholars have claimed repeatedly that Anaximander’s notion of the ἄπειρον marks the first metaphysical concept, or even the first theoretical entity, in Western thought. The present paper scrutinizes this claim. Characterizing natural phenomena as ἄπειρος— that is, as being inexhaustible or untraversable by standard human means—was common in daily practice, especially when referring to landmasses and seas but also when referring to vast numbers of countable objects. I will deny the assumption that Anaximander’s notion started off as being a theoretical answer to a specific philosophical question. That said, the aforementioned everyday notion of ἄπειρος could still lead to the development of theoretical concepts. Based on the observations Anaximander did with seasonal sundials, the inexhaustible landmasses and seas just mentioned became depicted on his world map by means of concentric circles. These circles then marked the bounds of experience and, by being fixed and finite, suggested the possibility of traversing beyond what is directly experienced. Evaluating claims from recent Anaximander scholarship, the paper ends with a brief comparison with concepts from modern physics which play an analogous role of demarcating the bounds of experience. Anaximander’s ἄπειρον: from the Life-world to the Cosmic Event Horizon Norman Sieroka Interest in Anaximander (c. 610-c. 547 BC) has increased in recent years.
    [Show full text]
  • Plato's Basic Metaphysical Argument Against Hedonism and Aristotle's Presentation of It at Eudemian Ethics 6.11
    Plato's Basic Metaphysical Argument against Hedonism David Wolfsdorf and Aristotle's Presentation of It at Eudemian Ethics 6.11 1. Introduction At Eudemian Ethics 6.11 (= Nicomachean Ethics 7.11) Aristotle introduces several views that others hold regarding pleasure's value. In particular I draw your attention to the following one. Aristotle writes that some believe that: A. No pleasure is a good thing, either in itself or incidentally. οὐδεµία ἡδονὴ εἶναι ἀγαθόν, οὔτε καθ᾽ αὑτὸ οὔτε κατὰ συµβεβηκός. (1152b8-9) Aristotle proceeds to give several reasons for this position. One is that: R. Every pleasure is a perceived genesis toward a nature, but no genesis is of the same kind as its ends, for example no building of a house is of the same kind as a house. (1152b13-15) πᾶσα ἡδονὴ γένεσίς ἐστιν εἰς φύσιν αἰσθητή, οὐδεµία δὲ γένεσις συγγενὴς τοῖς τέλεσιν, οἷον οὐδεµία οἰκοδόµησις οἰκίᾳ. Who are the believers of A and R that Aristotle is reporting? I suggest that the evidence leads us back to Plato's Philebus. There a view very similar to R is developed, and a view very similar to A is argued to depend on it. That the views Aristotle here reports can be traced back to Plato does not confirm that Plato himself held them. An argument is always necessary when inferring from a thesis stated or advanced in some Platonic text to a thesis maintained by Plato himself. But— setting that problem aside— I also said that A and R are "very similar to," I did not say that they were identical to the views expressed in Plato's Philebus.
    [Show full text]
  • Anaximander and the Problem of the Earth's Immobility
    Binghamton University The Open Repository @ Binghamton (The ORB) The Society for Ancient Greek Philosophy Newsletter 12-28-1953 Anaximander and the Problem of the Earth's Immobility John Robinson Windham College Follow this and additional works at: https://orb.binghamton.edu/sagp Recommended Citation Robinson, John, "Anaximander and the Problem of the Earth's Immobility" (1953). The Society for Ancient Greek Philosophy Newsletter. 263. https://orb.binghamton.edu/sagp/263 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by The Open Repository @ Binghamton (The ORB). It has been accepted for inclusion in The Society for Ancient Greek Philosophy Newsletter by an authorized administrator of The Open Repository @ Binghamton (The ORB). For more information, please contact [email protected]. JOHN ROBINSON Windham College Anaximander and the Problem of the Earth’s Immobility* N the course of his review of the reasons given by his predecessors for the earth’s immobility, Aristotle states that “some” attribute it I neither to the action of the whirl nor to the air beneath’s hindering its falling : These are the causes with which most thinkers busy themselves. But there are some who say, like Anaximander among the ancients, that it stays where it is because of its “indifference” (όμοιότητα). For what is stationed at the center, and is equably related to the extremes, has no reason to go one way rather than another—either up or down or sideways. And since it is impossible for it to move simultaneously in opposite directions, it necessarily stays where it is.1 The ascription of this curious view to Anaximander appears to have occasioned little uneasiness among modern commentators.
    [Show full text]
  • Parmenides B6.1–2 Without a Modal Fallacy
    Aporia vol. 21 no. 1—2011 Parmenides B6.1–2 without a Modal Fallacy MICHAEL J. HANSEN n all accounts, Parmenides makes a marvelous argument in the Way of Truth. However, there is no clear consensus among inter- Opreters about how to read it. The only noncontroversial point in interpreting the work seems to be that in it, Parmenides did something pro- found to philosophy. Despite this collective obligation to acknowledge Par- menides’ unique innovation (whatever it may be), it has become popular to read Parmenides as relying on a modal fallacy to make his argument. This would be an embarrassing mistake for such an influential work, especially given the argument’s deductive appearance. In this paper, I will outline the modal fallacy that Parmenides is accused of and argue for an interpretation that is free of the fallacy. I. The Alleged Modal Fallacy The critical fragment we must examine to decide the question is B6.1–2, in which the fallacy is supposed to occur: crhV toV levgein te noei`n t' ejoVn e!mmenai e!sti gaVr ei^nai, mhdeVn d' oujk e!otin . (Graham 214) Michael J. Hansen is a senior majoring in philosophy at Brigham Young University. He is interested in ancient philosophy, the philosophy of mind, epistemology, and metaphysics. In the fall, he will be pursuing a PhD in philosophy at the University of California–Los Angeles. This essay placed first in the 2011 David H. Yarn Philosophical Essay Contest. 2 MICHAEL J. HANSEN As usual, Parmenides’ language admits of many permissible translations for interpreters to quibble over, but this fragment is exceptionally difficult to render.
    [Show full text]
  • Lucan's Natural Questions: Landscape and Geography in the Bellum Civile Laura Zientek a Dissertation Submitted in Partial Fulf
    Lucan’s Natural Questions: Landscape and Geography in the Bellum Civile Laura Zientek A dissertation submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy University of Washington 2014 Reading Committee: Catherine Connors, Chair Alain Gowing Stephen Hinds Program Authorized to Offer Degree: Classics © Copyright 2014 Laura Zientek University of Washington Abstract Lucan’s Natural Questions: Landscape and Geography in the Bellum Civile Laura Zientek Chair of the Supervisory Committee: Professor Catherine Connors Department of Classics This dissertation is an analysis of the role of landscape and the natural world in Lucan’s Bellum Civile. I investigate digressions and excurses on mountains, rivers, and certain myths associated aetiologically with the land, and demonstrate how Stoic physics and cosmology – in particular the concepts of cosmic (dis)order, collapse, and conflagration – play a role in the way Lucan writes about the landscape in the context of a civil war poem. Building on previous analyses of the Bellum Civile that provide background on its literary context (Ahl, 1976), on Lucan’s poetic technique (Masters, 1992), and on landscape in Roman literature (Spencer, 2010), I approach Lucan’s depiction of the natural world by focusing on the mutual effect of humanity and landscape on each other. Thus, hardships posed by the land against characters like Caesar and Cato, gloomy and threatening atmospheres, and dangerous or unusual weather phenomena all have places in my study. I also explore how Lucan’s landscapes engage with the tropes of the locus amoenus or horridus (Schiesaro, 2006) and elements of the sublime (Day, 2013).
    [Show full text]
  • Thales of Miletus Sources and Interpretations Miletli Thales Kaynaklar Ve Yorumlar
    Thales of Miletus Sources and Interpretations Miletli Thales Kaynaklar ve Yorumlar David Pierce October , Matematics Department Mimar Sinan Fine Arts University Istanbul http://mat.msgsu.edu.tr/~dpierce/ Preface Here are notes of what I have been able to find or figure out about Thales of Miletus. They may be useful for anybody interested in Thales. They are not an essay, though they may lead to one. I focus mainly on the ancient sources that we have, and on the mathematics of Thales. I began this work in preparation to give one of several - minute talks at the Thales Meeting (Thales Buluşması) at the ruins of Miletus, now Milet, September , . The talks were in Turkish; the audience were from the general popu- lation. I chose for my title “Thales as the originator of the concept of proof” (Kanıt kavramının öncüsü olarak Thales). An English draft is in an appendix. The Thales Meeting was arranged by the Tourism Research Society (Turizm Araştırmaları Derneği, TURAD) and the office of the mayor of Didim. Part of Aydın province, the district of Didim encompasses the ancient cities of Priene and Miletus, along with the temple of Didyma. The temple was linked to Miletus, and Herodotus refers to it under the name of the family of priests, the Branchidae. I first visited Priene, Didyma, and Miletus in , when teaching at the Nesin Mathematics Village in Şirince, Selçuk, İzmir. The district of Selçuk contains also the ruins of Eph- esus, home town of Heraclitus. In , I drafted my Miletus talk in the Math Village. Since then, I have edited and added to these notes.
    [Show full text]
  • I Were Zeno's Arguments a Reply to Attacks Upon Parmenides?
    Were Zeno's a Arguments Reply To Attacks upon Parmenides? N. B. BOOTH NE of the mysteries about Zeno of Elea's arguments is that, whereas learn from all the available that Zeno was we evidence particularly concerned to defend the One of Parmenides 1, yet we find him, in his arguments about plurality, doing all that he can to refute the "ones" of a plurality.2 This would be reasonable if we could be sure that his arguments were valid only against the "ones" of a plurality, not against Parmenides's One; but it is by no means certain that this is true, as we shall see in the course of my discussion. The difficulty was already felt by the ancient commentators 3, and perhaps by Plato as well 4 ; it may be a "pseudo-problem", but if so, it is a pseudo-problem of some antiquity. One suggested solution is to the effect that, before Zeno produced his 5 arguments, certain critics had attacked Parmenides's One with much the same arguments as Zeno later used to attack the "ones" of the pluralists. The two main sources of evidence 6 for this suggestion are a passage in Plato's Parmenides ( i 2 8 c), and Zeno's arguments themselves ' ; a third is possibly to be found in the arguments of Parmenides's other pupil, Melissus.8 There is, regrettably, no definite statement on the subject in any of our authorities. In the passage from the Parmenides ( i 2 8 c), Plato makes the character "Zeno" apologize for the shortcomings of his book about plurality: "It I is really an attempt to support Parmenides's argument against those who try to redicule his theory that 'One is', saying that, if 'One is', then many absurd and inconsistent conclusions follow.
    [Show full text]
  • The Natural Philosophers
    The Natural Philosophers For us, the most interesting part is actually not what solutions these earliest philosophers arrived at, but The earliest Greek philosophers are sometimes which questions they asked and what type of answer called natural philosophers because they were mainly they were looking for. We are more interested in how concerned with the natural world and its processes. they thought than in exactly what they thought. We have already asked ourselves where everything We know that they posed questions relating to the comes from. Nowadays a lot of people imagine that at transformations they could observe in the physical some time something must have come from nothing. This world. They were looking for the underlying laws of idea was not so widespread among the Greeks. For one nature. They wanted to understand what was happening reason or another, they assumed that “something” had around them without having to turn to the ancient always existed. myths. And most important, they wanted to understand How everything could come from nothing was the actual processes by studying nature itself. This was therefore not the all-important question. On the other quite different from explaining thunder and lightning or hand the Greeks marveled at how live fish could come winter and spring by telling stories about the gods. from water, and huge trees and brilliantly colored So philosophy gradually liberated itself from flowers could come from the dead earth. Not to mention religion. We could say that the natural philosophers took how a baby could come from its mother’s womb! the first step in the direction of scientific reasoning, The philosophers observed with their own eyes thereby becoming the precursors of what was to become that nature was in a constant state of transformation.
    [Show full text]
  • Meet the Philosophers of Ancient Greece
    Meet the Philosophers of Ancient Greece Everything You Always Wanted to Know About Ancient Greek Philosophy but didn’t Know Who to Ask Edited by Patricia F. O’Grady MEET THE PHILOSOPHERS OF ANCIENT GREECE Dedicated to the memory of Panagiotis, a humble man, who found pleasure when reading about the philosophers of Ancient Greece Meet the Philosophers of Ancient Greece Everything you always wanted to know about Ancient Greek philosophy but didn’t know who to ask Edited by PATRICIA F. O’GRADY Flinders University of South Australia © Patricia F. O’Grady 2005 All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system or transmitted in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording or otherwise without the prior permission of the publisher. Patricia F. O’Grady has asserted her right under the Copyright, Designs and Patents Act, 1988, to be identi.ed as the editor of this work. Published by Ashgate Publishing Limited Ashgate Publishing Company Wey Court East Suite 420 Union Road 101 Cherry Street Farnham Burlington Surrey, GU9 7PT VT 05401-4405 England USA Ashgate website: http://www.ashgate.com British Library Cataloguing in Publication Data Meet the philosophers of ancient Greece: everything you always wanted to know about ancient Greek philosophy but didn’t know who to ask 1. Philosophy, Ancient 2. Philosophers – Greece 3. Greece – Intellectual life – To 146 B.C. I. O’Grady, Patricia F. 180 Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Meet the philosophers of ancient Greece: everything you always wanted to know about ancient Greek philosophy but didn’t know who to ask / Patricia F.
    [Show full text]