'Epistemology Naturalized' and the Vienna Circle

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

'Epistemology Naturalized' and the Vienna Circle DOI: https://doi.org/10.26512/rfmc.v8i2.35867 ’Epistemology Naturalized’ and the Vienna Circle [’Epistemologia Naturalizada’ e o Círculo de Viena] Thomas Uebel* Abstract: This paper considers W.V.O. Quine’s inauguration of naturalistic epistemology at the 14th International Congress of Philosophy in Vienna in 1969 and argues that, contrary to his suggestions, naturalistic epistemology was practiced in the Vienna Circle already back in the days when he visited them fresh out of graduate school. Keywords: Naturalistic Epistemology. Logical Empiricism. Quine. Carnap. Neurath. Resumo: Este artigo analisa o início da epistemologia naturalista de W.V.O. Quine, no 14o Congresso Internacional de Filosofia em Viena, em 1969 e argumenta que, ao contrário de suas sugestões, a epistemologia naturalista já era praticada no Círculo de Viena no tempo em que ele o visitava, recém-saído da pós-graduação. Palavras-chave: Epistemologia naturalista. Empirismo lógico. Quine. Carnap. Neurath. 1. Introduction Carnap’s, like the analytic/synthetic distinction or the distinction between W.V.O. Quine’s " Epistemology Natura- internal and external questions, that lized" was presented as an invited ad- Quine focused on. Now, however, it dress at the Fourteenth International was time to work on a larger canvass, to Congress of Philosophy on 9th Septem- pull together different strands in a pro- ber 1968 in Vienna, Austria. By an grammatic pronouncement that was to author who knew how to mark an oc- set an entire branch of philosophy on casion this paper did not disappoint. a new path. How better to stage such More than once before the philosophers a departure than by invoking, now as of the Vienna Circle whom Quine had genii loci, his " teacher and friend" of visited fresh out of graduate school, old and his former colleagues in the Vi- had served as foil for his own divergent enna Circle? So once more Quine set ideas in his earlier publications. Mostly out to revisit the Aufbau, even the Cir- it had been particular tenets of Rudolf cle’s protocol sentence debate, in order *Professor Emeritus at University of Manchester. Research interests in Epistemology, General Philosophy of Science and Philosophy of Social Science and in History of Analytic Philosophy and History of Philosophy of Science. E-mail: tho- [email protected]. ORCID: https://orcid.org/0000-0002-5414-235X. Revista de Filosofia Moderna e Contemporânea, Brasília, v.8, n.2, ago. 2020, p. 157-175 157 ISSN: 2317-9570 THOMAS UEBEL to contrast his own radical reorienta- on what the later Carnap got up to and tion of philosophy with theirs which, what his colleagues on the so-called left he suggested, was still stuck, for all of wing of the Circle did. its revolutionary flavor, in traditional When these questions are investiga- ways. ted more closely, it can be seen that The story Quine related that day by introducing naturalistic epistemo- stuck pretty well and seemed to con- logy to the world in Vienna in 1968 firm the death of logical positivism or Quine was not exactly taking coals to empiricism then already diagnosed in Newcastle-but he got pretty close. To reference works.1 The few scholars be sure, the devastation that Austro- who brought news from dusty archi- fascism and Nazism had wrought on ves that matters weren’t quite as neat the academic landscape in Vienna en- as all that were told to get out more sured that even locals were not aware or simply ignored. Thus still today in of this. In fact, it was not until the 1982 even as normally reliable repositories Moritz Schlick and Otto Neurath Cen- of philosophical learning as the Stan- tenarium conference, also in Vienna, ford Encyclopedia one can read under that C. G. Hempel recalled Neurath as " Naturalism in Epistemology" that " the a naturalistic philosopher (1982).3 Car- logical empiricists approached episte- nap’s naturalism-or better: the natura- mology, as other areas, as a matter of a listic potential of Carnap’s philosophy- priori ’rational reconstruction’, in Car- took still longer to be uncovered, as we nap’s famous phrase". With a brief refe- will see. I begin with what Quine told rence to the Aufbau the case was closed. the 1968 Congress before surveying the But is the Aufbau the only or even the lines of inquiry concerning Carnap that most representative work of Carnap’s a full investigation would have to con- and is Carnap the only philosopher of sult in depth. This includes a brief re- note or relevance in the Vienna Circle view of the case for Neurath’s natura- in the present context?2 Both of these lism in relation to which Carnap’s phi- questions matter quite centrally for the losophy must be viewed to appreciate issue of the relation between episte- its naturalistic potential. mological naturalism and logical po- sitivism/empiricism for it largely turns 1See, e.g., Passmore (1967, p.52). I use “logical positivism” and “logical empiricism” interchangeably. As I understand it, the difference the terms denoted at the time were but passing local rivalries; see Uebel (2011). 2See Rysview (2016). Which in other respects is very informative—also refers to Reichenbach’s Experience and Prediction and his take on the distinction of the contexts of inquiry—discovery v. justification—as unproblematically representative. It isn’t and it also matters for the question of the nature of the naturalism championed in the Circle, if any; see Uebel (2000). 3A few years later Dirk Koppelberg deepened the message: see his (1987) and (1990). On the state of Austrian philosophy in the 1950s see Haller (1983). 158 Revista de Filosofia Moderna e Contemporânea, Brasília, v.8, n.2, ago. 2020, p. 157-175 ISSN: 2317-9570 ’EPISTEMOLOGY NATURALIZED’ AND THE VIENNA CIRCLE 2. Quine on Carnap, 1968 can be less than adequately informa- tive, imagine Quine to be remembered only as a radical nominalist who wan- Whatever else must be said about it, let ted to do away with numbers.) me start by saying that " Epistemology The next thing to note is that we must Naturalized" is a magnificent paper: not read Quine as saying more than he sufficiently broad in its historical sweep actually did. Thus the Stanford article across the centuries to impress upon suggests that for Quine the Vienna Cir- its audience the momentous occasion cle pursued the " Cartesian quest for its proposals represent, yet detailed certainty [as] a remote motivation of enough with its analogies to the abor- epistemology, both on its conceptual tive reductive programmes of the past and its doctrinal side". This overlooks to induce a conviction in the audience that Quine conceded that Carnap had that the diagnosis presented is sound abandoned this " as a lost cause" and enough and holds a deep moral for phi- was motivated instead " to elicit and losophy if we ever want to escape the clarify the sensory evidence for science" perennial doldrums. and so to " deepen our understanding So how did Quine portray the logical of our discourse of the world" (QUINE, positivists of the Vienna Circle here? 1969, p. 74-5). Relatedly Quine spoke Well, he did not exactly misrepresent of Russell’s external world programme, them-though he did make one egregi- when he likened Carnap’s Aufbau pro- ous mistake-but he certainly did not ject to it, as aiming to " account for the tell the whole story. That as in his pre- external world as a logical construct vious writings his main focus was Car- of sense data" (CARNAP. 1969, p.74): nap is not surprising since, for better or there is notable room for interpreta- worse Carnap was logical positivism for tion in this formulation. With regard to him; more to the point is that Quine’s Carnap then, perhaps even to Russell, Carnap is not the whole of Carnap. Of Quine very carefully stopped short of course, it was not Quine’s job to be com- attributing the traditional foundationa- prehensive, but his selective focus does list project by stressing the elucidatory point up a very general feature of the import of the reductive projects under- common view of logical positivism-a taken (and in addition cleared Carnap feature concerning which the rhetorical of infallibilist yearnings). scene-settings of Quine’s papers (here Now the first we hear of and about and in " Two Dogmas") are not wholly Carnap himself in " Epistemology Na- innocent. That is that logical positivism turalized" is indeed as the author of is remembered for its early theoretical the book that came " nearest" to reali- starting points, not for the mature po- zing the Russellian external world pro- sitions reached later. (To see that this Revista de Filosofia Moderna e Contemporânea, Brasília, v.8, n.2, ago. 2020, p. 157-175 159 ISSN: 2317-9570 THOMAS UEBEL gram (QUINE, 1969 p.74), Der logische reduction of physical object discourse Aufbau der Welt (translated as The Lo- to talk of (constructed) sense data fai- gical Structure of the World. Herafter: led: there was no one-to-one mapping Aufbau, 1928). That’s fair enough in from the latter to the former. Yet this a way, given the qualifications we just time Quine also pointed out what " Two saw Quine slipping in. However, we Dogmas" did not-and what some rea- must add that recent scholarship has ders of his address evidently missed- conclusively established that there is namely that it was not doctrinal cer- far more to the Aufbau than that. Even tainty but merely translational reduc- if we discount its syncretist tendency to tion was Carnap’s point.5 To be sure, merge a great variety of disparate phi- this still leaves entirely unaddressed losophical tendencies and focus only on what one may wish to obtain transla- its reductionist strategy of establishing tional reduction for and unwary rea- a genealogy for all empirical concepts ders easily jump to the conclusion that on the basis of that of remembered si- it was for foundationalist designs.
Recommended publications
  • Logical Empiricism / Positivism Some Empiricist Slogans
    4/13/16 Logical empiricism / positivism Some empiricist slogans o Hume’s 18th century book-burning passage Key elements of a logical positivist /empiricist conception of science o Comte’s mid-19th century rejection of n Motivations for post WW1 ‘scientific philosophy’ ‘speculation after first & final causes o viscerally opposed to speculation / mere metaphysics / idealism o Duhem’s late 19th/early 20th century slogan: o a normative demarcation project: to show why science ‘save the phenomena’ is and should be epistemically authoritative n Empiricist commitments o Hempel’s injunction against ‘detours n Logicism through the realm of unobservables’ Conflicts & Memories: The First World War Vienna Circle Maria Marchant o Debussy: Berceuse héroique, Élégie So - what was the motivation for this “revolutionary, written war-time Paris (1914), heralds the ominous bugle call of war uncompromising empricism”? (Godfrey Smith, Ch. 2) o Rachmaninov: Études-Tableaux Op. 39, No 8, 5 “some of the most impassioned, fervent work the composer wrote” Why the “massive intellectual housecleaning”? (Godfrey Smith) o Ireland: Rhapsody, London Nights, London Pieces a “turbulant, virtuosic work… Consider the context: World War I / the interwar period o Prokofiev: Visions Fugitives, Op. 22 written just before he fled as a fugitive himself to the US (1917); military aggression & sardonic irony o Ravel: Le Tombeau de Couperin each of six movements dedicated to a friend who died in the war x Key problem (1): logicism o Are there, in fact, “rules” governing inference
    [Show full text]
  • Politics and Philosophy in the Left Vienna Circle
    Intersubjective Accountability: Politics and Philosophy in the Left Vienna Circle Thomas Uebel The University of Manchester In different places Rudolf Carnap and Otto Neurath affirmed “a noteworthy agreement” and an “inner link” between their philosophy of science and political movements agitating for radical socio-economic change. Given the normative abstinence of Vienna Circle philosophy, indeed the metaethical com- mitments of its verificationism, this claim presents a major interpretive chal- lenge that is only heightened when Neurath’s engagement for the socialization of national economies is taken into account. It is argued here that Carnap’s and Neurath’s positions are saved from inconsistency once some careful distinc- tions are understood and it is recognized that they, together with the other members of the Circle, adhered to an epistemic norm here called “intersubjective accountability.” 1. Introduction The question of the political potential possessed by the philosophies of the Vienna Circle is complex for more than one reason. It is so partly due to the politically heterogeneous membership of the Circle, partly due to the dif- ficult if not extreme political circumstances under which they had to operate, and partly due to the variable meanings of the parameter “political,” some of which are and some of which are not compatible with, in turn, variable ver- sions of the doctrine of the value-neutrality of science. For instance, philos- ophies of science may steadfastly be standing guard against pseudo-scientific nonsense being paraded as worthy of credence in public discourse, this con- cern for intellectual hygene becoming “political” depending on who spouts An earlier version of this paper was presented at the workshop “Positivismus als gesellschaftliches und politsches Projekt” convened by Eric Hilgendorf at the University of Münster in January 2017 and I thank the participants for discussions.
    [Show full text]
  • The Subterranean Influence of Pragmatism on the Vienna Circle: Peirce, Ramsey, Wittgenstein
    JOURNAL FOR THE HISTORY OF ANALYTICAL PHILOSOPHY THE SUBTERRANEAN INflUENCE OF PRAGMATISM ON THE VOLUME 4, NUMBER 5 VIENNA CIRCLE: PEIRCE, RAMSEY, WITTGENSTEIN CHERYL MISAK EDITOR IN CHIEF KEVIN C. KLEMENt, UnIVERSITY OF MASSACHUSETTS An underappreciated fact in the history of analytic philoso- EDITORIAL BOARD phy is that American pragmatism had an early and strong in- GaRY EBBS, INDIANA UnIVERSITY BLOOMINGTON fluence on the Vienna Circle. The path of that influence goes GrEG FROSt-ARNOLD, HOBART AND WILLIAM SMITH COLLEGES from Charles Peirce to Frank Ramsey to Ludwig Wittgenstein to HENRY JACKMAN, YORK UnIVERSITY Moritz Schlick. That path is traced in this paper, and along the SANDRA LaPOINte, MCMASTER UnIVERSITY way some standard understandings of Ramsey and Wittgen- LyDIA PATTON, VIRGINIA TECH stein, especially, are radically altered. MARCUS ROSSBERG, UnIVERSITY OF CONNECTICUT MARK TEXTOR, KING’S COLLEGE LonDON AUDREY YAP, UnIVERSITY OF VICTORIA RICHARD ZACH, UnIVERSITY OF CALGARY REVIEW EDITORS JULIET FLOYD, BOSTON UnIVERSITY CHRIS PINCOCK, OHIO STATE UnIVERSITY ASSISTANT REVIEW EDITOR SEAN MORRIS, METROPOLITAN STATE UnIVERSITY OF DenVER DESIGN DaNIEL HARRIS, HUNTER COLLEGE JHAPONLINE.ORG C 2016 CHERYL MISAK THE SUBTERRANEAN INflUENCE OF saving labor, is . true instrumentally. Satisfactorily . means PRAGMATISM ON THE VIENNA CIRCLE: PEIRCE, more satisfactorily to ourselves, and individuals will emphasize their points of satisfaction differently. To a certain degree, there- RAMSEY, WITTGENSTEIN fore, everything here is plastic. (James 1975, 34–35)2 CHERYL MISAK It was Peirce’s more sophisticated pragmatism that influenced Ramsey. C. K. Ogden, inventor of Basic English, publisher of the Tractaus, and co-author of The Meaning of Meaning, was Ram- sey’s mentor from the time he was a schoolboy.
    [Show full text]
  • Karl Sigmund, Exact Thinking in Demented Times: the Vienna Circle and the Epic Quest for the Foundations of Science New York, NY: Basic Books, 2017
    The Review of Austrian Economics https://doi.org/10.1007/s11138-018-0428-1 Karl Sigmund, Exact Thinking in Demented Times: The Vienna Circle and the Epic Quest for the Foundations of Science New York, NY: Basic Books, 2017. xviii + 480 pages. $17.99 (hardcover) Erwin Dekker1 # Springer Science+Business Media, LLC, part of Springer Nature 2018 It might be time for a revival of the demarcation principles between science and non- science of the Vienna circle and of Karl Popper’s critical rationalism if we are to believe the title of Karl Sigmund’sbookExact Thinking in Demented Times. Not only because he shows a deep appreciation for their thought in this book, but also because the title seems to contain a clear allusion to our own age. The book accompanied an Austrian 2015 exhibition on the Vienna Circle and the original German title of the book even suggests that these philosophers were thinking at the edge of the abyss, so what is there to learn about exact thinking in demented times from it? What Sigmund, an accomplished evolutionary game theorist, manages to do in the book is to provide a vivid portrayal of the different characters within and around the Vienna Circle, the most famous of the many circles that made up intellectual life in Vienna during the first decades of the twentieth century. We get to know the energetic and boisterous Otto Neurath with his red manes, the enigmatic and elusive Ludwig Wittgenstein, we meet the cautious Moritz Schlick who acts as the pater familias of the group of revolutionary philosophers, and perhaps the most systematic of them all Rudolf Carnap.
    [Show full text]
  • Passmore, J. (1967). Logical Positivism. in P. Edwards (Ed.). the Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Vol. 5, 52- 57). New York: Macmillan
    Passmore, J. (1967). Logical Positivism. In P. Edwards (Ed.). The Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Vol. 5, 52- 57). New York: Macmillan. LOGICAL POSITIVISM is the name given in 1931 by A. E. Blumberg and Herbert Feigl to a set of philosophical ideas put forward by the Vienna circle. Synonymous expressions include "consistent empiricism," "logical empiricism," "scientific empiricism," and "logical neo-positivism." The name logical positivism is often, but misleadingly, used more broadly to include the "analytical" or "ordinary language philosophies developed at Cambridge and Oxford. HISTORICAL BACKGROUND The logical positivists thought of themselves as continuing a nineteenth-century Viennese empirical tradition, closely linked with British empiricism and culminating in the antimetaphysical, scientifically oriented teaching of Ernst Mach. In 1907 the mathematician Hans Hahn, the economist Otto Neurath, and the physicist Philipp Frank, all of whom were later to be prominent members of the Vienna circle, came together as an informal group to discuss the philosophy of science. They hoped to give an account of science which would do justice -as, they thought, Mach did not- to the central importance of mathematics, logic, and theoretical physics, without abandoning Mach's general doctrine that science is, fundamentally, the description of experience. As a solution to their problems, they looked to the "new positivism" of Poincare; in attempting to reconcile Mach and Poincare; they anticipated the main themes of logical positivism. In 1922, at the instigation of members of the "Vienna group," Moritz Schlick was invited to Vienna as professor, like Mach before him (1895-1901), in the philosophy of the inductive sciences. Schlick had been trained as a scientist under Max Planck and had won a name for himself as an interpreter of Einstein's theory of relativity.
    [Show full text]
  • Vienna Circle Institute Library
    Vienna Circle Institute Library Volume 4 Series editor Friedrich Stadler University of Vienna, Institute Vienna Circle, Wien, Austria Institut Wiener Kreis Society for the Advancement of the Scientifi c World Conception Advisory Editorial Board: Ilkka Niiniluoto, University of Helsinki, Finland Jacques Bouveresse, Collège de France, Paris, Otto Pfersmann, Université Paris I Panthéon – France Sorbonne, France Martin Carrier, University of Bielefeld, Germany Miklós Rédei, London School of Economics, UK Nancy Cartwright, London School of Alan Richardson, University of British Economics, UK Columbia, CDN Richard Creath, Arizona State University, USA Gerhard Schurz, University of Düsseldorf, Massimo Ferrari, University of Torino, Italy Germany Michael Friedman, Stanford University, USA Peter Schuster, University of Vienna, Austria Maria Carla Galavotti, University of Bologna, Karl Sigmund, University of Vienna, Austria Italy Hans Sluga, University of California at Berkeley, Peter Galison, Harvard University, USA USA Malachi Hacohen, Duke University, USA Elliott Sober, University of Wisconsin, USA Rainer Hegselmann, University of Bayreuth, Antonia Soulez, Université de Paris 8, France Germany Wolfgang Spohn, University of Konstanz, Michael Heidelberger, University of Tübingen, Germany Germany Thomas E. Uebel, University of Manchester, UK Don Howard, University of Notre Dame, USA Pierre Wagner, Université de Paris 1, Sorbonne, Paul Hoyningen-Huene, University of Hanover, France Germany C. Kenneth Waters, University of Minnesota, USA Clemens Jabloner,
    [Show full text]
  • This Volume on the Vienna Circle's Influence in the Nordic Countries
    Vol. 8, no. 1 (2013) Category: Review essay Written by Carlo Penco This volume on the Vienna Circle’s influence in the Nordic countries gives a very interesting presentation of an almost forgotten landmark. In the years preceding the Second World War, European philosophy was at the high point of its intellectual vitality. Everywhere philosophical societies promoted a dense network of connections among scholars, with international meetings and strong links among individuals and associations. In this context, the Vienna Circle emerges as one of the many, also if probably the most well-known, centres of diffusion of a new style of philosophy, closely linked to the new logic and with a strongly empiricist attitude. At the same time, empiricism, formal logic and psychology constituted (and still constitute) the common background of most of the Nordic philosophers, a background which permitted them to develop connections with Vienna’s cultural environment (well known also for the work of psychologists such as Sigmund Freud, but also Charlotte and Karl Bühler). This piece of history, although limited to the connection between Nordic philosophy and Vienna Circle, helps to clarify the history of European philosophy, and the sharp difference of Nordic philosophy in respect of the development of philosophy in Southern and Central Europe in the half a century following the Second World War. The editors say in the introduction: . one of the least known networks of the Vienna Circle is the “Nordic connection”. This connection had a continuing influence for many of the coming decades, beginning with the earliest phase of the Vienna Circle and continuing with a number of adaptations and innovations well into contemporary times.
    [Show full text]
  • The Basic Elements of the Philosophy of Alfred J. Ayer
    University of Windsor Scholarship at UWindsor Electronic Theses and Dissertations Theses, Dissertations, and Major Papers 1-1-1957 The basic elements of the philosophy of Alfred J. Ayer. Robert M. Montague University of Windsor Follow this and additional works at: https://scholar.uwindsor.ca/etd Recommended Citation Montague, Robert M., "The basic elements of the philosophy of Alfred J. Ayer." (1957). Electronic Theses and Dissertations. 6282. https://scholar.uwindsor.ca/etd/6282 This online database contains the full-text of PhD dissertations and Masters’ theses of University of Windsor students from 1954 forward. These documents are made available for personal study and research purposes only, in accordance with the Canadian Copyright Act and the Creative Commons license—CC BY-NC-ND (Attribution, Non-Commercial, No Derivative Works). Under this license, works must always be attributed to the copyright holder (original author), cannot be used for any commercial purposes, and may not be altered. Any other use would require the permission of the copyright holder. Students may inquire about withdrawing their dissertation and/or thesis from this database. For additional inquiries, please contact the repository administrator via email ([email protected]) or by telephone at 519-253-3000ext. 3208. THE BASIC ELEMENTS OF THE PHILOSOPHY OF ALFRED J. AYER Submitted to the Department of Philosophy of Assumption University of Windsor in Part­ ial Fulfilment of the Requirements for the Degree of Master of Arts by Robert M. Montague, C.S.B., B.A. 1957 Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission. UMI Number: EC52461 INFORMATION TO USERS The quality of this reproduction is dependent upon the quality of the copy submitted.
    [Show full text]
  • The Demarcation Problem and Alternative Medicine by Donald Gillies, University College London
    The Demarcation Problem and Alternative Medicine by Donald Gillies, University College London (This is a paper which was given at a conference in La Coruña, Spain in 2003 on ‘Karl R. Popper: Revision of his Legacy’. A Spanish version of it has appeared in the conference proceedings.) Contents (1) Introduction (2) The Demarcation Problem and the Vienna Circle (3) Popper on the Demarcation Problem (4) Falsifiability and the Duhem-Quine Thesis (5) Alternative Medicine 1. Introduction In this paper I intend to examine Popper’s views on a philosophical problem with which he was very preoccupied throughout his life – namely the problem of demarcation. My aim is partly to expound Popper’s ideas against their historical background, but also to try to assess the merit of his ideas and their relevance today. I will begin in this introduction by giving a general sketch of my attitude to Popper’s philosophy. This can best be done by listing a number of points, some of which will be in favour of Popper and some critical of him. Point 1 is in favour of Popper. It is that he always worked on important philosophical problems. Indeed the problem of demarcation is central to philosophy of science and indeed to epistemology in general. Regrettably many philosophers go wrong by devoting a great deal of ingenuity to rather trivial questions. The result of such investigations can never be very interesting, and the ability to see what questions are important is part of what makes a great philosopher. Point 2 is also in favour of Popper.
    [Show full text]
  • 1. Introduction: the Vienna Circle, Carnap and Neurath
    doi: 10.5007/1808-1711.2013v17n2p319 THE UTOPIAOF UNIFIED SCIENCE: THE POLITICAL STRUGGLEOF OTTO NEURATH ANDTHE VIENNA CIRCLE IVAN FERREIRA DA CUNHA Abstract. Neurath’s approach to the problem of the unity of science is different from con- ceptions we may call traditional, to know, those that consider that what unites in one single concept the diverse sciences is the adoption of a method, or those that defend that this is carried through by certain characteristics which can be found in the body of knowledge considered scientific. Neurath’s stance also diverges from the standpoint that there is no unifying factor for science, that is, the view that the different sciences are only classified under such concept because of the historical origin of such activities. Neurath’s proposal is to consider science as an attitude, a posture in relation to the problems of the world, the scientific world-conception. This text presents such approach in connection to the aspect of social transformation that can be found in Neurath’s thought. This is done following a comprehension of the ideas of the Vienna Circle, seeking to understand a continuity among the ideas of the members of such group, especially Neurath and Carnap. The present text aims, as well, at recovering the Neurathian idea that we can use a philosophical approach to science to struggle against the problems of the world. Keywords: Unity of science; Neurath; Vienna Circle; philosophy of social sciences; encyclo- pedism. 1. Introduction: the Vienna Circle, Carnap and Neurath This text aims at discussing Neurath’s approach to the problem of the unity of sci- ence.
    [Show full text]
  • KARL POPPER's DEBT to LEONARD NELSON Nikolay
    Grazer Philosophische Studien 86 (2012), 137–156. KARL POPPER’S DEBT TO LEONARD NELSON Nikolay MILKOV University of Paderborn Summary Karl Popper has often been cast as one of the most solitary fi gures of twentieth- century philosophy. Th e received image is of a thinker who developed his scien- tifi c philosophy virtually alone and in opposition to a crowd of brilliant members of the Vienna Circle. Th is paper challenges the received view and undertakes to correctly situate on the map of the history of philosophy Popper’s contribution, in particular, his renowned fallibilist theory of knowledge. Th e motive for doing so is the conviction that the mainstream perspective on Popper’s philosophy makes him more diffi cult to understand than might otherwise be the case. Th e thinker who fi gures most signifi cantly in the account of Popper devel- oped in these pages is Leonard Nelson. Both a neo-Friesian and neo-Kantian, this philosopher deeply infl uenced Popper through his student Julius Kraft, who met with Popper on numerous occasions in the mid 1920s. It is in the light of this infl uence that we understand Popper’s recollection that when he criticized the Vienna Circle in the early 1930s, he looked upon himself “as an unorthodox Kantian”. Introduction Since Nelson’s philosophy is little known today, the essay commences with a brief account (in § 1) of how he developed elements of what was later dubbed analytic philosophy. Following that we identify (in § 2) the main points of Nelson’s impact on Popper, as well as some elements of divergence between them.
    [Show full text]
  • Logical Empiricism
    Logical Empiricism HISTORICAL CONTEMPORARY PERSPECTIVES Edited by Paolo Parrini, University ofFlorence Wesley C. Salmon, University ofPittsburgh Merrilee H. Salmon, University of Pittsburgh UNIVERSITY OF PITTSBURGH PRESS This book is dedicated to the memory of Wesley C . Salmon 1925-2001 Published by the University of Pittsburgh Press, Pittsburgh, P&, 15260 Copyright ® 2003, University of Pittsburgh Press All rights reserved Manufactured in the United States of America Printed on add-free paper 10987654321 ISBN 0 - 8n9- 4194-5 Contents Preface Introduction r Paolo Parrini and Wesley Salmon I. Turning Points and Fundamental Controversies rt A Turning Point in Philosophy : Carnap-Cassirer-Heidegger 13 Michael Friedman Carnap's "Elimination of Metaphysics through Logical Analysis of Language" : A Retrospective Consideration of the Relationship between Continental and Analytic Philosophy 30 Gottfried Gabriel Schlick and Husserl on the Essence of Knowledge 43 Roberta Lanfredini Carnap versus Gbdel on Syntax and Tolerance 57 S. Awodey and A. W Carus II. On the Origins and Development of the Vienna Circle 65 On the Austrian Roots of Logical Empiricism: The Case of the First Vienna Circle 67 Thomas Uebel On the International Encyclopedia, the Neurath-Carnap Disputes, and the Second World War 94 George Reisch Carl Gustav Hempel : Pragmatic Empiricist log Gereon Wolters III. The Riddle of Wittgenstein 123 The Methods of the Tractatus: Beyond Positivism and Metaphysics? 125 David G. Stern IV Philosophy of Physics 157 Two Roads from Kant : Cassirer, Reichenbach, and General Relativity ' 159 T A. Ryckman Vienna Indeterminism II : From Exner to Frank and von Mises 194 'Michael Stoltzner V. The Mind-Body Problem 231 The Mind-Body Problem in the Origin of Logical Empiricism : Herbert Feigl and Psychophysical Parallelism 233 Michael Heidelberger Logical Positivism and the Mind-Body Problem 263 Jaegwon Kim VI.
    [Show full text]