<<

International Phenomenological Society

!"#$%&'(%)*&+"&,%-.($,/0%!$#*.1&,"+2%"'%34//$1, 54+6.17/80%-&12%9$&''$%:&11&;$$ ).41<$0%=6",./.*62%&'(%=6$'.#$'.,.>"<&,%?$/$&1<6@%A.,B%CD@%E.B%F%7-&1B@%GDHD8@%**B%FIFJFDK =4;,"/6$(%;20%International Phenomenological Society )+&;,$%L?:0%http://www.jstor.org/stable/2107794 5<<$//$(0%KGMGNMKNGN%GH0GN

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use.

Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=ips.

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].

International Phenomenological Society is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to and Phenomenological Research.

http://www.jstor.org Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Vol. XLIX, No. 3, March i989

Time and Spatial Models: Temporality in Husserl

MARY JEANNE LARRABEE DePaul University

Recent treatments of time in Husserl offer accounts of the most funda- mental aspects of what Husserl terms inner time-consciousness, the immanent temporality that is the primal constitutive source of human experience.' A major difficulty with these expansions upon the outlines of Husserl's time theory is that they continue to use theoretically reduction- ist models for time, primarily that of "flux" or "flow," which are drawn from physical space and objects extended through such space. Discus- sion focuses on "temporal Objects," particularly conscious or mental processes that are "spread" or extended through immanent time, and on those characteristics of consciousness that make such spreading possible. The rationale for such an approach, of course, is obvious: the texts of Husserl himself repeatedly refer to immanent time as a "flux" or flow and

See, for example, Izchak Miller, Husserl, Perception and Temporal Awareness (Cam- bridge: Massachusetts Institute of Technology Press, i984). My own interpretation of Husserl's discussions on inner time-consciousness begins with the critical piece by John Brough, "The Emergence of an Absolute Consciousness in Husserl's Early Writings on Time-Consciousness,"Man and World 5 (1972): 298-326; reprintedin Husserl: Expo- sitions and Appraisals (Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame, 1977), ed. F. A. Elliston and P. McCormick, pp. 83-ioo. There are also discussions of Husserl's time theory as it developed subsequent to the period covered by Brough to be found in Robert Sokolow- ski's Husserlian Meditations. How Words Present Things (Evanston: Northwestern UniversityPress, 1974), chapter6. It must be understood that consciousness is used by Husserl to encompass a wide variety of acts, activities, and actions by the "subject," as well as occurrences and hap- penings within the subject, including passive, automatic, and anonymous ones. NOTE: Partial support for work on this essay was received from DePaul University's College of Liberal Arts and Sciences Faculty Summer Research Grant Program. The German term, 'Fluss', is often translated as 'flux', a somewhat appropriate cognate. I have opted for 'flow' because it fits the spatial modeling of Husserl's descriptions. 'Flux' is more enigmatic, and thus is acceptable for what it labels - and I will shift to it later in my text when discussing the deepest levels of immanent temporality.

TEMPORALITY IN HUSSERL 373 thus call up the image of the river moving along with its contents com- prised in that flowing, gaining their fluent qualities from it. In itself there is nothing inherently wrong with using a spatial model to open out an interpretation of temporal flow. But interpretations using such a metaphor have many limitations, often unrecognized, and they can lead, at least partially, to a mistaken understanding of Husserl's theory of time. The focus of the recent treatments, for instance, gives some account of the flowing of temporal Objects, but fails to capture the central aspect of processing itself. To clarify this point I will first investigate the two-fold description of inner time-consciousness that gives the primary spatial model of flow - in fact, of two intersecting flows. Next I will consider the manner in which dimensions of immanent temporality are overlooked or even lost in the spatial model. Finally, I will propose a variation on this spatial model so that we can gain access to the complexity of Husserl's theory of immanent temporality and provide an access to an adequate explanation of the source of process as processing. An alternative model must deliver a characterization of consciousness which is sufficiently multi-dimensional that it indicates conscious life as filling out a "space" incapable of being described by means of the narrowly limiting four- dimensionality of ordinary human experience of the world. This model might also cut through the mechanistic model of flow to a more dynamic metaphor of a decentered flowing that itself energizes the processing of consciousness.

What are the two aspects of inner time-consciousness that give the pri- mary spatial model of intersecting flows? A brief investigation of these aspects will demonstrate that the usual two-dimensional spatial model given by Husserlian interpreters flattens the flows to something like two tapes moving at right angles to one another. The theory of inner time-con- sciousness proposed by Husserl posits a temporalizing consciousness that constitutes both "external"-worldly time (the time of clocks) and the "internal" or inner time of consciousness and its mental or conscious pro- cesses (Erlebnisse, also termed 'lived experiences'). The three levels of this constitutive nexus are (a) worldly object time, (b) inner time of immanent "temporal Objects" (conscious processes such as acts and sensations),3

We must remain very clear here what is meant by "Object," a translation of the German Object;it is an all-purpose term for Husserl and thus includes as only one type the inner time Objects, as another the "objektiv"temporal objects (Gegenstdnde)within the world. The immanent time Objects in Husserl's discussion are clearly Erlebnisse(acts and hyletic data).

3 74 MARY JEANNE LARRABEE and (c) absolute consciousness of time itself.4 Objects, things, events within level (a) are constituted temporally, "given" within the temporal- ity of clock time, by the immanent temporality of level (b) Erlebnisse, while the latter are temporalized by the Absolute of level (c). The more complex and thus more textually accurate descriptions of Husserl's constituting temporality speak, not of one flow, but of a double flow within temporalization itself, as Husserl calls it. Each flow is marked, as it were, with a specific constitutive task or intentionality: "like two aspects of one and the same thing, there are in the unique flux of con- sciousness two inseparable, homogeneous intentionalities which require one another and are interwoven with one another." The double flow is that of (b) inner or immanent time, on one hand, and that of (c) inner time- consciousness, on the other, that is, the consciousness of inner time; both come under the title of immanent temporality, the temporality of con- ciousness itself: "By means of the one [intentionality], immanent time is constituted, i.e., an Objective time, an authentic one in which there is duration and alternation of that which endures. In the other [intentionality] is constituted the quasi-temporal disposition of the phases of the flux,. . . This prephenomenal, pre-immanent temporality is con- stituted intentionally as the form of temporally constitutive consciousness and in the latter itself" (Hua IO, 83 [PITC io9]).5 In the imagining or model-based expressing of inner time, we will say that the continuum of inner time (b) flows horizontally, and inner time-consciousness (c) verti- cally. They intersect, as it were, at the impressional consciousness "in" the

Edmund Husserl, Zur Phanomenologie des inneren Zeitbewusstseins (1883-1917), ed. Rudolf Boehm (Husserliana io) (The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, i966), section 34, p. 73; The Phenomenology of Internal Time-Consciousness, trans. J. S. Churchill (Blooming- ton: Indiana University, 1950), p. 98. Pagination of the original i928 publication cited in the margin of the Husserliana volume will be used, given after Hua Io, with the English translation (when used) in brackets with PITC. The differentiation of temporality (transcendental and immanent) into three levels is treated both in the Time Lectures dated 1905 by their i928 editors, Edith Stein and M. Heidegger, and in the supporting texts given in the Husserliana edition by Boehm and dated about 1907. The Time Lectures (1928), however, is a composite text, with what appear to be post-1905 discussions imported into the lecture texts dated 1905, at least some by Edith Stein in i9 i6-i8; see Boehm's Introduction to the Husserliana, vol. io. Brough (in "Emergence") presents Husserl's time theory as it evolved from a model based on perceptual apprehension (Auffassung) in 1901-1907 (what Brough calls the schematic interpretation) to a theory emphasizing the Absolute Consciousness and rejecting that model. This particular aspect of the shift is not questioned in my presenta- tion, although it probably would have some pertinence in a full-scale development of an alternative model. This distinction is also made in the discussion of the unity of the flux; Hua Io, section 3 8, 77 [PITC I02].

TEMPORALITY IN HUSSEkL 375 Now (of immanent time, not worldly objective time), giving us the pri- mary spatial model of intersecting flows, moving like two tapes at right angles.' The description of these two flows is more complex, however, than such a model might originally seem to represent. The flows are character- ized by a "doubled intentionality" that encompasses (i) the horizontal intentionalities running through the horizontal flow of inner time (b, above) and (z) the vertical intentionalities running through the vertical dimensions of inner time-consciousness (c, above).7 The horizontal inten- tionalities would appear to be those of the phases of inner time "through" which the enduring Erlebnisse (here, the inner time Objects) pass as enduring. These phases of inner time are generally called the inner time continuum of past - Now - future, broken down by Husserl more specifically into "time points": . . . just-just-past . . . just-past . . . Now . . . just-coming. . . ; thus the image of a flow along the horizontal line.8 The second aspect of immanent temporality provides the image of a flow along a vertical line, intersecting the horizontal one at the Now (of immanent time). The vertical intentionalities include the interconnections among phases of the actually constituting-temporalizing consciousness, phases lumped into three designations: retention [of the past], impres- sional consciousness [of the Now], and protention [of the future].9 Like

The model is already in difficulties here, for the impressional consciousness cannot accu- rately be described as "in the Now" nor "of' the Now, since impressional consciousness effectively constitutes the Now in the sense of "nowness" of actual momentary Erlebnis. In a sense that will be referred to later, however, impressional consciousness is the Now; specifically, its very impressionality, its liveliness (Lebendigkeit, but also lively presence - Leibhaftigkeit), is its Nowness Jetzigkeit). My presentation of a spatial model for time stems in part from an assessment of Miller, who adapts Husserl's diagrams from Hua Io, z8 [PITC 49] and 93 [izi]; Husserl, Perception and Temporal Awareness, p.

The Time Lectures, section 3 9, speaks of this double intentionality in regard to retention, its primary actualizing source; Hua 1O, 8o-8i [PITC io6]. 8 The time points are, of course, not to be thought of as mathematical ideal points; see E. Husserl, Phanomenologische Psychologie. Vorlesungen Sommersemester 1925, ed. Walter Biemel, Husserliana 9 (The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, i968), p. Zoo; Phenome- nological Psychology. Lectures, Summer Semester, 1925, trans. John Scanlon (The Hague: MartinusNijhoff, 1977). 9 See E. Husserl, Ideen zu einer reinen Phdnomenologie und phanomenologischen Phi- losophie, First Book, ed. W. Biemel, Husserliana 3 (The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 1976), i99; first half volume translated as Collected Works, Vol. 2: Ideas pertaining to a Pure Phenomenology and to a Phenomenological Philosophy, First Book. trans. Frederick Kersten (The Hague: Martinus Nijhdff, i982), with German pagination given in margins.

376 MARY JEANNE LARRABEE the horizontal time-phases, however, these three vertical phases hide divi- sions; retentional consciousness hides the continuum of (r.i) retention [of just-past], (r.z) retention of retention [of just-just-past], (r.3) retention of retention of retention, etc.; protention hides a parallel differentiation. The temporality modeled on the horizontal line yields the "fact" of flow in consciousness' processes (here we will be unconcerned with the time of the world's objects and events). Take, for instance, the specific act of perceiving an apple on the table that I now walk past. This act begins in a Now (of inner time) and continues through several Nows (I keep look- ing at it as I walk). Each Now-moment shades off into a "past" relative to the new Now, a past we show as part of the inner time-continuum.'0 Even- tually this particular perceiving ends and does not show up in a new Now. This perceiving, then, is said to "extend" across the inner time continuum and is thus identified as temporal. The identification as enduring or tem- poral is constituted on the basis of the act (or any conscious process, Erlebnis) "transversing" or "moving across" this horizontal line of inner time, a feature that phenomenological attending can note: "If I orient myself on a sound, I enter attentively into 'transverse-intentionali- ty' . . . ; then the enduring sound is present there, ever widening in its duration" (Hua io, 8z [PITC io8]). Thus, transverse or horizontal inten- tionality accomplishes one aspect of the temporalization of the Erlebnisse

Husserl names the horizontal line in his diagrams a "series of Now-points," but these technically could not be pictured on the same line since Nows do not co-exist. The spread of an Erlebnis across several of these Now-points is re-modeled in my presentation (which I do not claim is Husserl's, strictly speaking) as a spreading out to the left (for past phases of the Erlebnis) and to the right (for future phases of the Erlebnis)of the Now- point. This use of the horizontal line, however, does reflect Husserl's discussions of the "Quers-" intentionality that constitutes the temporal spread of Erlebnisse across the inner time line. The English translation of the Time Lectures, I think, has caused a major disservice to Husserlian scholarship by taking the terms 'Quersintentionalitdt' and 'Ldngsintentionalitdt' as reflecting the geographical image of latitude and longitude, thus providing the rough equivalents, 'vertical' and 'horizontal'. But 'Quer' in particular has various translations, one of which makes more sense for Husserl's own diagrams, that is, 'diagonal'. This "Quersintentionalitdt" constitutes the temporal duration of Erlebnisse by the increasing modifications shown along the diagonal line of retentional modifications. Look, for example, at Hua IO, 3 3 1: the diagram shows to where an Erleb- nis, say X, occurs Now; in the next moment tI, X would be "at" t,? and thus modified by retention', while in the third moment t, it would by "at" t,7 and thus modified by reten- tion' of retention', etc. The diagonal line drawn from to through t,0 and t,0, etc., shows the intentional interconnections of each successive retentional modification of X, giving it spread across a span of inner time (the latter not shown in Husserl's diagram). My model gives only one Now on the horizontal line and locates it in the inner time con- tinuum so that the temporal spread constituted by the diagonal intentionality is being pictured on the horizontal in my model.

TEMPORALITY IN HUSSERL 377 of consciousness. The vertical flow, in contrast, is the source of this temporalizing by pro- viding consciousness its own awareness of its processes in their process- ing. Each moment of the horizontal time-flow has a corresponding con- sciousness of it "in" the vertical flow: impressional consciousness of each Now, retentional of the past, and protentional of future. This point is modeled by extending a line above the Now point for the protentional line and below the Now for the retentional line; at the Now, the protentional and the retentional line "meet" at a point to represent impressional con- sciousness. This meeting occurs seemingly at exactly the same point that is called the Now of the inner time line, but the Now is distinct from impres- sional consciousness, despite the picturing of the model. What we call here the vertical flow incorporates what Husserl terms "longitudinal (Ldngs) intentionality" (Hua io, 8z [PITC io8]).Iz A continuous shov-

Miller gives a crucial misinterpretation of Husserl on this point. He identifies the "end-point" of the "first" or "primary" (to use his words) intentionality as being the "actual object" of the exemplified intending act, that is, the apple of a perceiving; see his Husserl, Perception and Temporal Awareness, sections 7.3 and 7.4. Such a mistake might be called a relatively simple one to make, given Husserl's use of sound as the exam- ple of an Erlebnis. The German Ton is not helpful, but the context makes clear when this is meant as Erlebnis, that is, as "immanent Object" rather than as the sound in the world, a transcendent object. The "first" intentionality of retention, in fact, resides solely with the act itself, and is not the "primary" or any intentionality of temporalizing conscious- ness. The act of perceiving is an immanent Object, within the level two cited earlier, tem- poralizing consciousness is placed on level three. The act has its own intentional reference to a perceived "object," but temporalizing consciousness has several intentionalities within itself. Miller has one intentionality of retention take on the role of the act's inten- tionality or intentional reference to its "object"; on this interpretation, a pure "passive" intentionality (retention) would thus be accomplishing what is really an active intention- ality that constitutes the perceived object, here, apple. He then reduces the other inten- tionality of retention to that belonging appropriately to the reflectivity of consciousness, when this second intentionality of retention actually serves as the transcendental precon- dition for reflection since it accomplishes the flux's unity with itself. Miller's mistake, of course, renders the displaying of immanent time-consciousness simpler, as it leaves out one intentional dimension of the "dual" immanent temporality of consciousness. Husserl designates retention's primary intentionality as a vertical ('Quers-') one, rather than the horizontal that my diagrams spatialize. The use of 'Quers-' makes sense (see note io); the characterization of the "secondary" intentionality of retention as horizon- tal, however, is puzzling, since this intentionality constitutes the unity of temporalizing consciousness and thus its totality, its all-at-once character of complete quasi- "simultaneity" (Hua Io, 8o). Yet there seems no appropriate "place" for this intention- ality on his diagrams of time. If Husserl envisioned the horizontal line of his diagrams, some clearly labeled the series of Nows (Hua 1O, z8 and 365), the usage is at best mis- leading. If he had in mind an image that would be expanded into his later notion of living present, then perhaps he intended the "Langsintentionalitat" to operate "within" each Now, although this way of expressing it is technically inaccurate.

378 MARY JEANNE LARRABEE ing-back, on the vertical flow, of the "expired" Now-consciousness into retentional modifications is a streaming from the Absolute of conscious- ness as temporalizing and self-temporalizing in an anonymous mode "prior to" (in the genetic, not a temporal sense) the reflective stance artic- ulated in this description. The intentionality operative throughout this vertical line maintains the connectedness of temporalizing consciousness, that is, provides the ordered connections of the phases of temporalizing consciousnesses that allow immanent temporality to temporalize its Erlebnisse, as well as itself. When we give a "frozen" or static picturing of actual conscious life, the vertical line is "connected" with diagonal lines, say, from retention (r.i) to the just-past, from the retention of retention (r.z) to the just-just-past, etc., of a particular Now. These diagonals indicate further possible inten- tionalities between the two flows, rather than just across one or the other flow. We could try this modeling, based primarily on the description in Section 39 of the Phenomenology of Internal Time-Consciousness: Flowing in absolute transition, the first primal sensation changes into a retention of itself, this retention into a retention of this retention, and so on. Conjointly with the first retention, however, a new "Now," a new primal sensation, is present and is joined continuously but momentarily with the first retention, so that the second phase of the flux is a primal sensation of the new Now and a retention of the earlier one. The third phase, again, is a new primal sensation with retention of the second primal sensation and a retention of the retention of the first, and so on. (Hua Io, 8i [PITC107]) The diagraming of this temporalizing is usually plotted onto a two-dimen- sional picture, the flows statically7drawn (for simplicity, our diagram leaves out the protentional phases):

DIAGRAM I. S I . sl .5o.sz .5s3s ri rz

rif

This diagram shows us a conscious process si (for example, smelling a freshly baked loaf of French bread) that has occurred in a Now, was then displaced by the coming sz, so that sz is Now and si just-past; the process repeating with s3. The sz when in the Now is an impressional conscious-

TEMPORALITY IN HUSSERL 379 ness connected with a retentional consciousness ri of si, the si presently just-past. In the next moment of the horizontal time flow comes S3 impres- sionally given, connected to retention rz of sz and ri' of si (ri' here being a modification of the retention ri). The recognition of the identity of si through s3 as the smelling of the same bread constitutes si through s3 as an enduring smelling act. At time 3 of s3 as Now, the identification occurs on the basis of the "attached" retentions rz and ri . The major problem with this sort of diagram is that it does not picture the processing accurately - it neither captures the Now of s3 with its complete temporal contexts nor the processing occurring at the Now of s3. For one thing, there is really no si or sz present at the Now of s3. Let us try an alternative diagramming procedure, one that gives each Now a dif- ferent picture. The above diagram would "split" into three pictures, giv- ing the appropriate temporal characters at each moment:

DIAGRAM II.

P.I . . . just-past/- . . . Now/si . . . just coming/sz . . .

P.z . . . just-past/si . . . Now/sz . . . just coming/s3 . . .

ri[si] P.3 just-just-past/si just-past/sz . . Now/s. just coming/*.

ri [sz] \ ~~~~~~~~~~~~~~I rz(ri '[si]) The advantage of this different picturing is the ability to display both the "standing" or static features of inner time - the vertical and the horizon- tal lines as they remain the same formally - and the "streaming" feature of immanent temporality, that is, as it continuously functions to tempo- ralize the fluctuating "content" of the inner-time line. The former static features of inner time are named by the series ". . . just-just-past . . . just-past . . . Now . . . just coming" on the vertical line and by "s# [impressional consciousness] - ri [retention] - r2 [retention of reten- tion], etc." on the horizontal. These static features are always as they are, formally, given in this naming. The latter streaming feature, for this par- ticular moment of conscious life P.3, is shown by the "si . . . s . . . s3"

I Identity is the subject of Giuseppina Chiara Moneta, On Identity: A Study of Genetic Phenomenology (The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 1976), especially chapter 4, The Tem- poral Structure of Identity.

3 80 MARY JEANNE LARRABEE on both lines, giving the concrete specifics of this momentary conscious- ness; change comes here at each moment. Where the retentional modifications with a present impressional consciousness (as shown in P.3) identify the s i and sz and s3 as the same, they are linked as one continuous smelling of bread spread across from the Now (of P. 3) into the past phases linked with it. Both in this case of identification across s1-S3 and in a situation where there are three successive different Erlebnisse, however, none of them (always excepting the impressionally given Erlebnis) is actually present on the inner time, the horizontal, line; their apparent presentness is simply a feature of the picturing as intersecting lines. Other than the actually Now phase of Erlebniss, the past or coming phases of acts or impressions are present on the vertical line as retentionally or protentionally given. It is the continuum of retentional, impressional, and protentional conscious- nesses that temporalizes the Erlebnisse, that give them temporal spread if they endure or give them momentariness if they do not, that give them as simultaneous or coincident with one another, etc. The smellings and any other Erlebnisse are not self-temporalizing but are temporalized by this more fundamental functioning of consciousness as inner-time conscious- ness.

II We must note, however, that there is a conceptualization within this mod- eling, for there are not really two lines in the temporalizing of conscious- ness. The two lines actually - that is, in the life of a consciousness - fold into one another much as impressional consciousness is there with the Now, separate in phenomenological description but not really distinct as living consciousness. And here, in part, problems emerge, especially for any two-dimensional (vertical-horizontal) modeling of temporality. Hus- serl characterizes the longitudinal intentionality (of the model's vertical line), that is, of the flowing phases of the consciousness of inner time (at least the series of retentional phases), as "the unity of the flux itself as a one-dimensional, quasi-temporal order" (Hua io, 8z [PITC io8]).'4 How should such a description be taken? The vertical line is that part of the model that must represent consciousness being aware all at once of temporal extensity of Erlebnisse across the horizontal line. Representing the primal temporalizing flux, the vertical line, as a line, already diverts us from its true being; and picturing the horizontal line of inner time both as a line and as separate from the vertical is a conceptualization reminiscent

I4 My emphasis. It seems appropriate to shift here to the term 'flux' for the temporalizing consciousness referred to as self-constituting in being a unity.

TEMPORALITY IN HUSSERL 3 8 I of the serial interpretation of objective or clock time, one second follow- ing the next in a continuous flow along a line. The time and temporality of consciousness itself cannot be adequately modeled by two lines intersect- ing one another, since inner time and inner-time consciousness are really one (form a unity) and are one-dimensional. However, this model may be the simplest way for presenting characteristics of them, the model echoing always with disclaimers - the humanly experienced clock time. The main disclaimer is that the model includes an abstracting conceptualiza- tion that can obviate full awareness of the essentials of consciousness' temporalizing. Are dimensions of inner time and temporality overlooked in this spatial model of flow? As we just saw, the model derives from an abstracting sep- aration. A critical feature of this abstraction is, in fact, a misconstrual of intentionality within consciousness. The model does not offer sufficient scope for glimpsing the variety of intentional currents constantly at work with consciousness' constitutive processes, especially the intentionalities dependent on but not identical with those of immanent temporality. I par- ticularly have in mind the workings of genetic constitution, those of the concrete transcendental ego, of the historicized I. Here I will only indicate aspects of these limitations: First, the shiftings of Sinne (senses, "meanings") throughout the spec- trum of temporalized consciousness cannot be integrated well into this model of two moving tapes, with its implicit system of flows. The vertical and horizontal are pictured as flowing away from one another, at a 9oo angle, whereas genetic associations and their related passivities bounce throughout consciousness' past, present, and future. The only connec- tions of this sort in the model appear to be the diagonals, but these give us little more than an indication of non-temporalizing intentional connec- tions. Besides, if some types of diagonal could display the genetic connec- tions, they would more likely be drawn between lower left and upper right quadrants of the diagram, and in both directions. Thus, there appears to be little ground in the model, in particular, for the shifting "upwards" from the past into both the present and the future, the shiftings of specific concrete Sinne.'5

IS Much of Husserl's discussions of genetic intentionalities is found in Cartesian Medita- tions, Analyses of Passive Synthesis, and Experience and Judgment. For a thorough discussion of Husserl's treatment of association, see Elmar Holenstain, Phanomenologie und Assoziation. Zu Struktur und Funktion eines Grundprinzips der passive Gen- esis bei E. Husserl (The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 1972), although some details of his analyses misalign the various aspects of genetic constitution.

3 8 z MARY JEANNE LARRABEE Take, for example, the smelling Erlebnis mentioned above and let us place it in a concrete context in order to see what some of these Sinn-shift- ings would be. I am walking along a dingy manufacturing street with a friend, both of us in a concentrated discussion of the merits of Nietzsche so that we barely attend to where we walk. There comes wafting past us a strong odor of baking bread. About one half minute after my nose came in contact with the odor, I get indications, floating through the edges of my consciousness, of spring nights in Paris. These indications come as a jum- ble of content - the strong heady smell of French bread, the warm night, another philosophical conversation. My response is an olfactory percep- tion of newly baked bread accompanied by a sudden shift of attention from the current conversation to a strongly felt need to express pleasure at the smell. My friend, on the other hand, barely noticed the bread smell and thinks it odd that I should make so much of it when Nietzsche is far more interesting. The genetic connections are (a) the initial sensory impressions occurring to me that (b) passively associate with (c) the Sinne of bread etc. from years before, so that they (d) are brought to passive rec- ollection, and (e) motivate a present activity (f) which might not have occurred otherwise. This would be only one of various ways that my present can be colored or constituted genetically through associations whose "movements" back and forth throughout consciousness' "temporal field" are not strictly regulated by, although they presuppose, the constituting accomplishments of immanent temporality. Second, the very processing of process itself cannot be adequately indi- cated in a static model. At most the static model grants some room for the movement of flow: the temporally extended Erlebnis is said to move con- tinuously, hence to flow, from time-point to time-point along the inner- time continuum. But such is not thle true processing of this process; the image is simply a mirroring of movement through the world's space (con- ceived from a commonsensical perspective). The processing of Erlebnisse is not merely a spatialized extension across a temporal expanse. For if we look at an analog for flowing in the real world, we would see that the flowing of the river encompasses more than simply the fact that a specific portion of its water traverses a measurable area between two points on its bed. The flowing or process of flow includes more importantly what goes on to the water as it moves between any such points; it includes the dyna- misms of flowing.

III With these limitations on the current static (or any static) model in mind, I would like nonetheless to look at possible variations on the spatial model as a first step to unfolding the full implications of a Husserlian theory of

TEMPORALITY IN HUSSERL 383 immanent temporality. A first step can still only proceed in certain pre- dictable ways, predetermined by the type of model being used (here a spa- tial one). Recognized as a first step, any alternative models at this stage would be pictured with the demonstrated need to incorporate other fea- tures of lived conscious life. A model beginning with Husserlian imma- nent temporality and proceeding eventually to genetic intentionalities is likely to emerge in the end as a preliminary model of consciousness, for Husserl then of an embodied conscious "I" capable of engagement in a variety of ways with world, self and others. We will keep these elements in mind for later. There are several ways in which to formulate alternative models, but in any case we need to replace the somewhat flat or two-dimensional model. We could move to a three-dimensional spatial model or locate a better metaphor for the movement of flow than the passage along a straight line. Here are a number of possibilities, not necessarily mutually exclusive: MODEL A. Introduce coloring into each static picturing of inner time (such as Diagrams I and II). Different colorings will then designate the concrete characteristics of a specific immanent temporal span. The color associated with a specific Erlebnis, for example, the smelling of French bread, will move from each Now out along both vertical and horizontal lines, as well as fill out the space described by addition of diagonals between the appropriate points on the inner time and the inner time-con- sciousness lines. In the rejected Diagram I, such a coloring would picture stripes of color being added at each shift of a new Erlebnis away from the Now, the resultant image being a triangular rainbow. In Diagram II, how- ever, the colors would each pull out from the Now through the triangular space but would remain "connected" to the Now even as new Erlebnisse begin; thus, the colors of non-simulfaneous Erlebnisse could overlap. Each new Now would be pictured as the focal point of the flowing away colors, and these colors could then be reflected in some degree in the pro- tended future of that new Now, so that each new Now would be intrinsi- cally - and distinctively - colored by its own peculiar retentional and protentional horizons. The addition of color would allow for specificities in conscious life, yet this model still flattens the flows and their intercon- nections to a two-dimensional, although bi-modal (lines and color), expression. MODEL B. Change the manner of interconnections for the intentional- ities. Rather than the interconnections of a flow (primarily before and after, yielding the serialized time-continuum), use other water images for example, ripples, vortex, whirlpool. This proposal might move us to a three-dimensional spatial model and one difficult to picture on paper.

3 84 MARY JEANNE LARRABEE One possibility of presenting this three-dimensional model, albeit in a flattened manner, would be through computer-generated graphics that would allow for a picturing of movement of these various kinds.'6 The advantage of this change is the ability to represent some dynamisms of the process itself, for example, the ways in which water pulls and pushes bits of itself along, around and about within the stream, rather than moving in a totally lock step fashion. MODEL C. Increase the ways in which intentional dimensions connect throughout the horizontal and vertical "paths." The more inclusive move here would be to broaden the diagrammings to include the temporalizing as well as other intentionalities, particularly those following from the "active" passivities of genetic associations. The formal structures of immanent temporality, as we have already seen, must be of an appropri- ate complexity to allow inclusion of these genetic associations, wherein elements of present impressions intentionally associate with past elements of Sinn and the retained constitutive activities, so that these impressions effectively result in the shifting of Sinn from past to present and into the future and thus "move" consciousness along. Both model A and model B provide possibilities of picturing these intentionalities, A in its intermingling of colors that show specific Sinne and B in its shift to three-dimensional space with altered imagery. Model C would provide a picturing of those aspects of immanent temporality that set up the possibilities for these intentionalities. The relevant dimen- sion is the unity or one-ness constituted by the vertical (Ldngs-) intention- ality. Without attempting to picture the unity as it really is (not temporal itself but "quasi"-temporal and therefore not a simultaneity), we can draw on its implications to build into our model the implicit connectibility of anything in the model with anything else. In other words, this model will allow us to draw lines (or smear traces of color) from any point within our diagram to any other. If we take our Diagram II (for example), the space set up by immanent temporality includes the lower left quadrant for

i6 Certain branches of recent mathematics, such as the geometry of fractals and other theo- ries of dynamic systems, have demonstrated computer-generated images that capture some of what might prove appropriate here. See, for instance, H.-O. Peitgen and P. H. Richter, The Beauty of Fractals: Images of Complex Dynamical Systems (Berlin: Springer, i986), and Chaos, Fractals, and Dynamics, ed. P. Fischer and W. R. Smith (New York: M. Dekker, i985). Robert L. Devaney notes that nonlinear dynamical sys- tems exhibit behavior that occurs in more general manifolds, specifically the chaotic and random behavior of solutions which can be widely variant given relatively small differ- ences in the initial conditions of the equation; see An Introduction to Chaotic Dynami- cal Systems (Menlo Park, California: Benjamin/Cummings, i986), also James Gleick, Chaos: Making a New Science (New York: Viking Press, i987).

TEMPORALITY IN HUSSERL 385 the past and the upper right for the future, the Now given as a dot. Model C would claim all this area as "present" because of the unifying synthesis of self-temporalizing consciousness, and thus the model would allow all manner of lines to be drawn throughout these two "spaces" in any direc- tions, but all either beginning at, ending at, or moving through the Now. A compilation of the models B and C into one model, intended as a three-dimensional model but pictured here in two-dimensional space, would look something like this, the two quadrants being open-ended cones:.7

is D'

FKN

Ae NN \A

- \!

N is the Now-point. Line AN shows where an Erlebnis occurring Now intentionally relates to a past Sinn, e.g., when my present smelling qua sensation pairs associatively with a past retained Sinn A of French bread. Line NB shows a current Erlebnis providing the specifics of a future experience; e. g., my present smelling of bread qua perceiving act delin- eates the pretended context, "a bakery down the street that I'll get to if I walk this way" (these pretended Sinne need not be conceptually regis- tered). ENF pictures a shift of Sinn from past into pretended future; DNC, a pretended Sinn feeding back into past Sinn; GH, associative connec- tions occurring between past Sinne. While straight lines could be used to display linear connections, curved lines might show other types of connec- tions. Beyond Model C, we might have to take account of the "solidity" or "extensity" of the impressional consciousness itself,'8 conjoined as it is

17 If the reader is familiar with Hermann Minkowski's i908 geometry of events in space- time, similarities may be apparent between his diagram of four-dimensional objective world and my diagram of "subjective" temporality; see Jonathan Powers, Philosophy and the New Physics (New York: Methuen, i982), p. 96. This similarity might prove helpful in pursuing the correlations between immanent temporality and the structures of experienced world time. i8 See, for instance, Ideas I, section 8i, p. i6z; and E. Husserl, Ideen zu einer reinen phd- nomenologischen Philosophie, Second Book, ed. Marly Biemel, Husserliana, Vol. 4 (The Hague:Martinus Nijhoff, I95z), p. 149: ". . . Localizationof feelings[Empfindnisse] is in fact something in principle different from extension of any material attributes of

386 MARY JEANNE LARRABEE with (a) the spatial embodiment of the human subject - the "space" within which sensory impressions occur, and (b) the simultaneously occurring acts, e.g., of perceiving, imagining, etc. And this total Now-con- sciousness (consciousness taking place in the present Now) is necessarily correlated with the intentionally constituted world with its objects occu- pying three-dimensionally objective space and enduring through objec- tive time. The addition of such elements to any model of time, that is, to display the intentional relationship between constituting immanent tem- porality and constituted objective time, would immediately show the pov- erty of our current models and diagrams with respect to the picturing of the Now, which occupies a mere point. Perhaps the model must move into hyperspace or some other multi-dimensional model. We could continue, but these indications for further work are sufficient for our purpose here."'

IV The recognition of possibilities for an alternative modeling of time, espe- cially those that allow for the explication of the genetic associative consti- tutions on the basis of immanent temporality, is crucial to a full articula- tion of the complexities of conscious life, not as abstractively pictured in the diagrammings of inner time as quasi-geometric lines, but as actually lived by human individuals Where an account of inner time-conscious- things' They are indeed spread in space. . . . However, this spread [extensity, Ausbreit- ung] . . . is indeed something essentially different from extension [Ausdehnung] in the sense of all the attributes that characterize the res extensa" (italics omitted). '9 Diagrams in multi-dimensional geometry offer some ideas for breaking out of the two- or three-dimensional portrayals of mental structure. A move to at least a four-dimensional spatial model (a model in hyperspace) that then incorporates process (e.g., as a computer generated graphic) throughout the model would allow the imaging of this "extensity" of Now-consciousness in its concreteness, rather than in the overly abstracted manner of a point. A general discussion of multi-dimensional geometry can be found in R. Rucker, Geometry,Relativity and the FourthDimension (New York: Dover, 1977), or Jeffrey R. Weeks, The Shape of Space: How to VisualizeSurfaces and Three-Dimensional Manifolds (New York: Marcel Dekker, i985), or Rucker's more expansive work, The Fourth Dimension: Toward a Geometry of Higher Reality (Boston: Houghton Mifflin, i984).

20 Given the abstractiveness and limitations of models for consciousness, why continue try- ing to picture it at all? Imagery, metaphors, models, and the like have been historically implicated in the continuing growth of knowledge.' While these are not a necessary condi- tion for understanding either reality or consciousness, they have been used to great effect in many fields and undertakings. For instance, Robert W. Weisberg claims that the dis- covery of the structure of DNA by James Watson and Francis Crick was fostered by their commitment to use model-building as an integral part of their research; chapter 6 in Cre- ativity:Genius and OtherMyths (New York: W. H. Freeman, i986). K. J. Gilhooly, Thinking:Directed, Undirectedand Creative(London: Academic Press, i98z), cites

TEMPORALITY IN HUSSERL 387 ness must end in a claim that certain supposed experiences of some human individuals are of little account for a phenomenological science of con- scious life, such an unfolding of the contours of inner time-consciousness has abstracted too far from concrete human living. The formal descrip- tion of inner-time consciousness must articulate with some persons' experiences of the beautiful, with others' experiences of the ineffable within themselves or of the peculiar but seemingly ever,-presentambigui- ties of human existence, as much as with human experiences of the mathe- matical. It must be coherent with the experiences of the inexpressible and with the inexpressible of experience, just as much as with the experience of one small apple, of one continuous tone, or of one pure concept. Many of these types of human experience find their descriptive basis more in the nameless Absolute of immanent temporality than in the abstractively pre- sented quasi-serial flow of the horizontal line."' And, more importantly, we must recognize that the abstractive separation of this horizontal line of the inner time series from the vertical line of the various consciousnesses of it is paralleled by the abstractive separation of this formal description of immanent temporality from the concrete living out of it within the dynamic of genetic associative interconnections that concretely fill out the contexts and horizons of each Now. This dynamic, located at the center of what Husserl terms the living present, may very well be the source of the processing that is immanent temporality - an appropriate account of which is lacking in any interpretation based on a Diagram I or two-dimen- sional model for inner time. A full account of processing precludes the

the advantages of model building in problem-solving. Rudolf Rucker concedes the help- fulness of images in elaborating four-dimensional space, but notes that they are not in fact needed to carry out mathematical analysis; see his image (in two dimensions) of a hypercube in Geometry. I would thus agree with positions integrating all human experiences into consideration under conscious experience, as found, for example, in John R. Battista's psychological work. Battista rejects the limitation of the term "consciousness" to reflective awareness, since such would leave out early.pre-reflective childhood experience, all dreaming, and "ecstatic" or mystical experiences occurring without self-awareness; this use of the term consciousness', however, need not imply any existential claims concerning the object of the experiences. See "The Science of Consciousness," in The Stream of Consciousness: Scientific Investigations into the Flow of Human Experience, ed. K. S. Pope and J. L. Singer (New York: Plenum Press, 1978), pp. 5 7-87. Eliot Deutsch reflects the eastern tra- dition, in Personbood, Creativity, and Freedom (Honolulu: University of Hawaii Press, i982), by describing consciousness as a power "the being of which is to be bound or boundless," that is, either tied to objects and thus temporal, or unified and thus timeless (pp. 3 5-3 6). This view coheres to some extent with Robert E. Ornstein's psychology that posits two major modes of consciousness, analytic and holistic (related to rational and intuitive knowing), in The Psychology of Consciousness, zd ed. (New York: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich, 1977). Parallels between Husserl's phenomenology of time and these recent psychologies of consciousness might be worth pursuing.

388 MARY JEANNE LARRABEE reductionof inner time to a series, for this processingencompasses the slippage between membersof any time that is conceptualizedas series. Accordingto geneticanalysis, the Now is the centerof humanlife and of inner-timeconsciousness as temporalizing.Each Now in its concreteness prescribesthe effectivenessof the past upon it and the pretending of specificsinto its future.An expansionon sucha descriptionof a concretely lived Now must be accomplishedwhen searchingfor the appropriate model, spatial or otherwise,for immanenttemporality. Furtherelaboration of immanenttemporality must not only serveas a basisfor the wide varietyof humanexperience and the geneticanalyses of them, but extend discussionsto includethe concretemonadological ego or "I."" For it is the I who now exists in its concretealive presence,acts now in beginningto act in specificways towards an object or person within its world, continuesnow acting,or ends that actingnow through movingon to act in furtherways towardsother persons or things.But this concreteI is calledtoward activity in a Now, not by an absentfuture, but by its concretelypresent future as it is delineatedby an associativeprojec- tion of senses,Sinne. The delineationsof sensesonto a futureis rootedin this Now, for these Sinneare calledfrom the I's past that is still presentto it. These shiftingsof Sinnecontinuously move forward,as temporalized Erlebnissecontinuously move back, togetherwith the total contexts in which they occur (includingany noemata constitutivelycorrelated to acts;also the horizontalintentionalities of thesecore noemata). Thus each Now is not so much an absence definedby its not being either past or future,but is the livingconcrete I presentto the veryslippage that placesit within the constitutiveprocessing that continuouslyprovides a specified context, a worldthat it lives.These few topicsdisplay an essentialconnec- tion betweenthe seeminglyformal discussions of immanenttemporality and the extraordinarilyconcrete and materiallyspecified life of the living I, a connectionthat must be elaboratedfully beforethe contoursof Hus- serl'stheory of innertime can be said to have been filledout.3 Verylittle

2I prefer the more literal translation of Ich, despite its seeming awkwardness. I take the primary usage of 'I' to be the primal sense of a vague identifiable and self-identified "etwas," this something or other of the natural attitude which is the "core" of the con- scious being that human beings are. The 'I' exists inchoately within very early human life and is a sense that shapes most of an individual's human existence. It is this 'I' that I accept in the natural attitude as 'just there' and that I question as I move into the phenom- enological attitude, seeing myself as a "different" I while phenomenologizing, although still the "same" I. The recognition within the phenomenological epoche of the essential characteristics of this 'I' carries with it no metaphysical commitment to a substantial ego or ego-subject in the traditional sense, nor does it necessarily carry with it a Humean scepticism concerning personal identity. 23 Charles T. Tart attempts, from a psychological perspective, a static diagram of a concrete

TEMPORALITY IN HUSSERL 3 89 of these topics can even be allowed such a connection if the original, Dia- gram I, variety of spatial model for inner time substitutes for a richer alter- native. A move toward the models proposed above or other alternative models for the immanent temporality of consciousness has ramifications beyond those already mentioned. I am interested, for example, in how it might cohere with and further explicate the kinaesthesia of -embodied existing that is the current mode of human living. Several criticisms have been lev- eled against what is taken as the full story concerning Husserl's theory of sensation in general and of kinaesthetic sensings in particular.4 Since bodily "space" is temporalized both within and beyond the delimited space of the physical body as "living thing in objective space-time," the fundamental temporalizing of immanent time-consciousness has to be capable of accounting for, and of grounding constitutively, a multi- dimensionality of immanent spatiality which itself resists the usual mod- els of objective space.5 For Husserl, the kinaesthetic field provides the ground zero of the impressional consciousness of the embodied human

consciousness with its embedded but interacting structures of habituated materials; this diagram might show a "multidimensional map of psychological space" allowing one to determine "where the individual is in that space." See his "Discrete States of Conscious- ness," in Symposium on Consciousness (American Association for the Advancement of Science, 1974), ed. Philip R. Lee, et al. (New York: Viking Press, I976), pp. 89-175. 24 Several accounts of Husserl's theory of sensation dismiss the phenomenologist's reflective access to hyletic data, thus calling their "existence" for phenomenology into question; see, for instance, Quentin Smith, "A Phenomenological Examination of Hus- serl's Theory of Hyletic Data," Philosophy Today zi (1977): 356-67. Others miscon- strue the nature of hyletic data due to importations of faulty assumptions concerning Husserl's phenomenological method and the like. While retaining the notion of hyletic data or "experience," for example, Shaun Gallagher disconnects hyletic experience and thus the body from consciousness; this move reifies either the body or consciousness in a way not intended by Husserl. See "Hyletic Experience and the Lived Body," Husserl Studies 3 (i986): 13i-66. 25 notes a connection between temporalizing and spatializing within Hus- serl; see Speech and Phenomenon, trans. D. B. Allison (Evanston: Northwestern Uni- versity Press, 1973), p. 143. Derrida's conflation of temporalizing and spatializing, how- ever, is too simple a reading of Husserl's text. Robert Magliola deals with Derrida's view of time in Derrida on the Mend (West Lafayette, Indiana: , i984); he summarizes Derrida as saying that for Husserl ". . . the relation of the 'present' to the 'past' and 'future' is a negative relation, that is, the present is not the not-now." Magliola notes interestingly enough that "the human mind, for Derrida, always defines by negative reference and only by negative reference" (p. 24). Whether or not Magliola accurately captures Derrida's position, I am inclined to reject such a view of human mind, because the foundational aspect of consciousness, the "cause" of those differences, must itself be beyond such distinctions, especially when they are presented in a conceptualized fashion. Husserl's descriptions of flux, especially of the living present, display the core of con- scious life, whereas such a negativizing thrust covers it up.

390 MARY JEANNE LARRABEE subjectivity. It might be said that impressional consciousness is "located" throughout the kinaesthetic field - the latter, of course, a multi-faceted dimension of the impressional Now.76 The primary spatial model for time is often associated with the imagery drawn from bodily/kinaesthetic movements - the body moving forward, towards its future, away from its past ("Leave your past behind you"); the inclination is thus strong to tie both inner time and the kinaesthetic field to objective space. We must differentiate, however, between Husserl's attempts to describe the essen- tial features of our natural attitude, including its often naive interpreta- tions of our own lived spatiality and immanent temporality, and Husserl's transcendentally phenomenological accounts of what makes the natural attitude possible. There is much work to be done in this area.Z7 A reflection upon alternative models might also move against several current flows within contemporary philosophical life. A recasting of Hus- serl's consciousness into something irretrievably linguistic in all its occur- rences cannot sustain Husserl's task of an essential description of human conscious activities.8 It would indeed have to admit a limitation to fairly specified areas of Husserl interpretation or agree to an incompatibility of what it claims is Husserl's theory and much of Husserl's text, particularly that on temporality and the intrinsically connected discussions of genetic constitution.

z6 There are many interesting hints, with Husserl's C-Manuscripts particularly, of the dynamics of the living present and its connections with impressional consciousness, kinaesthesia, genetic elements, the "I" and other specifics of conscious life. See, for exam- ple, C z 1 (1931)- 27 Algis Mickunas shows one important direction that a phenomenology of kinaesthesia and therefore corporeality must take - he links the pre-theoretical level of vital-kinaes- thetic involvements in the world with the moral level of human activities; see "The Vital Connection," Analecta Husserliana z2 (i987): 35-53. J. N. Mohanty locates an approach to the phenomenon of body and thus of kinaesthesia in his attack upon the Hei- deggerian and post-modernist anti-foundationalisms; he includes body as one of three "recalcitrant phenomena" that only transcendental reflection can free from a self-forget- fulness tied to naive human life. See "The Destiny of Transcendental Philosophy," in Phenomenology in a Pluralistic Context (Albany: State University of New York Press, i983), ed. W. McBrideand C. Schrag,pp, 235-43, especiallyfrom p. 240 on. z8 Both Maurita J. Harney and J. N. Mohanty discuss the way in which Husserl's account of intentionality can actually supplement Frege's theory of sense, their work being in part responses to recent interpretations of Husserl's view of Sinn, noema, and Bedeutung as analogous to aspects of Fregean semantical theory. Harvey rejects a F0llesdalian view, in Intentionality, Sense and the Mind (The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, i984), especially p. 145; Mohanty clarifies the appropriateness of F0llesdal's theses on noema if read with care, but rejects Dreyfus' reading, as well as any reduction of all Husserlian Sinn to con- ceptual meaning (Bedeutung), in Husserl and Frege (Bloomington: Indiana University

Press, i98z), pp. 75-85 and II5-i6.

TEMPORALITY IN HUSSERL 391 The attack from deconstructivists and other "post-modernists" attempting a move beyond the end of metaphysics would have to be reconstituted, its critique of the philosophy of "presence" clarified with respect to a Husserl whose central presence of consciousness is present only in its very slippage between the future and the past which it consti- tutes in a sense not captured by any word-play or textually linear re-read- ings. If we can devise a spatial model that cannot be tied to a two-dimen- sional reading of logical thinking, the Husserlian theory of immanent time can capture the inexorably complex interplay of consciousness. It might even capture, in an essential description, the human attempts to philoso- phize seemingly beyond but still within the limits of Western thought.'9

29 For a discussion of Husserl's theory of immanent time from a Derridean perspective, see Rudolf Bernet, "Die ungegenwartige Gegenwart. Anwesenheit und Abwesenheit in Hus- serls Analysedes Zeitbewusstseins,"Pbdnomenologische Forschung I4 (i983): i6-57. In contrast, Alan White criticizes Derrida's failure to appreciate "the subtleties of Hus- serl's account of the interplay of presence and absence," p. 46. Robert Sokolowski is more direct, citing the presence of Derridean absence in Husserl's discussions of objective givenness; see "The Theory of Phenomenological Description," in Descriptions (Albany: State University of New York, i985), ed. D. Ihde and H. Silverman, pp. 25-34.

39X MARY JEANNE LARRABEE