Our Idea of God

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Our Idea of God Our Idea of God An Introduction to Philosophical Theology Thomas V. Morris Our Idea of God "Morris's book displays all the signs of excellence we have come to expect from him-philosophical adroitness, fairness in stating opposing positions, and the sort offresh, almost breezy, prose sryle that makes him a friend to students." CORNELIUS PLANTINGA, JR. Calvin Theological Seminary What can we know about God? What is the range of God's power? How is God related to time? These are a few of the central issues that philosophical theology addresses. Introducing the discipiine by discussing the problem of method, Thomas V. Morris goes on to examine God's goodness, power and knowledge. After a careful look at God's relation to time, eternity and creation, Morris concludes with a discussion of the doctrines of the Incarnation and Trinity. Morris (Ph.D., Yale) is associate professor of philosophy at the University of Notre Dame and the general editor of The Library of Religious Philosophy. He is the author of The Logic of God Incarnate, Philosophy ofReligion and Philosophy and the Christian Faith. "Original and refreshing in bringing together in relatively brief format some of the best of contemporary philosophical theology." CHARLES TALIAFERRO St. Olaf College "An excellent introduction to the problems associated with our conception of the divine attributes .... Lucid and fair." WILLIAM J. WAINWRIGHT University of Wisconsin-Milwaulue ISBN 0-87784-346-5 9 Contours of Christian Philosophy c. STEPHEN EVANS Series Editor Our Idea of God An Introduction to Philosophical Theology Thomas V. Morris INfERVARSI1Y PREss DOWNERS GROVE, IlliNOIS 60515 e 1991 by Thomas V. Moms All rights reserved. No pan oftms book may be reproduad in any form without written pmnission from InterVarsity Press, P.o. Box 1400, Duwners Grove, Illinois 60515. InterVarsity Press is the book-publi.rhing division ofInterVarsity Christian Fellowship, a student movement actin on campus at hundreds ofuniPCrsities, CIIlleges and schools ofnursing in the United States ofAmerica, and a member mwement of the In_tional Felluwship of Evangelical Students. For information about IoaU and regional activities, write Public &/ations Dept., InterVarsity Christian Fe/Juwship, 6400 Schroeder RJt., P.o. Box 7895, Madison, WI 53707-7895. ISBN 0-87784-346-5 Printed in the United States ofAmerica § Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Moms, Thomas V. Our idea of God: an inlTOduction to philosophical theology/ Thomas V Moms. p. cm.-(Contours of Christian philosophy) Includes bibliographical references. ISBN 0-87784-346-5 1. Philosophical theology. 2. God-Attributes. I. Title. II. Series. BT40.M694 1991 231:044-dc20 90-19145 CIP 15 14 13 12 11 10 9 8 7 6 5 4 3 2 03 02 01 00 99 98 97 96 95 94 93 92 91 To Paul and Marcia Bennett, whose friendship) encouragement and generosity have enriched this lift in many ways, for me and for my family. Introduction 11 1. The Project of Philosophical Theology 15 The Possibility of Theology 16 Our Grounds for Proceeding 23 2. The Concept of God 27 The Problem of Method 28 Peifect Being Theology 35 Questions and Refinements: The Ultimate Method 40 3. God's Goodness 47 Perspectives on God's Goodness 48 The Necessity of God's Goodness 51 The Problems of Praiseworthiness and Moral Freedom 56 4. The Power of God 65 The Magnitude ofDivine Power 66 Problems for Divine Power 73 5. God's Knowledge 83 The Nature of God's Knowledge 83 God's Knowledge and the Future: The Problem 86 Reactions to the Problem 92 Certainty and Uncertainty about God's Knowledge 102 6. The Being of God 105 Necessity: The Exalted Modality 106 Divine Simplicity 113 7. God's Eternity 119 The Atemporally Eternal and the Temporally Everlasting 120 Atemporalist Ar.guments 121 Temporalist Ar.guments 130 8. The Creation 139 The Nature of Creation 141 Creaturely Dependence 154 9. God Incarnate and Triune 159 The Doctrine of the Incarnation 159 Two Pictures of God Incarnate 166 The Doctrine of the Trinity 174 Notes 185 Books for Further Reading 191 General Preface The Contours of Christian Philosophy series will consist of short introductory­ level textbooks in the various fields of philosophy. These books will introduce readers to major problems and alternative ways ofdealing with those problems_ These books, however, will differ from most in that they will evaluate alternative viewpoints not only with regard to their general strength, but also with regard to their value in the construction of a Christian world and life view_ Thus, the books will explore the implications of the various views for Christian theology as well as the implications that Christian convictions might have for the philosophical issues discussed. It is crucial that Christians attain a greater degree of philosophical awareness in order to improve the quality of general scholarship and evangelical theology. My hope is that this series will contribute to that end. Although the books are intended as examples of Christian scholarship, it is hoped that they will be of value to others as well; these issues should concern all thoughtful persons. The assumption which underlies this hope is that complete neutrality in philosophy is neither possible nor desirable. Philosophi­ cal work always reflects a person's deepest commitments. Such commitments, however, do not preclude a genuine striving for critical honesty. C. Stephen Evans Series Editor Introduction Many people, even within the ranks of devout religious believers, have only the haziest conception of God. When this is brought to their attention, a significant number of such people admit that this vagueness about God bothers them deeply, but they often add that they don't have a clue as to how to go about getting clearer on this most important idea. It is one aim of the present book to assist in dealing with this problem. I attempt to provide an example of how some simple, straightforward philosophical methods of thinking can shed light on theological matters which might otherwise remain obscure. It is my hope that this little book will help to stimulate its readers to think more deeply about matters of religious conviction. This book is also meant to serve as an elementary introduction to philosophical theology. The philosophical issues which can arise concerning so exalted a subject matter as the concept of God can become very complex, and recent treatments of these issues by philosophers have been as technical and demanding as pioneering work in any other field of serious human intellectual inquiry. I have sought to keep my discussions of these issues as streamlined, and as accessible to non-philosophers, as possible. The topic is too important to be reserved for specialists only. In every chapter, I have tried to focus on the most basic issues and to keep complications to a minimum. There are many more technical treatises available for those readers who want to pursue these topics further. My aim is to provide a place to begin. 12 OUR IDEA OF GOD In these pages, I attempt to focus on some purely conceptual issues. My center of attention is how we think about, or conceive of, God. Hence, the book's title. In another book, I shall be concentrating on questions concerning the rationality of religious belief, the nature of faith, and the cogency of arguments for the existence of God. Those topics are not at the center of my attention here, but the issues which are treated in the present book will be found to hook up with those other topics in numerous and interesting ways. Clarifying our idea of God will put us into a position to make more progress on at least some of these other philosophically important questions. I want to thank all these friends and colleagues who suggested, and even sometimes insisted over a period of years, that I write such a book. I hope that they are at least to some degree satisfied with the result. I also want to thank all my colleagues who urged that, before beginning the project, I should upgrade my word·processing capability. Everything I have written earlier has been put to paper with a cheap ball-point pen. I decided to take this good advice, and I am happy to acknowledge that the writing of this manuscript was a much more pleasant experience because of my new Pelikan 800 fountain pen, which I enjoyed using throughout. Sherry Reichold, Nancy Kegler, and Cheryl. Reed did an excellent job of putting it into a real word processor. Their efforts and results are appreciated I also thank everyone who read an earlier version of this book and provided helpful comments. Some parts of the book were scrutinized in the weekly discussion group sponsored by Notre Dame's Center for the Philosophy of Religion. I thank my colleagues in that group for their many pieces of helpful advice. I also want to acknowledge the stimulus provided by written comments sent to me by Stephen Evans, Charles Taliaferro, Jonathan Kvanvig, Jerry Walls and James Sadowski. Portions of chapter nine are drawn from "The Metaphysics of God Incarnate," which has appeared in the book Trinity, Incarnation and Atonement, edited by Ronald J. Feenstra and Cornelius Plantinga, Jr. (Notre Dame, Ind.: University of Notre Dame Press, 1989). I thank the editors and Notre Dame Press for the permission to make further use of some of this material. So many facets of our idea of God need to be re-thought again and again because of the inexhaustible resources of this ultimate concept. INTRODUCTION 13 Finally, I would like to thank the George A and Eliza Gardner Howard Foundation for their generous award of a Howard Foundation Fellowship, administered by Brown University, to cover the academic year 1989·90, during which time this project was completed and many others were begun.
Recommended publications
  • An Anselmian Approach to Divine Simplicity
    Faith and Philosophy: Journal of the Society of Christian Philosophers Volume 37 Issue 3 Article 3 7-1-2020 An Anselmian Approach to Divine Simplicity Katherin A. Rogers Follow this and additional works at: https://place.asburyseminary.edu/faithandphilosophy Recommended Citation Rogers, Katherin A. (2020) "An Anselmian Approach to Divine Simplicity," Faith and Philosophy: Journal of the Society of Christian Philosophers: Vol. 37 : Iss. 3 , Article 3. DOI: 10.37977/faithphil.2020.37.3.3 Available at: https://place.asburyseminary.edu/faithandphilosophy/vol37/iss3/3 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Journals at ePLACE: preserving, learning, and creative exchange. It has been accepted for inclusion in Faith and Philosophy: Journal of the Society of Christian Philosophers by an authorized editor of ePLACE: preserving, learning, and creative exchange. applyparastyle "fig//caption/p[1]" parastyle "FigCapt" applyparastyle "fig" parastyle "Figure" AQ1–AQ5 AN ANSELMIAN APPROACH TO DIVINE SIMPLICITY Katherin A. Rogers The doctrine of divine simplicity (DDS) is an important aspect of the clas- sical theism of philosophers like Augustine, Anselm, and Thomas Aquinas. Recently the doctrine has been defended in a Thomist mode using the intrin- sic/extrinsic distinction. I argue that this approach entails problems which can be avoided by taking Anselm’s more Neoplatonic line. This does involve AQ6 accepting some controversial claims: for example, that time is isotemporal and that God inevitably does the best. The most difficult problem involves trying to reconcile created libertarian free will with the Anselmian DDS. But for those attracted to DDS the Anselmian approach is worth considering.
    [Show full text]
  • The Principle of Plenitude and Natural Theology in Nineteenth-Century
    BJHS, 1986, 19, 263-282 The Principle of Plenitudeand NaturalTheology in Nineteenth-CenturyBritain RICHARD R. YEO- I In his classic study, The GreatChain of Being,Arthur Lovejoy delineated a complexset of concepts and assumptionswhich referredto the perfectionof God and the fullnessof creation. In attemptingto distil the basicor 'unitidea' which constitutedthis patternof thought, he focusedon the assumptionthat 'theuniverse is a plenumformarum in which the range of conceivablediversity of kinds of livingthings is exhaustivelyexemplified'. He called this the 'principleof plenitude'.Lovejoy argued that this idea impliedtwo others-continuity and gradation-and that togetherthese reflecteda pre-occupation with the 'necessity of imperfectionin all its possible degrees',a concernwhich had pervadedWestern thought since Plato and gave riseto the powerfulontology known as the 'greatchain of being'.' AlthoughLovejoy's approach to the historyof ideashas been criticized,2 this need not imply that the conceptshe discussedare no longerof interestto intellectualhistorians or historiansof science. Rather,it suggestsa need for historicalsensitivity to the different formulations of those ideas in specific contexts. William Bynum canvassed this alternative in an essay dealing with the possible fate of the chain of being in the nineteenthcentury, a periodwhich lay outsideLovejoy's survey. Lovejoy's pursuit of his theme and its manifoldpermutations ended in the lateeighteenth century, with the thesis that the chain of being acquireda temporaldimension and was thus transformedinto a chain of becoming.In makingthis point, Lovejoyrevealed the inherenttensions in the 1 A. O. Lovejoy, The Great Chain of Being. New York, 1960, p. 52,338. For a recent account which stresses the principle of plenitude as 'the very foundation of the Chain of Being', see L.
    [Show full text]
  • Proclus and Artemis: on the Relevance of Neoplatonism to the Modern Study of Ancient Religion
    Kernos Revue internationale et pluridisciplinaire de religion grecque antique 13 | 2000 Varia Proclus and Artemis: On the Relevance of Neoplatonism to the Modern Study of Ancient Religion Spyridon Rangos Electronic version URL: http://journals.openedition.org/kernos/1293 DOI: 10.4000/kernos.1293 ISSN: 2034-7871 Publisher Centre international d'étude de la religion grecque antique Printed version Date of publication: 1 January 2000 ISSN: 0776-3824 Electronic reference Spyridon Rangos, « Proclus and Artemis: On the Relevance of Neoplatonism to the Modern Study of Ancient Religion », Kernos [Online], 13 | 2000, Online since 21 April 2011, connection on 01 May 2019. URL : http://journals.openedition.org/kernos/1293 ; DOI : 10.4000/kernos.1293 Kernos Kernos, 13 (2000), p. 47-84. Proclus and Artemis: On the Relevance of Neoplatonism to the Modern Study of Andent Religion* Imagine the situation in which contemporary philosophers would find themselves if Wittgenstein introduced, in his Philosophical Investigations, the religious figure of Jesus as Logos and Son of God in order to illuminate the puzzlement ofthe private-language paradox, or if in the second division of Being and Time Heidegger mentioned the archangel Michael to support the argument of 'being toward death'. Similar is the perplexity that a modern reader is bound to encounter when, after a highly sophisticated analysis of demanding metaphysical questions about the relationship of the one and the many, finitude and infinity, mind and body, Proclus, l in ail seriousness and without the slightest touch of irony, assigns to some traditional gods of Greek polytheism a definitive place in the structure of being.
    [Show full text]
  • ¼ PHILOSOPHY of RELIGION.Pdf
    ACONCISE ENCYCLOPEDIA of the PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION other books in the same series A Concise Encyclopedia of Judaism, Dan Cohn-Serbok, ISBN 1–85168–176–0 A Concise Encyclopedia of Hinduism, Klaus K. Klostermaier, ISBN 1–85168–175–2 A Concise Encyclopedia of Christianity, Geoffrey Parrinder, ISBN 1–85168–174–4 A Concise Encyclopedia of Buddhism, John Powers, ISBN 1–85168–233–3 A Concise Encyclopedia of the Baha´’ı´ Faith, Peter Smith, ISBN 1–85168–184–1 A Concise Encyclopedia of Islam, Gordon D. Newby, ISBN 1–85168–295–3 related titles published by oneworld Ethics in the World Religions, Edited by Joseph Runzo and Nancy M. Martin, ISBN 1–85168–247–3 The Fifth Dimension, John Hick, ISBN 1–85168–191–4 Global Philosophy of Religion: A Short Introduction, Joseph Runzo, ISBN 1–85168–235–X God: A Guide for the Perplexed, Keith Ward, ISBN 1–85168–284–8 God, Faith and the New Millennium, Keith Ward, ISBN 1–85168–155–8 Love, Sex and Gender in the World Religions, Edited by Joseph Runzo and Nancy M. Martin, ISBN 1–85168–223–6 The Meaning of Life in the World Religions, Edited by Joseph Runzo and Nancy M. Martin, ISBN 1–85168–200–7 The Phenomenon of Religion, Moojan Momen, ISBN 1–85168–161–2 ACONCISE ENCYCLOPEDIA of the PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION ANTHONY C. THISELTON A CONCISE ENCYCLOPEDIA OF THE PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION Oneworld Publications (Sales and Editorial) 185 Banbury Road Oxford OX2 7AR England www.oneworld-publications.com # Anthony C. Thiselton 2002 All rights reserved. Copyright under Berne Convention A CIP record for this title is available from the British Library ISBN 1–85168–301–1 Cover design by Design Deluxe Typeset by LaserScript, Mitcham, UK Printed and bound in the United Kingdom by Bell & Bain Ltd, Glasgow NL08 Contents Preface and acknowledgements vi A Concise Encyclopedia of the Philosophy of Religion 1 Chronology 329 Index of names 337 Preface and acknowledgements Aims, scope and target readership he following selection of subject entries has been shaped in the light of Tmany years of feedback from my own students.
    [Show full text]
  • Some Antecedents of Leibniz's Principles
    Some Antecedents of Leibniz’s Principles by Martinho Antônio Bittencourt de Castro A thesis submitted in fulfilment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy School of History and Philosophy University of New South Wales Sydney, Australia April 2008 2 Declaration I hereby declare that this submission is my own work and to the best of my knowledge it contains no materials previously published or written by another person, or substantial proportions of material which have been accepted for the award of any other degree or diploma at UNSW or any other educational institution, except where due acknowledgement is made in the thesis. Any contribution made to the research by others, with whom I have worked at UNSW or elsewhere, is explicitly acknowledged in the thesis. I also declare that the intellectual content of this thesis is the product of my own work, except to the extent that assistance from others in the project's design and conception or in style, presentation and linguistic expression is acknowledged. Date: 12 June 2008 3 Abstract Leibniz considered that scepticism and confusion engendered by the disputes of different sects or schools of metaphysics were obstacles to the progress of knowledge in philosophy. His solution was to adopt an eclectic method with the aim of uncovering the truth hidden beneath the dispute of schools. Leibniz’s project was, having in mind the eclectic method, to synthesise a union between old pre-modern philosophy, based on formal and final causes, and new modern philosophy which gave preference to efficient causes. The result of his efforts is summarised in the Monadology.
    [Show full text]
  • Aristotle's Physics
    Aristotle’s Physics: The Metaphysics of Change, Matter, Motion and Time Philipp Blum, [email protected] Hauptseminar, autumn term Seminar admin Semester plan Topics: .. Introduction I: Aristotle’s concept of natural science, explanation and causation in relation to his metaphysics .. Introduction II: Aristotelian time + Aristotelian space = Aristotelian space-time? .. no meeting (St. Leodegar) .. Physics I, II.-: Beginnings and Causes .. Physics, II.-: Forms and natures .. Physics II.-: Chance, Necessity and Teleological Explanation .. Physics III: Motion and the Infinite .. Physics IV.-: Place and the Void .. Physics IV.-: Time .. Physics V+VI: Motions .. Physics VII: Movings .. Physics VIII: The First Motion and the First Mover .. The Aristotelian theory of relations and reciprocal powers .. Aristotelian process ontology and the ontological status of lesser entities Editions, introductions Editions: I find the bilingual German edition by Hans Günter Zekl in the Meiner Verlag (Aristoteles , ) very useful. In the Clarendon Aristotle Series, only five books have been edited: • Books I and II: Charlton (, ) • Books III and IV: Hussey (, ) • Book VIII: Graham () The greek text isavailable in the Loeb ClassicalLibrary: https://www.loebclassics.com/view/LCL228/ 1957/volume.xml, Thomas Aquinas’ commentary is here: http://dhspriory.org/thomas/Physics. htm. Among the entries on the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (generally a very good resource) I found useful are the following: • https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/aristotle/, by
    [Show full text]
  • Appealing to Simplicity Is Unfair
    J. Appl. Environ. Biol. Sci. , 5(8S )30-32 , 2015 ISSN: 2090-4274 Journal of Applied Environmental © 2015, TextRoad Publication and Biological Sciences www.textroad.com Appealing to Simplicity is Unfair Mohsen Sate Department of Theology, Isfahan (Khorasgan) Branch, Islamic Azad University, Isfahan, Iran Received: March 8, 2015 Accepted: May 10, 2015 ABSTRACT What might be meant by saying that one theory is more ‘simple’ than another? Is the simpler theory always better? This article attempts to answer these questions and then to show that none of the a priori and empiricist justifications of simplicity are sufficient. Thus appealing to simplicity in philosophy, and even in science, seems to be unfair. KEYWORDS : Simplicity, plenitude, a prior, empiricist. _________________________________________________________________________________________ 1. INTRODUCTION Most philosophers believe that the principle of simplicity is a theoretical virtue in science, as well as in philosophy. Sober says about this principle, “it has been described and defended as if it were a deletion rule, counseling agnosticism” (1981: 145). To explain simplicity, Ockham says that a hypothesis should not be asserted, or an entity postulated, if it is not needed to explain anything (1). In other words, other things being equal, the simpler theory is preferable. Discussion of the principle of simplicity and its various justifications will be the first subject of this paper. Secondly, to address that appealing to simplicity in philosophy is more controversial than in science, I will examine the value of different justifications of simplicity. The term simplicity can be interpreted in different ways. It seems to be used in various contexts and for different aims.
    [Show full text]
  • Essence, Existence, and Necessity: Spinoza's Modal Metaphysics
    University of Rhode Island DigitalCommons@URI Senior Honors Projects Honors Program at the University of Rhode Island 2012 Essence, Existence, and Necessity: Spinoza’s Modal Metaphysics Austen Haynes [email protected] Creative Commons License This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-Noncommercial-No Derivative Works 3.0 License. Follow this and additional works at: http://digitalcommons.uri.edu/srhonorsprog Part of the History of Philosophy Commons, and the Metaphysics Commons Recommended Citation Haynes, Austen, "Essence, Existence, and Necessity: Spinoza’s Modal Metaphysics" (2012). Senior Honors Projects. Paper 345. http://digitalcommons.uri.edu/srhonorsprog/345http://digitalcommons.uri.edu/srhonorsprog/345 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Honors Program at the University of Rhode Island at DigitalCommons@URI. It has been accepted for inclusion in Senior Honors Projects by an authorized administrator of DigitalCommons@URI. For more information, please contact [email protected]. 1 Essence, Existence, and Necessity: Spinozaʼs Modal Metaphysics “For with thee is the fountain of life: in thy light shall we see light.”1 Austen Haynes 1 Psalms 36:9. 2 Abstract “In thought, as in nature, there is no creation from absolute nothing.” I have taken on the daunting project of giving an account of Spinoza’s metaphysics, and laying out the reasoning behind his doctrines. In a letter written in December 1675, barely over a year before his death, Spinoza told Henry Oldenburg that the fatalistic necessity (which was disturbing readers of his philosophy) was in fact the “principal basis” of his Ethics. Since all of his metaphysical doctrines are entwined with this necessity, it is my task to piece this puzzle together.
    [Show full text]
  • Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz, the Humanist Agenda and the Scientific Method
    3237827: M.Sc. Dissertation Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz, the humanist agenda and the scientific method Kundan Misra A dissertation submitted in partial fulfilment of the requirements for the degree of Master of Science (Research), University of New South Wales School of Mathematics and Statistics Faculty of Science University of New South Wales Submitted August 2011 Changes completed September 2012 THE UNIVERSITY OF NEW SOUTH WALES Thesis/Dissertation Sheet Surname or Family name: Misra First name: Kundan Other name/s: n/a Abbreviation for degree as given in the University calendar: MSc School: Mathematics and Statistics Faculty: Science Title: Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz, the humanist agenda and the scientific method Abstract 350 words maximum: Modernity began in Leibniz’s lifetime, arguably, and due to the efforts of a group of philosopher-scientists of which Leibniz was one of the most significant active contributors. Leibniz invented machines and developed the calculus. He was a force for peace, and industrial and cultural development through his work as a diplomat and correspondence with leaders across Europe, and in Russia and China. With Leibniz, science became a means for improving human living conditions. For Leibniz, science must begin with the “God’s eye view” and begin with an understanding of how the Creator would have designed the universe. Accordingly, Leibniz advocated the a priori method of scientific discovery, including the use of intellectual constructions or artifices. He defended the usefulness and success of these methods against detractors. While cognizant of Baconian empiricism, Leibniz found that an unbalanced emphasis on experiment left the investigator short of conclusions on efficient causes.
    [Show full text]
  • Spinoza on the Spirit of Friendship by David Belcheff a Thesis Presented
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by ASU Digital Repository Spinoza on the Spirit of Friendship by David Belcheff A Thesis Presented in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree Master of Arts Approved April 2014 by the Graduate Supervisory Committee: Eugene Clay, Co-chair Norbert Samuelson, Co-chair Peter Foley ARIZONA STATE UNIVERSITY May 2014 ABSTRACT Baruch de Spinoza (1632-1677) is most often treated as a secular philosopher in the literature. But the critical-historical and textual analyses explored in this study suggest that Spinoza wrote the Ethics not as a secular project intended to supersede monotheism for those stoic enough to plumb its icy depths, but rather, and as is much less often assumed, as a genuinely Judeo-Christian theological discourse accounting for the changing scientific worldviews and political realities of his time. This paper draws upon scholarship documenting Spinoza's involvement with Christian sects such as the Collegiants and Quakers. After establishing the largely unappreciated importance of Spinoza's religious or theological thought, a close reading of the Ethics demonstrates that friendship is the theme that ties together Spinoza's ethical, theological, political, and scientific doctrines. i For Tanya ii ACKNOWLEDGMENTS Many thanks to Dr. Norbert M. Samuelson, not least of all for introducing me to Spinoza. Being able to work closely with Dr. Samuelson has given me a privileged insight into the works of Gersonides and of other medieval Jewish thinkers from which many of Spinoza’s important insights sprang. Humble thanks to Dr.
    [Show full text]
  • STUDIES in MODALITY and COSMOLOGY Plenitude and Possibility in the Late Ancient and Arabic Traditions
    STUDIES IN MODALITY AND COSMOLOGY Plenitude and Possibility in the Late Ancient and Arabic Traditions A Summary Taneli Kukkonen To be presented for public discussion, by due permission of the Faculty of Theology, at the University of Helsinki in Auditorium XII on Wednesday, May 15th, 2002, at noon. ABSTRACT STUDIES IN MODALITY AND COSMOLOGY Plenitude and Possibility in the Late Ancient and Arabic Traditions Taneli Kukkonen University of Helsinki, FIN The thesis consists of six separately published articles and a summary. All deal in some form with occurrences in late Ancient and medieval Arabic philosophy of what is known as the “principle of Plenitude”. Professor Arthur O. Lovejoy, who coined the term in his 1936 study The Great Chain of Being, gave to the principle the formulation that “no genuine potentiality of being can remain unfulfilled”. While allusive, the formulation is rather vague. The notion that all possibilities find actualisation can be employed in various different ways in different conceptual contexts. In an argument, it can serve as a presupposition or as a conclusion; it can be grounded in modal logic, metaphysical concerns, or the theological precept that God is ultimately liberal. Sometimes the possibility is raised only in order to be disputed. All of these options were explored in the debates covered in these essays. In the late Ancient and Arabic periods, the treatment of modal notions was often tied in with cosmological issues. The discussions therefore touch upon such subjects as for instance the need for science to make necessary universal judgements. Among the philosophers whose thought is assessed are such figures as Proclus (d.
    [Show full text]
  • Space and Time As Relations: the Theoretical Approach of Leibniz
    philosophies Article Space and Time as Relations: The Theoretical Approach of Leibniz Basil Evangelidis ID Faculty of Humanities, Philosophy, Leiden University, Limesstraße 4d, 63450 Hanau, Germany; [email protected]; Tel.: +49-151-6818-4147 Received: 17 December 2017; Accepted: 27 March 2018; Published: 2 April 2018 Abstract: The epistemological rupture of Copernicus, the laws of planetary motions of Kepler, the comprehensive physical observations of Galileo and Huygens, the conception of relativity, and the physical theory of Newton were components of an extremely fertile and influential cognitive environment that prompted the restless Leibniz to shape an innovative theory of space and time. This theory expressed some of the concerns and intuitions of the scientific community of the seventeenth century, in particular the scientific group of the Academy of Sciences of Paris, but remained relatively unknown until the twentieth century. After Einstein, however, the relational theory of Leibniz gained wider respect and fame. The aim of this article is to explain how Leibniz foresaw relativity, through his critique of contemporary mechanistic philosophy. Keywords: space; time; absolute; relative; motion; acceleration; relativity 1. Introduction Leibniz was of the belief that space and time are not real entities but virtual relationships and mathematical concepts. He was led to this conclusion through the problem of the relationship of the mind with space, the study of the nature of the continuous in various mathematical fields, and the observation of linear and centrifugal movement, as well as the confrontation with atomism based on the assumption of the inexistence of vacuum. Space is an order of coexisting phenomena, as time is an order of successive phenomena.
    [Show full text]