Observation and Adaptation Etymology: from the Latin “Ad

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Observation and Adaptation Etymology: from the Latin “Ad Observation and Adaptation Etymology: from the Latin “ad” = toward, “aptus” = fitted, appropriate Three dictionary definitions for adaptation in the biological sense: 1. any alteration in the structure or function of an organism or any of its parts that results from natural selection and by which the organism becomes better fitted to survive and multiply in its environment 2. a form or structure modified to fit a changed environment 3. the ability of a species to survive in a particular ecological niche, esp. because of alterations of form or behavior brought about through natural selection In this lab, we will be most interested in the second definition, i.e., in traits that are called adaptations. In particular, we will be concerned with how one can demonstrate that a trait is, in fact an adaptation. This is one of the major activities of evolutionary biology. Adaptation as defined in Freeman (2002): Any heritable trait that increases the fitness of an individual with that trait compared to individuals without the trait. This definition leaves out one feature that is considered key when deciding whether or not a trait is an adaptation: did the feature evolve in response to selection for the function it currently performs? This issue was discussed most famously in a 1979 paper called “The Spandrels of San Marco and the Panglossian Paradigm: a critique of the adaptationist programme” by Stephen J. Gould and Richard Lewontin. The message of this paper was that we shouldn’t assume that every feature of an organism is an adaptation, i.e., that it was molded by natural selection for its current function. Gould and Lewontin chide adaptationists for making up too many adaptive stories, akin to Rudyard Kipling’s Just-So Stories (e.g., “How the Leopard Got Its Spots,” “How the Camel Got Its Hump,” etc.). It’s very easy, particularly with a little practice, to look at traits of an organism and come up with stories about why they are adaptive. This is fine as long as the stories can be made into testable hypotheses. The danger lies in making up stories and then accepting them based on their plausibility alone. Gould and Lewontin referred to the adaptationist program as the “Panglossian Paradigm” in reference to the character of Pangloss in Voltaire’s Candide. Pangloss’s philosophy is “...that things cannot be other than they are, for since everything was made for a purpose, it follows that everything is made for the best purpose. Observe: our noses were made to carry spectacles, so we have spectacles. Legs were clearly intended for breeches, and we wear them.” (Penguin Classics edition, p. 20) Gould and Lewontin accuse people who follow the adaptationist program of making essentially the same mistakes as Pangloss, albeit in a Darwinian context. An adaptationist (to continue the absurd example from Candide) might observe a group of people with glasses, note that the nose is holding up the glasses in each of these individuals, and infer that noses are adaptations for holding up glasses. Nobody would deny the utility of noses for holding up glasses, but this example is trivial enough for it to be clear that noses probably evolved in response to selection for some other function and were later co-opted for eyeglass- holding-up. The giraffe-neck presents another possible case in which the seemingly obvious function for which a feature is adaptive may not actually be the function for which the feature evolved. Why is the giraffe neck so long? The most oft-cited evolutionary scenario is that it allows giraffes to reach branches not accessible to other animals, thus providing them with a unique food source. When a feature is secondarily coopted for a function other than the one for which it originally evolved, it has historically been known as a “preadaptation.” This is a somewhat dangerous term because it sounds as if it means that a feature evolved with some goal in mind (e.g., that the giraffe neck became longer in anticipation of future utility for feeding on high leaves.). Still, it is a useful term in that it distinguishes between features that evolved due to natural selection for their current functions, and features that originally evolved for one function and then were coopted for a later function. You should be able to distinguish between a “preadaptation” and an adaptation. It is also possible that some traits are just not “adaptive,” e.g., they may be by-products of the physical architecture of an organism, or they may be due to developmental or genetic constraints. Gould and Lewontin use a non-biological architectural example: The spandrels of San Marco. They discuss the dome of the cathedral of San Marco in Venice and note that there are beautiful mosaics in the triangular spaces that occur where the round dome meets two rounded arches that meet at right angles. An adaptationist might assume that those spaces were put there just so the mosaics would have a spot to live. In fact, these spaces (called spandrels, or, more precisely, “pendentives”), are a necessary by-product of placing a round dome on four rounded arches that occur at right angles to each other. Once the architect decided to build the dome that way, there was no getting around having these spandrels. Three hundred years after the cathedral was built, the mosaics were put in the spandrels. Clearly, the spandrels had no function in and of themselves when the cathedral was built, but somebody later put them to good use. Gould has written a paper suggesting that the word “spandrel” be used in biology to name features that arise without initial adaptive functions (e.g., those that are architectural by-products of development) but take on new functions later in evolution (Gould 1997). Gould had earlier proposed, in a paper with Elizabeth Vrba (Gould and Vrba 1982), that we call traits that perform a current adaptive function but arose either for some other function or with no adaptive function at all as “exaptations.” Thus both preadaptations and “spandrels” qualify as exaptations. The terminology may seem very nitpicky, but it forces us to think about the details of a trait and how it might have evolved, and it forces us to go beyond the mere creation of plausible stories in the study of adaptation. One example Gould gives of a “biological spandrel” is the umbilicus of a snail shell. A snail shell grows by coiling a tube around a central axis. The space along the axis that necessarily results is known as the umbilicus. The space is a by-product of how the shell is built, but some snails use the umbilicus to brood eggs. Gould poses the question: is the umbilicus a spandrel in the sense that it arose as a geometric by- product of coiling a tube around an axis and was then coopted by some snail species to be used in egg brooding, or was the design of the shell selectively favored because it provided this handy space for brooding eggs? Gould looks at a phylogeny of gastropods and notes that although all species have an umbilicus, only a few species brood eggs in it, and one can map the apparent origin of this use of the umbilicus on the tree. He concludes that these few independent origins of egg brooding in the umbilicus suggest that the umbilicus space arose as a spandrel that was coopted for egg-brooding in several snail lineages. This example serves as a transition to the next topic: the comparative method. Given that we want to perform rigorous tests for adaptation rather than just making up plausible stories, how can we do this? The comparative method seeks to evaluate hypotheses by testing for patterns across species, such as correlations among traits, or correlations between traits and features of the environment. For example, if we consistently see a certain feature associated with a certain environment (e.g., white fur in arctic mammals), then we might ask whether selective pressures in that environment favor that phenotype. Or, if we consistently see two traits occurring together (e.g., long, thin beaks in nectar-feeding birds, large testes in bats with large group sizes), we might see if there is some adaptive reason for that association. In the bat example discussed in your textbook, it was hypothesized that it is advantageous for males of bat species that roost in large groups to have relatively large testes because females in larger groups are more likely to have multiple matings, and sperm competition is likely to be more intense as a consequence. Phylogenies and the Comparative Method: a hypothetical example Imagine that you look across ten bird species and see that there are eight species in which two traits (e.g., a long beak and a nectar diet) appear together and two species in which the birds have neither trait. This seems like an interesting pattern, and it suggests that the beak shape is an adaptation for feeding on nectar. You might be tempted to perform a standard statistical test of association between beak morphology and diet (e.g., a chi-square test of association). A problem arises when one considers the assumptions of the statistical tests one would use in this situation. One assumption of standard statistical tests (parametric and nonparametric alike) is that the observations are independent of each other. This is generally true when observations are sampled randomly from a population—the probability of picking one item is independent of the probability of picking another. Another way of thinking about this is in terms of data values—in a sample of independent observations, knowing the value of one observation does not tell you anything about the value of another observation.
Recommended publications
  • The Spandrels of Self-Deception: Prospects for a Biological Theory of a Mental Phenomenon
    The Spandrels of Self-Deception: Prospects for a Biological Theory of a Mental Phenomenon D. S. Neil Van Leeuwen Self-deception is so undeniable a fact of human life that if anyone tried to deny its existence, the proper response would be to accuse this person of it. —Allen Wood1 1. Introduction to the Problems Even prior to a characterization of self-deception, it’s easy to see that it’s widespread. This is puzzling, because self-deception seems paradoxical. Here are three apparent problems. First, self-deception seems to involve a conceptual contradiction; in order to deceive, one must believe the contrary of the deception one is perpetrating, but if one believes the contrary, it seems impossible for that very self to believe the deception.2 Second, a view of the mind has become widely accepted that makes rationality constitutive and exhaustive of the mental; this is the interpretive view of the mental put forth by Donald Davidson and followers.3 According to this view, the idea of attributing irrational beliefs to agents makes little sense, for we cannot make sense of what someone’s beliefs are unless they are rational. But self-deception is highly irrational.4 Third, a brief survey of other cognitive mechanisms (such as vision) reveals that most are well suited for giving us reliable information about ourselves and our environment. Self- deception, however, undermines knowledge of ourselves and the world. If having good information brings fitness benefits to organisms, how is it that self-deception was not weeded out by natural selection? Otherwise put, why does self-deception exist? (For convenience, I shall refer to these as puzzles 1, 2, and 3.) Puzzles such as these make self-deception an intriguing explanatory target.
    [Show full text]
  • The Spandrels of San Marco and the Panglossian Paradigm: a Critique of the Adaptationist Programme
    The Spandrels of San Marco and the Panglossian Paradigm: A Critique of the Adaptationist Programme. (Excerpted1 by W. M. Schaffer) Stephen Jay Gould and Richard C. Lewontin. 1979. Proc. Roy. Soc. London, Ser. B, 505: 581-598. An adaptationist programme has dominated evolutionary thought in England and the United States during the past forty years. It is based on faith in the power of natural selection as an optimizing agent. It proceeds by breaking an organism into unitary "traits" and proposing an adaptive story for each considered separately. Trade-offs among competing selective demands exert the only brake upon perfection; non-optimality is thereby rendered as a result of adaptation as well. We criticize this approach and attempt to reassert a competing notion (long popular in continental Europe) that organisms must be analyzed as integrated wholes, with Baupläne[2] so constrained by phyletic heritage, pathways of development, and general architecture that the constraints them- selves become more interesting and more important in delimiting pathways of change than the selective force that may mediate change when it occurs. We fault the adaptationist programme for its failure to distinguish current utility from reasons for origin (male tyrannosaurs may have used their diminutive front legs to titillate female partners, but this will not explain why they got so small); for its unwillingness to consider alternatives to adaptive stories; for its reliance upon plau- sibility alone as a criterion for accepting speculative tales; and for its failure to consider adequately such competing themes as random fixation of alleles, production of non-adaptive structures by developmental correlation with selected features … , the separability of adaptation and selection, multiple adaptive peaks, and current utility as an epiphenomenon of nonadaptive structures.
    [Show full text]
  • Exaptation, Adaptation, and Evolutionary Psychology
    Exaptation, Adaptation, and Evolutionary Psychology Armin Schulz Department of Philosophy, Logic, and Scientific Method London School of Economics and Political Science Houghton St London WC2A 2AE UK [email protected] (0044) 753-105-3158 Abstract One of the most well known methodological criticisms of evolutionary psychology is Gould’s claim that the program pays too much attention to adaptations, and not enough to exaptations. Almost as well known is the standard rebuttal of that criticism: namely, that the study of exaptations in fact depends on the study of adaptations. However, as I try to show in this paper, it is premature to think that this is where this debate ends. First, the notion of exaptation that is commonly used in this debate is different from the one that Gould and Vrba originally defined. Noting this is particularly important, since, second, the standard reply to Gould’s criticism only works if the criticism is framed in terms of the former notion of exaptation, and not the latter. However, third, this ultimately does not change the outcome of the debate much, as evolutionary psychologists can respond to the revamped criticism of their program by claiming that the original notion of exaptation is theoretically and empirically uninteresting. By discussing these issues further, I also seek to determine, more generally, which ways of approaching the adaptationism debate in evolutionary biology are useful, and which not. Exaptation, Adaptation, and Evolutionary Psychology Exaptation, Adaptation, and Evolutionary Psychology I. Introduction From a methodological point of view, one of the most well known accusations of evolutionary psychology – the research program emphasising the importance of appealing to evolutionary considerations in the study of the mind – is the claim that it is overly “adaptationist” (for versions of this accusation, see e.g.
    [Show full text]
  • Exaptation in Human Evolution: How to Test Adaptive Vs Exaptive Evolutionary Hypotheses
    doi 10.4436/jass.89015 JASs Invited Reviews Journal of Anthropological Sciences Vol. 89 (2011), pp. 9-23 Exaptation in human evolution: how to test adaptive vs exaptive evolutionary hypotheses Telmo Pievani & Emanuele Serrelli University of Milan Bicocca, Piazza dell’Ateneo Nuovo, n. 1 - 20126 Milan, Italy e-mail: [email protected]; [email protected] Summary - Palaeontologists, Stephen J. Gould and Elisabeth Vrba, introduced the term “ex-aptation” with the aim of improving and enlarging the scientific language available to researchers studying the evolution of any useful character, instead of calling it an “adaptation” by default, coming up with what Gould named an “extended taxonomy of fitness” . With the extension to functional co-optations from non-adaptive structures (“spandrels”), the notion of exaptation expanded and revised the neo-Darwinian concept of “pre- adaptation” (which was misleading, for Gould and Vrba, suggesting foreordination). Exaptation is neither a “saltationist” nor an “anti-Darwinian” concept and, since 1982, has been adopted by many researchers in evolutionary and molecular biology, and particularly in human evolution. Exaptation has also been contested. Objections include the “non-operationality objection”.We analyze the possible operationalization of this concept in two recent studies, and identify six directions of empirical research, which are necessary to test “adaptive vs. exaptive” evolutionary hypotheses. We then comment on a comprehensive survey of literature (available online), and on the basis of this we make a quantitative and qualitative evaluation of the adoption of the term among scientists who study human evolution. We discuss the epistemic conditions that may have influenced the adoption and appropriate use of exaptation, and comment on the benefits of an “extended taxonomy of fitness” in present and future studies concerning human evolution.
    [Show full text]
  • Literature Meets Biology: an Evolutionary Approach to Literary Studies
    University of Montana ScholarWorks at University of Montana Graduate Student Theses, Dissertations, & Professional Papers Graduate School 2011 Literature Meets Biology: An Evolutionary Approach to Literary Studies Samantha Reneé Dwyer The University of Montana Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarworks.umt.edu/etd Let us know how access to this document benefits ou.y Recommended Citation Dwyer, Samantha Reneé, "Literature Meets Biology: An Evolutionary Approach to Literary Studies" (2011). Graduate Student Theses, Dissertations, & Professional Papers. 628. https://scholarworks.umt.edu/etd/628 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Graduate School at ScholarWorks at University of Montana. It has been accepted for inclusion in Graduate Student Theses, Dissertations, & Professional Papers by an authorized administrator of ScholarWorks at University of Montana. For more information, please contact [email protected]. LITERATURE MEETS BIOLOGY: AN EVOLUTIONARY APPROACH TO LITERARY STUDIES INCLUDING A READING OF HEJINIAN’S MY LIFE AND SHAKESPEARE’S KING LEAR by Samantha Reneé Dwyer Bachelor of Arts, English Literature, University of Montana Missoula, MT 2007 Thesis presented in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Master of Arts in English Literature The University of Montana Missoula, MT December 2010 Approved by: Perry Brown, Associate Provost for Graduate Education Graduate School Louise Economides, Co-Chair English John Glending, Co-Chair English Sarah Certel Biology Contents Introduction……………………………..…………………………………………………………1 Chapter 1: The Present State of English Departments………………………………………….…5 I. The descent of humanities.......……………………………………………………………5 II. Current problems with literary theory…………………………………………………….8 Chapter 2: Introducing Evocriticism……………………………………………………………..18 I. A new paradigm………………………………………………………………………….18 II. A cautious approach……………………………………………………………………...23 III.
    [Show full text]
  • Macroevolutionary Patterns of Flowering Plant Speciation and Extinction
    PP69CH25_Vamosi ARI 4 April 2018 8:6 Annual Review of Plant Biology Macroevolutionary Patterns of Flowering Plant Speciation and Extinction Jana C. Vamosi,1 Susana Magallon,´ 2 Itay Mayrose,3 Sarah P. Otto,4 and HerveSauquet´ 5,6 1Department of Biological Sciences, University of Calgary, Calgary, Alberta T2N 1N4, Canada; email: [email protected] 2Instituto de Biologıa,´ Universidad Nacional Autonoma´ de Mexico,´ Ciudad de Mexico´ 04510, Mexico´ 3Department of Molecular Biology and Ecology of Plants, George S. Wise Faculty of Life Sciences, Tel Aviv University, Tel Aviv 69978, Israel 4Department of Zoology and the Biodiversity Research Centre, University of British Columbia, Vancouver, British Columbia V6T 1Z4, Canada 5Laboratoire Ecologie,´ Systematique,´ Evolution,´ Universite´ Paris-Sud, CNRS UMR 8079, 91405 Orsay, France 6National Herbarium of New South Wales (NSW), Royal Botanic Gardens and Domain Trust, Sydney, NSW 2000, Australia Annu. Rev. Plant Biol. 2018. 69:685–706 Keywords First published as a Review in Advance on biome, conservation, dispersal, diversification, pollination, polyploidy, February 28, 2018 sexual system The Annual Review of Plant Biology is online at plant.annualreviews.org Abstract https://doi.org/10.1146/annurev-arplant-042817- Species diversity is remarkably unevenly distributed among flowering plant 040348 Annu. Rev. Plant Biol. 2018.69:685-706. Downloaded from www.annualreviews.org lineages. Despite a growing toolbox of research methods, the reasons under- Access provided by University of British Columbia on 05/17/18. For personal use only. Copyright c 2018 by Annual Reviews. lying this patchy pattern have continued to perplex plant biologists for the All rights reserved past two decades. In this review, we examine the present understanding of transitions in flowering plant evolution that have been proposed to influence speciation and extinction.
    [Show full text]
  • Florida State University Libraries
    Florida State University Libraries Electronic Theses, Treatises and Dissertations The Graduate School 2009 Literary Studies and the Third Culture Curtis D. Carbonell Follow this and additional works at the FSU Digital Library. For more information, please contact [email protected] FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY COLLEGE OF ARTS AND SCIENCES LITERARY STUDIES AND THE THIRD CULTURE By CURTIS D. CARBONELL A Dissertation sub itted to the Depart ent of Interdisciplinary Hu anities in partial fulfill ent of the require ents for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy Degree Awarded: Spring Se ester, 2..9 Copyright 0 2..9 Curtis D. Carbonell All Rights Reser1ed The e bers of the Co ittee appro1e the Dissertation of Curtis D. Carbonell defended on Dece ber 9th, 2..2. ______________________ 4ar5 Cooper Professor Co-Directing Dissertation ______________________ Ralph Berry Professor Co-Directing Dissertation ______________________ 4ichael Ruse Outside Co ittee 4e ber ______________________ Da1id 7ohnson Co ittee 4e ber Appro1ed: _____________________________________________ Da1id 7ohnson, Chair, Depart ent of Interdisciplinary Hu anities ii TABLE OF CONTENTS TABLE OF CONTENTS...................................................................................................iii ABSTRACT........................................................................................................................1 PREFACE .........................................................................................................................1ii INTRODUCTION...............................................................................................................1
    [Show full text]
  • Male and Female Nipples As a Test Case for the Assumption That Functional Features Vary Less Than Nonfunctional Byproducts
    Male and Female Nipples as a Test Case for the Assumption that Functional Features Vary Less than Nonfunctional Byproducts Ashleigh J. Kelly, Shelli L. Dubbs, Fiona Kate Barlow & Brendan P. Zietsch Adaptive Human Behavior and Physiology e-ISSN 2198-7335 Adaptive Human Behavior and Physiology DOI 10.1007/s40750-018-0096-1 1 23 Your article is protected by copyright and all rights are held exclusively by Springer International Publishing AG, part of Springer Nature. This e-offprint is for personal use only and shall not be self-archived in electronic repositories. If you wish to self-archive your article, please use the accepted manuscript version for posting on your own website. You may further deposit the accepted manuscript version in any repository, provided it is only made publicly available 12 months after official publication or later and provided acknowledgement is given to the original source of publication and a link is inserted to the published article on Springer's website. The link must be accompanied by the following text: "The final publication is available at link.springer.com”. 1 23 Author's personal copy Adaptive Human Behavior and Physiology https://doi.org/10.1007/s40750-018-0096-1 ORIGINAL ARTICLE Male and Female Nipples as a Test Case for the Assumption that Functional Features Vary Less than Nonfunctional Byproducts Ashleigh J. Kelly1 & Shelli L. Dubbs1 & Fiona Kate Barlow1 & Brendan P. Zietsch1 Received: 19 April 2018 /Revised: 16 May 2018 /Accepted: 17 May 2018 # Springer International Publishing AG, part of Springer Nature 2018 Abstract Objectives Evolutionary researchers have sometimes taken findings of low variation in the size or shape of a biological feature to indicate that it is functional and under strong evolutionary selection, and have assumed that high variation implies weak or absent selection and therefore lack of function.
    [Show full text]
  • Evidence for the Adaptive Evolution Minireview of Mutation Rates
    Cell, Vol. 101, 581±584, June 9, 2000, Copyright 2000 by Cell Press Evidence for the Adaptive Evolution Minireview of Mutation Rates David Metzgar*³ and Christopher Wills*² under starvation conditions in Escherichia coli (Rosen- *Department of Biology berg et al., 1998). Loss-of-function mutations in genes ² Center for Molecular Genetics required for growth can back-mutate, allowing survival University of California, San Diego and reproduction. The rate of these back-mutations (as La Jolla, California 92093 well as of other, nonadaptive mutations) increases greatly with starvation. This mutator phenotype is not itself heritableÐthe survivors produce progeny cells Adaptive evolution has long been regarded as the result with normal mutation rates. of postmutational sorting by the process of natural se- The SOS response has been implicated in such adap- lection. Mutations have been postulated to occur at ran- tive mutation (Rosenberg et al., 1998). The SOS system dom, producing genetically different individuals that is a DNA repair mechanism induced when the E. coli then compete for resources, the result being selection genome suffers physical damage such as double-strand of better adapted genotypes. Molecular biology has breaks, and can be triggered by starvation. It includes demonstrated, however, that the rate and spectrum of alternative DNA polymerase enzymes, such as DinB and mutations is in large part under the control of genetic the UmuDЈ2C complex, which are capable of replicating factors. Because genetic factors are themselves the badly damaged sequences. In the process of repair, subject of adaptive evolution, this discovery has brought these alternative polymerases generate mutations at a into question the random nature of mutagenesis.
    [Show full text]
  • Body Depth and Pectoral Fin Ecomorphology Coevolve in Lake Malawi Cichlid Fishes
    Erschienen in: Ecology and Evolution ; 8 (2018), 23. - S. 11945-11953 Received: 1 July 2018 | Revised: 22 September 2018 | Accepted: 1 October 2018 https://dx.doi.org/10.1002/ece3.4651 DOI: 10.1002/ece3.4651 ORIGINAL RESEARCH Dissecting a potential spandrel of adaptive radiation: Body depth and pectoral fin ecomorphology coevolve in Lake Malawi cichlid fishes Christopher D. Hulsey1 | Roi Holzman2 | Axel Meyer1 1Department of Biology, University of Konstanz, Konstanz, Germany Abstract 2School of Zoology, Faculty of Life The evolution of body shape reflects both the ecological factors structuring organis‐ science, Tel Aviv University, Tel Aviv, Israel mal diversity as well as an organism’s underlying anatomy. For instance, body depth and The Inter‐University Institute for Marine Sciences, Eilat, Israel in fishes is thought to determine their susceptibility to predators, attractiveness to mates, as well as swimming performance. However, the internal anatomy influencing Correspondence Christopher D. Hulsey, Department of diversification of body depth has not been extensively examined, and changes in Biology, University of Konstanz, Konstanz, body depth could arise as a by‐product of functional changes in other anatomical Germany. Email: darrin.hulsey@uni‐konstanz.de structures. Using an improved phylogenetic hypothesis for a diverse set of Lake Malawi cichlid fishes, we tested the evolutionary association between body depth Funding information National Science Foundation, Grant/Award and the height of the pectoral girdle. To refine the functional importance of the ob‐ Number: IOS‐0919459; United States–Israel served substantial correlation, we also tested the coevolution of pectoral girdle Bi‐National Science Foundation, Grant/ Award Number: 2011067 height and pectoral fin area.
    [Show full text]
  • Noise, Logic, and the Span of Time
    ings did he suggest that the function per- function by moderating, through a variety of REFERENCES formed by an exaptation needs to be biologi- themes, our evolutionarily functional fear of death. Thus, recognition of our own mortali- Buss, D. M., Haselton, M. G., Shackelford, T. cal. As Buss et al. reported, Gould (1991) K., Bleske, A. L., & Wakefield, J. C. (1998). offered two definitions of exaptation: "a fea- ty is a spandrel, and the practice of religion is Adaptations, exaptations, and spandrels. ture, now useful to an organism, that did not an exaptation. American Psychologist, 53, 533-548. arise as an adaptation for its present role, but Moreover, it is a priori unlikely that Gould, S. J. (1987). Freudian slip. Natural was subsequently coopted for its current func- such complex psychological phenomena can History, 96, 14-21. tion" (p. 43) and "features that now enhance meet the standards of evidence proposed by Gould, S. J. (1991). Exaptation: A crucial tool fitness, but were not built by natural selection Buss et al. (1998). Specifically, they suggest- for an evolutionary psychology. Journal of for their current role" (p. 47). Thus, although ed that evidence of special design for a hy- Social Issues, 47, 43-65. exaptations always provide a current func- Gould, S. J. (1997). The exaptive excellence pothesized function be demonstrated before of spandrels as a term and prototype. Pro- tion, that function need not be biological. In concluding that any structure or behavior is fact, Gould's (1991) thesis is geared toward ceedings of the National Academy of Sci- adaptive.
    [Show full text]
  • Patterns, Mechanisms and Genetics of Speciation in Reptiles and Amphibians
    G C A T T A C G G C A T genes Review Patterns, Mechanisms and Genetics of Speciation in Reptiles and Amphibians Katharina C. Wollenberg Valero 1,* , Jonathon C. Marshall 2, Elizabeth Bastiaans 3, Adalgisa Caccone 4, Arley Camargo 5 , Mariana Morando 6, Matthew L. Niemiller 7, Maciej Pabijan 8 , Michael A. Russello 9, Barry Sinervo 10, Fernanda P. Werneck 11 , 12, 13 14 Jack W. Sites Jr. y, John J. Wiens and Sebastian Steinfartz 1 Department of Biological and Marine Sciences, University of Hull, Cottingham Road, Hull HU6 7RX, UK 2 Department of Zoology, Weber State University, 1415 Edvalson Street, Dept. 2505, Ogden, UT 84401, USA 3 Department of Biology, State University of New York, College at Oneonta, Oneonta, NY 13820, USA 4 Department of Ecology and Evolutionary Biology, Yale University, New Haven, CT 06520, USA 5 Centro Universitario de Rivera, Universidad de la República, Ituzaingó 667, Rivera 40000, Uruguay 6 Instituto Patagónico para el Estudio de los Ecosistemas Continentales (IPEEC, CENPAT-CONICET) Bv. Brown 2915, Puerto Madryn U9120ACD, Argentina 7 Department of Biological Sciences, The University of Alabama in Huntsville, Huntsville, AL 35899, USA 8 Department of Comparative Anatomy, Institute of Zoology and Biomedical Research, Jagiellonian University, ul. Gronostajowa 9, 30-387 Kraków, Poland 9 Department of Biology, University of British Columbia, Okanagan Campus, 3247 University Way, Kelowna, BC V1V 1V7, Canada 10 Department of Ecology and Evolutionary Biology, University of California, Santa Cruz, Coastal Biology Building,
    [Show full text]