The Continuum Hypothesis, Part II W

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

The Continuum Hypothesis, Part II W fea-woodin.qxp 6/29/01 1:11 PM Page 681 The Continuum Hypothesis, Part II W. Hugh Woodin Introduction So the resolution of the theory of the structure In the first part of this article, I identified the cor- H(ω2), ∈ could well be a far more difficult rect axioms for the structure P(N), N, +, ·, ∈ , challenge than was the resolution of the theory of which is the standard structure for Second Order the structure H(ω1), ∈. Number Theory. The axioms, collectively “Projec- One example of the potential subtle aspects of tive Determinacy”, solve many of the otherwise un- the structure H(ω2), ∈ is given in the following solvable, classical problems of this structure. theorem from 1991, the conclusion of which is in Actually working from the axioms of set theory, essence a property of the structure H(ω2), ∈. ZFC, I identified a natural progression of structures Theorem (Woodin). Suppose that the axiom Mar- ∈ ∈ increasing in complexity: H(ω), , H(ω1), , tin’s Maximum holds. Then there exists a surjection and H(ω2), ∈, where for each cardinal κ, H(κ) ρ : R → ω2 such that {(x, y) | ρ(x) <ρ(y)} is a pro- denotes the set of all sets whose transitive closure jective set. has cardinality less than κ. The first of these struc- tures is logically equivalent to N, +, ·, the stan- As we saw in Part I, assuming the forcing axiom, dard structure for number theory; the second is Martin’s Maximum, CH holds projectively in that logically equivalent to the standard structure for if X ⊆ R is an uncountable projective set, then Second Order Number Theory; and the third struc- |X| = |R|. This is because Projective Determinacy ture is where the answer to the Continuum Hy- must hold. However, the preceding theorem shows pothesis, CH, lies. The main topic of Part I was the that assuming Martin’s Maximum, CH fails pro- structure H(ω1), ∈. jectively in that there exists a surjection Are there analogs of these axioms, say, some ρ : R → ω2 generalization of Projective Determinacy, for the such that {(x, y) | ρ(x) <ρ(y)} is a projective set. structure H(ω2), ∈? Any reasonable generaliza- tion should settle the Continuum Hypothesis. Such a function ρ is naturally viewed as a “pro- An immediate consequence of Cohen’s method jective counterexample” to CH, for it is a coun- of forcing is that large cardinal axioms are not terexample to the following reformulation of CH: R → R terribly useful in providing such a generalization. Suppose that π : α is a surjection of onto Indeed it was realized fairly soon after the dis- the ordinal α; then α<ω2. covery of forcing that essentially no large cardinal There is a curious asymmetry which follows hypothesis can settle the Continuum Hypothesis. from (the proofs of) these results. Assume there This was noted independently by Cohen and by exist infinitely many Woodin cardinals. Then: Levy-Solovay. Claim (1) There can be no projective “proof” of CH (there can be no projec- W. Hugh Woodin is professor of mathematics at the Uni- tive well-ordering of R of length ω1). versity of California, Berkeley. His e-mail address is [email protected]. Part I of this article appeared in the June/July 2001, Claim (2) There can be a projective issue, pp. 567-576. “proof” of ¬CH (there can be, in The research reported was supported in part by NSF the sense just defined, a projective grant number 9322442. counterexample to CH). AUGUST 2001 NOTICES OF THE AMS 681 fea-woodin.qxp 6/29/01 1:11 PM Page 682 Therefore, if there exist infinitely many Woodin car- Can the theory of the structure dinals and if the Continuum Hypothesis is to be H(ω2), ∈ be finitely axiomatized decided on the basis of “simple” evidence (i.e., (over ZFC) in a (reasonable) logic which projective evidence), then the Continuum Hy- extends first order logic? pothesis must be false. This is the point of the first The logics arising naturally in this analysis sat- claim. But is this an argument against CH? If so, the isfy two important conditions, Generic Soundness playful adversary might suggest that a similar line and Generic Invariance. As a consequence, any ax- ∈ of argument indicates that ZFC is inconsistent, for ioms we find will yield theories for H(ω2), , while we can have a finite proof that ZFC is in- whose “completeness” is immune to attack by ap- consistent, we, by Gödel’s Second Incompleteness plications of Cohen’s method of forcing, just as is Theorem, cannot have a finite proof that ZFC is con- the case for number theory. sistent (unless ZFC is inconsistent). There is a key How shall we define the relevant strong logics? difference here, though, which is the point of the There is a natural strategy motivated by the Gödel second claim. If there is more than one Woodin car- Completeness Theorem. If φ is a sentence in the L ∈ dinal, then a projective “proof” that CH is false can language (ˆ=, ˆ) for set theory, then “ZFC φ” in- always be created by passing to a Cohen extension. dicates that there is a formal proof of φ from ZFC. More precisely, if M,E is a model of ZFC to- This is an arithmetic statement. gether with the statement “There exist 2 Woodin The Gödel Completeness Theorem shows that cardinals”, that is, if if φ is a sentence, then ZFC φ if and only if M,E φ for every structure M,E such that M,E ZFC+“There exist 2 Woodin cardinals,” M,E ZFC. ∗ ∗ then there is a Cohen extension, M ,E , of Therefore a strong logic 0 can naturally be M,E such that M∗,E∗ ZFC + φ, where φ is defined by first specifying a collection of test struc- the sentence which asserts that there exists a sur- tures—these are structures of the form M = M,E, where E ⊂ M × M—and then defining “ZFC φ” jection ρ : R → ω2 such that {(x, y) | ρ(x) <ρ(y)} 0 is a projective set. This theorem, which is the the- if for every test structure M, if M ZFC, then orem behind the second claim above, shows that M φ. what might be called the Effective Continuum Hy- Of course, we shall only be interested in the case pothesis is as intractable as the Continuum Hy- that there actually exists a test structure M such pothesis itself. that M ZFC. In other words, we require that ZFC These claims are weak evidence that CH is false, be consistent in our logic. so perhaps large cardinal axioms are not quite so The smaller the collection of test structures, useless for resolving CH after all. the stronger the logic, i.e., the larger the set of sen- Of course there is no a priori reason that CH tences φ which are proved by ZFC. Note that if should be decided solely on the basis of projective there were only one test structure, then for each evidence. Nevertheless, in the 1970s Martin con- sentence φ either ZFC 0 φ or ZFC 0 ¬φ. So in jectured that the existence of projective evidence the logic 0 defined by this collection of test against CH will eventually be seen to follow from structures, no propositions are independent of reasonable axioms. the axioms ZFC. By the Gödel Completeness Theorem, first order Axioms for H(ω2) logic is the weakest (nontrivial) logic. Encouraged by the success in Part I in finding the To formulate the notion of Generic Soundness, correct axioms for H(ω1), and refusing to be dis- I first define the cumulative hierarchy of sets: couraged by the observation that large cardinal ax- this is a class of sets indexed by the ordinals. The ioms cannot settle CH, we turn our attention to set with index α is denoted Vα, and the definition H(ω2). Here we have a problem if we regard large is by induction on α as follows: V0 = ∅ ; cardinal axioms as our sole source of inspiration: Vα+1 = P(Vα) ; and if β is a limit ordinal, then Even if there is an analog of Projective Determinacy Vβ = ∪{Vα | α<β}. It is easily verified that the for H(ω2), how can we find it or even recognize it sets Vα are increasing, and it is a consequence of if we do find it? the axioms that every set is a member of Vα for My point is simply that the axiom(s) we seek can- large enough α. not possibly be implied by any (consistent) large It follows from the definitions that Vω = H(ω) cardinal hypothesis remotely related to those cur- and that Vω+1 ⊆ H(ω1). However, Vω+1 = H(ω1). rently accepted as large cardinal hypotheses. Nevertheless, Vω+1 and H(ω1) are logically equiv- Strong Logics alent in that each can be analyzed within the other. The solution is to take an abstract approach. This The relationship between Vω+2 and H(ω2) is far we shall do by considering strengthenings of first more subtle. If the Continuum Hypothesis holds, order logic and analyzing the following question, then these structures are logically equivalent, but which I shall make precise. the assertion that these structures are logically 682 NOTICES OF THE AMS VOLUME 48, NUMBER 7 fea-woodin.qxp 6/29/01 1:11 PM Page 683 equivalent does not imply the Continuum Hy- Definition. For a given strong logic 0, the theory pothesis. of the structure H(ω2), ∈ is “finitely axiomatized Suppose that M is a transitive set such that over ZFC” if there exists a sentence Ψ such that for M,∈ ZFC.
Recommended publications
  • Set Theory, by Thomas Jech, Academic Press, New York, 1978, Xii + 621 Pp., '$53.00
    BOOK REVIEWS 775 BULLETIN (New Series) OF THE AMERICAN MATHEMATICAL SOCIETY Volume 3, Number 1, July 1980 © 1980 American Mathematical Society 0002-9904/80/0000-0 319/$01.75 Set theory, by Thomas Jech, Academic Press, New York, 1978, xii + 621 pp., '$53.00. "General set theory is pretty trivial stuff really" (Halmos; see [H, p. vi]). At least, with the hindsight afforded by Cantor, Zermelo, and others, it is pretty trivial to do the following. First, write down a list of axioms about sets and membership, enunciating some "obviously true" set-theoretic principles; the most popular Hst today is called ZFC (the Zermelo-Fraenkel axioms with the axiom of Choice). Next, explain how, from ZFC, one may derive all of conventional mathematics, including the general theory of transfinite cardi­ nals and ordinals. This "trivial" part of set theory is well covered in standard texts, such as [E] or [H]. Jech's book is an introduction to the "nontrivial" part. Now, nontrivial set theory may be roughly divided into two general areas. The first area, classical set theory, is a direct outgrowth of Cantor's work. Cantor set down the basic properties of cardinal numbers. In particular, he showed that if K is a cardinal number, then 2", or exp(/c), is a cardinal strictly larger than K (if A is a set of size K, 2* is the cardinality of the family of all subsets of A). Now starting with a cardinal K, we may form larger cardinals exp(ic), exp2(ic) = exp(exp(fc)), exp3(ic) = exp(exp2(ic)), and in fact this may be continued through the transfinite to form expa(»c) for every ordinal number a.
    [Show full text]
  • Calibrating Determinacy Strength in Levels of the Borel Hierarchy
    CALIBRATING DETERMINACY STRENGTH IN LEVELS OF THE BOREL HIERARCHY SHERWOOD J. HACHTMAN Abstract. We analyze the set-theoretic strength of determinacy for levels of the Borel 0 hierarchy of the form Σ1+α+3, for α < !1. Well-known results of H. Friedman and D.A. Martin have shown this determinacy to require α+1 iterations of the Power Set Axiom, but we ask what additional ambient set theory is strictly necessary. To this end, we isolate a family of Π1-reflection principles, Π1-RAPα, whose consistency strength corresponds 0 CK exactly to that of Σ1+α+3-Determinacy, for α < !1 . This yields a characterization of the levels of L by or at which winning strategies in these games must be constructed. When α = 0, we have the following concise result: the least θ so that all winning strategies 0 in Σ4 games belong to Lθ+1 is the least so that Lθ j= \P(!) exists + all wellfounded trees are ranked". x1. Introduction. Given a set A ⊆ !! of sequences of natural numbers, consider a game, G(A), where two players, I and II, take turns picking elements of a sequence hx0; x1; x2;::: i of naturals. Player I wins the game if the sequence obtained belongs to A; otherwise, II wins. For a collection Γ of subsets of !!, Γ determinacy, which we abbreviate Γ-DET, is the statement that for every A 2 Γ, one of the players has a winning strategy in G(A). It is a much-studied phenomenon that Γ -DET has mathematical strength: the bigger the pointclass Γ, the stronger the theory required to prove Γ -DET.
    [Show full text]
  • Set-Theoretic Geology, the Ultimate Inner Model, and New Axioms
    Set-theoretic Geology, the Ultimate Inner Model, and New Axioms Justin William Henry Cavitt (860) 949-5686 [email protected] Advisor: W. Hugh Woodin Harvard University March 20, 2017 Submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Bachelor of Arts in Mathematics and Philosophy Contents 1 Introduction 2 1.1 Author’s Note . .4 1.2 Acknowledgements . .4 2 The Independence Problem 5 2.1 Gödelian Independence and Consistency Strength . .5 2.2 Forcing and Natural Independence . .7 2.2.1 Basics of Forcing . .8 2.2.2 Forcing Facts . 11 2.2.3 The Space of All Forcing Extensions: The Generic Multiverse 15 2.3 Recap . 16 3 Approaches to New Axioms 17 3.1 Large Cardinals . 17 3.2 Inner Model Theory . 25 3.2.1 Basic Facts . 26 3.2.2 The Constructible Universe . 30 3.2.3 Other Inner Models . 35 3.2.4 Relative Constructibility . 38 3.3 Recap . 39 4 Ultimate L 40 4.1 The Axiom V = Ultimate L ..................... 41 4.2 Central Features of Ultimate L .................... 42 4.3 Further Philosophical Considerations . 47 4.4 Recap . 51 1 5 Set-theoretic Geology 52 5.1 Preliminaries . 52 5.2 The Downward Directed Grounds Hypothesis . 54 5.2.1 Bukovský’s Theorem . 54 5.2.2 The Main Argument . 61 5.3 Main Results . 65 5.4 Recap . 74 6 Conclusion 74 7 Appendix 75 7.1 Notation . 75 7.2 The ZFC Axioms . 76 7.3 The Ordinals . 77 7.4 The Universe of Sets . 77 7.5 Transitive Models and Absoluteness .
    [Show full text]
  • Mice with Finitely Many Woodin Cardinals from Optimal Determinacy Hypotheses
    MICE WITH FINITELY MANY WOODIN CARDINALS FROM OPTIMAL DETERMINACY HYPOTHESES SANDRA MULLER,¨ RALF SCHINDLER, AND W. HUGH WOODIN Abstract We prove the following result which is due to the third author. 1 1 Let n ≥ 1. If Πn determinacy and Πn+1 determinacy both hold true and 1 # there is no Σn+2-definable !1-sequence of pairwise distinct reals, then Mn 1 exists and is !1-iterable. The proof yields that Πn+1 determinacy implies # that Mn (x) exists and is !1-iterable for all reals x. A consequence is the Determinacy Transfer Theorem for arbitrary n ≥ 1, 1 (n) 2 1 namely the statement that Πn+1 determinacy implies a (< ! − Π1) de- terminacy. Contents Abstract 1 Preface 2 Overview 4 1. Introduction 6 1.1. Games and Determinacy 6 1.2. Inner Model Theory 7 1.3. Mice with Finitely Many Woodin Cardinals 9 1.4. Mice and Determinacy 14 2. A Model with Woodin Cardinals from Determinacy Hypotheses 15 2.1. Introduction 15 2.2. Preliminaries 16 2.3. OD-Determinacy for an Initial Segment of Mn−1 32 2.4. Applications 40 2.5. A Proper Class Inner Model with n Woodin Cardinals 44 3. Proving Iterability 49 First author formerly known as Sandra Uhlenbrock. The first author gratefully ac- knowledges her non-material and financial support from the \Deutsche Telekom Stiftung". The material in this paper is part of the first author's Ph.D. thesis written under the su- pervision of the second author. 1 2 SANDRA MULLER,¨ RALF SCHINDLER, AND W. HUGH WOODIN 3.1.
    [Show full text]
  • Arxiv:1901.02074V1 [Math.LO] 4 Jan 2019 a Xoskona Lrecrias Ih Eal Ogv Entv a Definitive a Give T to of Able Basis Be the Might Cardinals” [17]
    GENERIC LARGE CARDINALS AS AXIOMS MONROE ESKEW Abstract. We argue against Foreman’s proposal to settle the continuum hy- pothesis and other classical independent questions via the adoption of generic large cardinal axioms. Shortly after proving that the set of all real numbers has a strictly larger car- dinality than the set of integers, Cantor conjectured his Continuum Hypothesis (CH): that there is no set of a size strictly in between that of the integers and the real numbers [1]. A resolution of CH was the first problem on Hilbert’s famous list presented in 1900 [19]. G¨odel made a major advance by constructing a model of the Zermelo-Frankel (ZF) axioms for set theory in which the Axiom of Choice and CH both hold, starting from a model of ZF. This showed that the axiom system ZF, if consistent on its own, could not disprove Choice, and that ZF with Choice (ZFC), a system which suffices to formalize the methods of ordinary mathematics, could not disprove CH [16]. It remained unknown at the time whether models of ZFC could be found in which CH was false, but G¨odel began to suspect that this was possible, and hence that CH could not be settled on the basis of the normal methods of mathematics. G¨odel remained hopeful, however, that new mathemati- cal axioms known as “large cardinals” might be able to give a definitive answer on CH [17]. The independence of CH from ZFC was finally solved by Cohen’s invention of the method of forcing [2]. Cohen’s method showed that ZFC could not prove CH either, and in fact could not put any kind of bound on the possible number of cardinals between the sizes of the integers and the reals.
    [Show full text]
  • Are Large Cardinal Axioms Restrictive?
    Are Large Cardinal Axioms Restrictive? Neil Barton∗ 24 June 2020y Abstract The independence phenomenon in set theory, while perva- sive, can be partially addressed through the use of large cardinal axioms. A commonly assumed idea is that large cardinal axioms are species of maximality principles. In this paper, I argue that whether or not large cardinal axioms count as maximality prin- ciples depends on prior commitments concerning the richness of the subset forming operation. In particular I argue that there is a conception of maximality through absoluteness, on which large cardinal axioms are restrictive. I argue, however, that large cardi- nals are still important axioms of set theory and can play many of their usual foundational roles. Introduction Large cardinal axioms are widely viewed as some of the best candi- dates for new axioms of set theory. They are (apparently) linearly ordered by consistency strength, have substantial mathematical con- sequences for questions independent from ZFC (such as consistency statements and Projective Determinacy1), and appear natural to the ∗Fachbereich Philosophie, University of Konstanz. E-mail: neil.barton@uni- konstanz.de. yI would like to thank David Aspero,´ David Fernandez-Bret´ on,´ Monroe Eskew, Sy-David Friedman, Victoria Gitman, Luca Incurvati, Michael Potter, Chris Scam- bler, Giorgio Venturi, Matteo Viale, Kameryn Williams and audiences in Cambridge, New York, Konstanz, and Sao˜ Paulo for helpful discussion. Two anonymous ref- erees also provided helpful comments, and I am grateful for their input. I am also very grateful for the generous support of the FWF (Austrian Science Fund) through Project P 28420 (The Hyperuniverse Programme) and the VolkswagenStiftung through the project Forcing: Conceptual Change in the Foundations of Mathematics.
    [Show full text]
  • Equivalents to the Axiom of Choice and Their Uses A
    EQUIVALENTS TO THE AXIOM OF CHOICE AND THEIR USES A Thesis Presented to The Faculty of the Department of Mathematics California State University, Los Angeles In Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree Master of Science in Mathematics By James Szufu Yang c 2015 James Szufu Yang ALL RIGHTS RESERVED ii The thesis of James Szufu Yang is approved. Mike Krebs, Ph.D. Kristin Webster, Ph.D. Michael Hoffman, Ph.D., Committee Chair Grant Fraser, Ph.D., Department Chair California State University, Los Angeles June 2015 iii ABSTRACT Equivalents to the Axiom of Choice and Their Uses By James Szufu Yang In set theory, the Axiom of Choice (AC) was formulated in 1904 by Ernst Zermelo. It is an addition to the older Zermelo-Fraenkel (ZF) set theory. We call it Zermelo-Fraenkel set theory with the Axiom of Choice and abbreviate it as ZFC. This paper starts with an introduction to the foundations of ZFC set the- ory, which includes the Zermelo-Fraenkel axioms, partially ordered sets (posets), the Cartesian product, the Axiom of Choice, and their related proofs. It then intro- duces several equivalent forms of the Axiom of Choice and proves that they are all equivalent. In the end, equivalents to the Axiom of Choice are used to prove a few fundamental theorems in set theory, linear analysis, and abstract algebra. This paper is concluded by a brief review of the work in it, followed by a few points of interest for further study in mathematics and/or set theory. iv ACKNOWLEDGMENTS Between the two department requirements to complete a master's degree in mathematics − the comprehensive exams and a thesis, I really wanted to experience doing a research and writing a serious academic paper.
    [Show full text]
  • MAGIC Set Theory Lecture 6
    MAGIC Set theory lecture 6 David Aspero´ University of East Anglia 15 November 2018 Recall: We defined (V : ↵ Ord) by recursion on Ord: ↵ 2 V = • 0 ; V = (V ) • ↵+1 P ↵ V = V : β<δ if δ is a limit ordinal. • δ { β } S (V : ↵ Ord) is called the cumulative hierarchy. ↵ 2 We saw: Proposition V↵ is transitive for every ordinal ↵. Proposition For all ↵<β, V V . ↵ ✓ β Definition For every x V , let rank(x) be the first ↵ such that 2 ↵ Ord ↵ x V . 2 2 ↵+1 S Definition For every set x, the transitive closure of x, denoted by TC(x), is X : n <! where { n } X = x S • 0 X = X • n+1 n So TC(x)=Sx x x x ... [ [ [ [ S SS SSS [Exercise: TC(x) is the –least transitive set y such that x y. ✓ ✓ In other words, TC(x)= y : y transitive, x y .] { ✓ } T Definition V denotes the class of all sets; that is, V = x : x = x . { } Definition WF = V : ↵ Ord : The class of all x such that x V for { ↵ 2 } 2 ↵ some ordinal ↵. S Note: WF is a transitive class: y x V implies y V since 2 2 ↵ 2 ↵ V↵ is transitive. Proposition If x WF, then there is some ↵ Ord such that x V . ✓ 2 ✓ ↵ Proof. Define the function F(y)=min γ y V . By the assumption { | 2 γ} on x, F is a well-defined function there. By Replacement γ y x : γ = F(y) is a set, and by Union it has a { |9 2 } supremum ↵.
    [Show full text]
  • Determinacy and Large Cardinals
    Determinacy and Large Cardinals Itay Neeman∗ Abstract. The principle of determinacy has been crucial to the study of definable sets of real numbers. This paper surveys some of the uses of determinacy, concentrating specifically on the connection between determinacy and large cardinals, and takes this connection further, to the level of games of length ω1. Mathematics Subject Classification (2000). 03E55; 03E60; 03E45; 03E15. Keywords. Determinacy, iteration trees, large cardinals, long games, Woodin cardinals. 1. Determinacy Let ωω denote the set of infinite sequences of natural numbers. For A ⊂ ωω let Gω(A) denote the length ω game with payoff A. The format of Gω(A) is displayed in Diagram 1. Two players, denoted I and II, alternate playing natural numbers forming together a sequence x = hx(n) | n < ωi in ωω called a run of the game. The run is won by player I if x ∈ A, and otherwise the run is won by player II. I x(0) x(2) ...... II x(1) x(3) ...... Diagram 1. The game Gω(A). A game is determined if one of the players has a winning strategy. The set A is ω determined if Gω(A) is determined. For Γ ⊂ P(ω ), det(Γ) denotes the statement that all sets in Γ are determined. Using the axiom of choice, or more specifically using a wellordering of the reals, it is easy to construct a non-determined set A. det(P(ωω)) is therefore false. On the other hand it has become clear through research over the years that det(Γ) is true if all the sets in Γ are definable by some concrete means.
    [Show full text]
  • Omega-Models of Finite Set Theory
    ω-MODELS OF FINITE SET THEORY ALI ENAYAT, JAMES H. SCHMERL, AND ALBERT VISSER Abstract. Finite set theory, here denoted ZFfin, is the theory ob- tained by replacing the axiom of infinity by its negation in the usual axiomatization of ZF (Zermelo-Fraenkel set theory). An ω-model of ZFfin is a model in which every set has at most finitely many elements (as viewed externally). Mancini and Zambella (2001) em- ployed the Bernays-Rieger method of permutations to construct a recursive ω-model of ZFfin that is nonstandard (i.e., not isomor- phic to the hereditarily finite sets Vω). In this paper we initiate the metamathematical investigation of ω-models of ZFfin. In par- ticular, we present a new method for building ω-models of ZFfin that leads to a perspicuous construction of recursive nonstandard ω-models of ZFfin without the use of permutations. Furthermore, we show that every recursive model of ZFfin is an ω-model. The central theorem of the paper is the following: Theorem A. For every graph (A, F ), where F is a set of un- ordered pairs of A, there is an ω-model M of ZFfin whose universe contains A and which satisfies the following conditions: (1) (A, F ) is definable in M; (2) Every element of M is definable in (M, a)a∈A; (3) If (A, F ) is pointwise definable, then so is M; (4) Aut(M) =∼ Aut(A, F ). Theorem A enables us to build a variety of ω-models with special features, in particular: Corollary 1. Every group can be realized as the automorphism group of an ω-model of ZFfin.
    [Show full text]
  • Unsolvable Problems, the Continuum Hypothesis, and the Nature of Infinity
    Unsolvable problems, the Continuum Hypothesis, and the nature of infinity W. Hugh Woodin Harvard University January 9, 2017 V : The Universe of Sets The power set Suppose X is a set. The powerset of X is the set P(X ) = fY Y is a subset of X g: Cumulative Hierarchy of Sets The universe V of sets is generated by defining Vα by induction on the ordinal α: 1. V0 = ;, 2. Vα+1 = P(Vα), S 3. if α is a limit ordinal then Vα = β<α Vβ. I If X is a set then X 2 Vα for some ordinal α. I V0 = ;, V1 = f;g, V2 = f;; f;gg. I These are just the ordinals: 0, 1, and 2. I V3 has 4 elements. I This is not the ordinal 3 (in fact, it is not an ordinal). I V4 has 16 elements. I V5 has 65; 536 elements. I V1000 has a lot of elements. V! is infinite, it is the set of all (hereditarily) finite sets. The conception of V! is mathematically identical to the conception of the structure (N; +; ·). Beyond the basic axioms: large cardinal axioms The axioms I The ZFC axioms of Set Theory specify the basic axioms for V . I These axioms are naturally augmented by additional principles which assert the existence of \very large" infinite sets. I These additional principles are called large cardinal axioms. I There is a proper class of measurable cardinals. I There is a proper class of strong cardinals. I There is a proper class of Woodin cardinals.
    [Show full text]
  • Forcing? Thomas Jech
    WHAT IS... ? Forcing? Thomas Jech What is forcing? Forcing is a remarkably powerful case that there exists no proof of the conjecture technique for the construction of models of set and no proof of its negation. theory. It was invented in 1963 by Paul Cohen1, To make this vague discussion more precise we who used it to prove the independence of the will first elaborate on the concepts of theorem and Continuum Hypothesis. He constructed a model proof. of set theory in which the Continuum Hypothesis What are theorems and proofs? It is a use- (CH) fails, thus showing that CH is not provable ful fact that every mathematical statement can from the axioms of set theory. be expressed in the language of set theory. All What is the Continuum Hypothesis? In 1873 mathematical objects can be regarded as sets, and Georg Cantor proved that the continuum is un- relations between them can be reduced to expres- countable: that there exists no mapping of the set sions that use only the relation ∈. It is not essential N of all integers onto the set R of all real numbers. how it is done, but it can be done: For instance, Since R contains N, we have 2ℵ0 > ℵ , where 2ℵ0 0 integers are certain finite sets, rational numbers and ℵ are the cardinalities of R and N, respec- 0 are pairs of integers, real numbers are identified tively. A question arises whether 2ℵ0 is equal to with Dedekind cuts in the rationals, functions the cardinal ℵ1, the immediate successor of ℵ0.
    [Show full text]