Plato's Socrates, Sophistic Antithesis and Scepticism

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Plato's Socrates, Sophistic Antithesis and Scepticism DOUGAL BLYTH | 25 Plato’s Socrates, Sophistic Antithesis and Scepticism Dougal Blyth The University of Auckland [email protected] ABSTRACT In some Platonic dialogues Socrates appar- ently shares significant characteristics with contemporary sophists, especially a technique of antithetical argumentation. Since sophists an- ticipated later Academic philosophers in arguing antithetically and a resultant form of scepticism, then, with Socrates’ repeated claims to igno- rance, Plato’s depiction of him arguing antitheti- cally suggests later Academics could plausibly appeal to Plato for evidence that Socrates and he were sceptics, as it seems they actually did. Keywords: Plato, Socrates, Sceptics, Sophists, antithesis. https://doi.org/10.14195/2183-4105_19_2 26 | Plato’s Socrates, Sophistic Antithesis and Scepticism Later members of Plato’s school, those we the most plausible for them individually and to- collectively call Academic sceptics, claimed gether, in virtue of their shared characteristics, consistency with both Socrates and Plato.1 Sev- although it is not meant to imply that they form eral scholars in recent years have traced and in- an exclusive group, nor to deny the relevance of terpreted the limited evidence for this ancient evidence from other dialogues. sceptic interpretation of Plato, and evaluated it Quite a number of other dialogues do not more or less positively.2 Moreover some scholars exhibit a predominance of either antithetic ar- have advanced in their own names sceptic inter- gumentation or Socratic refutations, but instead pretations of both Socrates and Plato.3 While it more or less systematically supported claims, of- seems to me that the truth about Plato overall ten implicitly at least attributable to Socrates, or is more complex (although in a sense consistent another main speaker, although certainly those with this view),4 here I want to draw attention to of Socrates are often hedged about with warn- another kind of support for the interpretation of ings that they are only his beliefs (e.g. Meno 98a- Plato’s depiction of Socrates as a sceptic, from b, Rep. 6.506c-e), or merely the implications of the evidence of fifth century BC sophists. the current argument in a given dialogue (cf. I will argue that Socrates, in some Platon- Crito 46b, Phaedo 107b, Rep. 3.394d), or occur ic dialogues concerned with both individual in highly rhetorical contexts (e.g. Symp. 211c- sophists and the nature of knowledge, shares 212a; Phaedr. 245c-57b).6 Thus, finally I shall significantly in a range of characteristics be- consider a problem for an Academic sceptic in- longing (or at least attributed by Plato) to sever- terpretation of Plato’s Socrates, the problem of al sophists, including, significantly, a technique his belief statements, and present as briefly as of antithetical argumentation.5 Moreover inde- I can an evaluation of some possible ways later pendent evidence suggests some sophists an- Academics might most plausibly reconcile this ticipated the later Academic philosophers not significant common feature of many dialogues just in arguing antithetically but also a form of with a sceptical interpretation of Plato overall.7 scepticism, and that among these sophists an- tithetical argumentation probably led to their scepticism. Thus, in conjunction with Socrates’ ACADEMIC ARGUMENTATION repeated claims to ignorance in the dialogues, AND SOCRATES in this sophistic context Plato’s depiction of him arguing antithetically suggests that later One argumentative technique that undeni- Academics could indeed quite plausibly appeal ably connects Plato’s Socrates explicitly with to Platonic dialogues for evidence that Socrates the sceptical Academy is dialectical refutation. was a sceptic. Cicero refers to Socrates’ use of this against the I will initially restrict the detailed case to the sophists at Fin. 2.2, where he then reports that plausibility of a sceptical interpretation of the Arcesilaus (c.316-c.240 BC), who is said to have Socrates presented by Plato in the Protagoras, initiated the sceptic turn in the Academy when Hippias Minor, Gorgias, Meno, Lysis and The- he became its scholarch (c.265 BC), revived aetetus, and Plato as the author of these. The this technique, which was no longer in use in justification for focusing on these dialogues is his own day. Yet later in the same work Cicero merely that, on the basis of the evidence I shall shows that Arcesilaus also engaged in extended discuss, the sceptical interpretation seems to me speeches designed to counterbalance an oppos- DOUGAL BLYTH | 27 ing dogmatic position (Fin. 5.10). As Acad. 1.45 Yet as I shall show below, both the latter tech- puts it, he argued against everyone’s opinions, niques seem also to be found repeatedly in Plato. This will then raise the question of motive. so that when equally weighty arguments A speech directed against another speaker’s were found for contrary positions on the position might be considered in intention just same subject, it was easier to withhold as- eristic, or again refutatory, that is, designed to sent from either position (trans. Inwood achieve either a merely verbal victory in the and Gerson). one case, or a seriously meant change of mind in the opponent. But a refutation, in the latter A.A. Long, who regards Arcesilaus as the origi- case, might aim at either the opponent’s or audi- nator of the conception of Socrates as a sceptic,8 ence’s adoption of the opposite case (as formally also states, also in a reductio ad absurdum, for instance), or merely the realisation of ignorance (as similarly Arcesilaus in effect was the founder of in Socrates’ dialectical refutations); the aim is Greek scepticism, as a methodology then aporetic. for demonstrating that every claim to This recognition of ignorance (as apparently knowledge or belief could be met with in many Socratic refutations) might involve the a counter-argument of equal strength.9 presupposition that neither foregoing case is correct, so motivating the search for a new ac- In the following I aim to raise doubts about this count of the matter (zetetic scepticism), or if no claim. further alternative seems possible, the presup- Long rightly distinguishes between the pro- position will be that one or other of the two op- duction of arguments on either side of a case posed foregoing cases must be correct and the and arguing the opposite case to an opponent, other not (i.e., a dilemma), in which case either noting that more reliable sources do not report further inquiry is again required (again, zetetic Arcesilaus to have argued both sides of a case scepticism), or the abandonment of either all himself.10 This was subsequently the practice of opinions or just claims to certain knowledge the later Academic scholarch Carneades (214- (ephectic scepticism, epochê).14 In what follows I 129/8 BC), who notoriously spoke publicly on will aim to locate sophistic, Socratic and Aca- successive days for and against the view that demic scepticism within these contours, and, justice is intrinsically beneficial to the agent, with some further adjustments, trace their while on the Athenian embassy to Rome in 155 deeper similarities.15 BC.11 Moreover Cicero, who used reports of these speeches in De republica Bk 3, structured most of the works of his retirement around this SOPHISTIC ANTILOGY AND principle.12 SCEPTICISM Long himself acknowledges that Arcesilaus could justifiably claim to be practicing Socrates’ Clearly fifth century sophists realised two own technique of refutation, and observes that things about speeches: firstly, that they can the techniques of argument contra, or both pro be more or less persuasive, and secondly that and contra, owed something to the rhetorical there is always a speech that can be made for tradition—that is, ultimately, to the sophists.13 the opposite case.16 In the Clouds Aristophanes 28 | Plato’s Socrates, Sophistic Antithesis and Scepticism presents the Right and Wrong Speeches as liv- Socrates interprets Protagoras both in the The- ing teachers in Socrates’ school.17 Thus it was aetetus (152a, 161c) and Cratylus (285e-386a). common knowledge by the late 420s BC that Note that Socrates’ subsequent depiction of Pro- some sophists were teaching that every argu- tagoras in the Theaetetus (166d-167d) as aiming ment is opposed by another, and it is the power to improve people by changing the way things of persuasion, not the truth of a case, which de- appear to them, while implying that the latter’s termines which argument wins a case. Diogenes own rhetorical practice was indeed eristic-re- Laertius (9.51) states that Protagoras was the futatory, does not contradict the proposal here first to declare that there are two mutually op- that he recognised the proto-sceptical implica- posed arguments on any topic, while Aristotle tion that no speech can be naturally right or reports that Protagoras promised to make the wrong, since it presupposes just that.21 weaker argument stronger (Rhetoric 1402a14- Fragment 4 from Protagoras expresses apo- 6). Plato’s Apology 18b-d, 19b-c, has Socrates retic scepticism about the gods.22 We can see this claiming this was the popular belief about him- as another application of the same principle. If self as a result of the Clouds.18 human logoi cannot attain any objective truth, The Clouds demonstrates that the popular it might seem that we can be assured what the perception was that one case is naturally right, truth is by the authority of the gods, communi- while the sophists unscrupulously teach people cated in prophecies and oracles, and the many to win with the naturally weaker, or unjust, case. famous mythical poems inspired by the Muses. But it seems Protagoras went further, drawing But Protagoras denies knowledge of the gods as a conclusion that went beyond merely eristic a source of truth.
Recommended publications
  • Taking Sides and the Prehistory of Impartiality
    1. PREHISTORIES OF IMPARTIALITY TAKING SIDES AND THE PREHISTORY OF IMPARTIALITY Anita Traninger 1. Introduction: Taking Sides In his article “Taking Sides in Philosophy”, Gilbert Ryle inveighs against the ‘party-labels’ commonly awarded in philosophy. He impugns in partic- ular the conventional requirement to declare to what school one belongs because ‘[t]here is no place for “isms” in philosophy’.1 In concluding, how- ever, he is prepared to make ‘a few concessions’: Although, as I think, the motive of allegiance to a school or a leader is a non- philosophic and often an anti-philosophic motive, it may have some good results. Partisanship does generate zeal, combativeness, and team-spirit. [. .] Pedagogically, there is some utility in the superstition that philosophers are divided into Whigs and Tories. For we can work on the match-winning propensities of the young, and trick them into philosophizing by encourag- ing them to try to “dish” the Rationalists, or “scupper” the Hedonists.2 Even though Ryle chooses to reduce the value of taking sides to a propae- deutic set-up as a helpmeet for the young to come up with striking argu- ments, what he describes is precisely the modus operandi of dialectics, which had since antiquity been the methodological basis of philosophy. Dialectics conceived of thinking as a dialogue, and an agonistic one at that: it consisted in propounding a thesis and attacking it through questions. Problems were conceived of as being a choice between two positions, whence the name the procedure received in Roman times: in utramque partem disserere, arguing both sides of a question or arguing pro and con- tra.
    [Show full text]
  • Diogenes Laertius, Vitae Philosophorum, Book Five
    Binghamton University The Open Repository @ Binghamton (The ORB) The Society for Ancient Greek Philosophy Newsletter 12-1986 The Lives of the Peripatetics: Diogenes Laertius, Vitae Philosophorum, Book Five Michael Sollenberger Mount St. Mary's University, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://orb.binghamton.edu/sagp Part of the Ancient History, Greek and Roman through Late Antiquity Commons, Ancient Philosophy Commons, and the History of Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Sollenberger, Michael, "The Lives of the Peripatetics: Diogenes Laertius, Vitae Philosophorum, Book Five" (1986). The Society for Ancient Greek Philosophy Newsletter. 129. https://orb.binghamton.edu/sagp/129 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by The Open Repository @ Binghamton (The ORB). It has been accepted for inclusion in The Society for Ancient Greek Philosophy Newsletter by an authorized administrator of The Open Repository @ Binghamton (The ORB). For more information, please contact [email protected]. f\îc|*zx,e| lîâ& The Lives of the Peripatetics: Diogenes Laertius, Vitae Philosoohorum Book Five The biographies of six early Peripatetic philosophers are con­ tained in the fifth book of Diogenes Laertius* Vitae philosoohorum: the lives of the first four heads of the sect - Aristotle, Theophras­ tus, Strato, and Lyco - and those of two outstanding members of the school - Demetrius of Phalerum and Heraclides of Pontus, For the history of two rival schools, the Academy and the Stoa, we are for­ tunate in having not only Diogenes' versions in 3ooks Four and Seven, but also the Index Academicorum and the Index Stoicorum preserved among the papyri from Herculaneum, But for the Peripatos there-is no such second source.
    [Show full text]
  • Beyond Skepticism Foundationalism and the New Fuzziness: the Role of Wide Reflective Equilibrium in Legal Theory Robert Justin Lipkin
    Cornell Law Review Volume 75 Article 2 Issue 4 May 1990 Beyond Skepticism Foundationalism and the New Fuzziness: The Role of Wide Reflective Equilibrium in Legal Theory Robert Justin Lipkin Follow this and additional works at: http://scholarship.law.cornell.edu/clr Part of the Law Commons Recommended Citation Robert Justin Lipkin, Beyond Skepticism Foundationalism and the New Fuzziness: The Role of Wide Reflective Equilibrium in Legal Theory , 75 Cornell L. Rev. 810 (1990) Available at: http://scholarship.law.cornell.edu/clr/vol75/iss4/2 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Journals at Scholarship@Cornell Law: A Digital Repository. It has been accepted for inclusion in Cornell Law Review by an authorized administrator of Scholarship@Cornell Law: A Digital Repository. For more information, please contact [email protected]. BEYOND SKEPTICISM, FOUNDATIONALISM AND THE NEW FUZZINESS: THE ROLE OF WIDE REFLECTIVE EQUILIBRIUM IN LEGAL THEORY Robert Justin Liphint TABLE OF CONTENTS INTRODUCTION .............................................. 812 I. FOUNDATIONALISM AND SKEPTICISM ..................... 816 A. The Problem of Skepticism ........................ 816 B. Skepticism and Nihilism ........................... 819 1. Theoretical and PracticalSkepticism ................ 820 2. Subjectivism and Relativism ....................... 821 3. Epistemic and Conceptual Skepticism ................ 821 4. Radical Skepticism ............................... 822 C. Modified Skepticism ............................... 824 II. NEW FOUNDATIONALISM
    [Show full text]
  • Language Logic and Reality: a Stoic Perspective (Spring 2013)
    Language Logic and Reality: A Stoic Perspective Aaron Tuor History of Lingustics WWU Spring 2013 1 Language, Logic, and Reality: A Stoic perspective Contents 1 Introduction: The Tripartite Division of Stoic Philosophy.............................3 2 Stoic Physics...................................................................................................4 3 Stoic Dialectic.................................................................................................4 3.1 A Stoic Theory of Mind: Logos and presentations..........................4 3.2 Stoic Philosophy of Language: Lekta versus linguistic forms.........6 3.3 Stoic Logic.......................................................................................7 3.3.1 Simple and Complex Axiomata........................................7 3.3.2 Truth Conditions and Sentence Connectives....................8 3.3.3 Inference Schemata and Truths of Logic..........................9 3.4 Stoic Theory of Knowledge.............................................................10 3.4.1 Truth..................................................................................10 3.4.2 Knowledge........................................................................11 4 Conclusion: Analysis of an eristic argument..................................................12 4.1 Hermogenes as the Measure of "Man is the measure."...................13 Appendix I: Truth Tables and Inference Schemata...........................................17 Appendix II: Diagram of Communication.........................................................18
    [Show full text]
  • The Liar Paradox As a Reductio Ad Absurdum Argument
    University of Windsor Scholarship at UWindsor OSSA Conference Archive OSSA 3 May 15th, 9:00 AM - May 17th, 5:00 PM The Liar Paradox as a reductio ad absurdum argument Menashe Schwed Ashkelon Academic College Follow this and additional works at: https://scholar.uwindsor.ca/ossaarchive Part of the Philosophy Commons Schwed, Menashe, "The Liar Paradox as a reductio ad absurdum argument" (1999). OSSA Conference Archive. 48. https://scholar.uwindsor.ca/ossaarchive/OSSA3/papersandcommentaries/48 This Paper is brought to you for free and open access by the Conferences and Conference Proceedings at Scholarship at UWindsor. It has been accepted for inclusion in OSSA Conference Archive by an authorized conference organizer of Scholarship at UWindsor. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Title: The Liar Paradox as a Reductio ad Absurdum Author: Menashe Schwed Response to this paper by: Lawrence Powers (c)2000 Menashe Schwed 1. Introduction The paper discusses two seemingly separated topics: the origin and function of the Liar Paradox in ancient Greek philosophy and the Reduction ad absurdum mode of argumentation. Its goal is to show how the two topics fit together and why they are closely connected. The accepted tradition is that Eubulides of Miletos was the first to formulate the Liar Paradox correctly and that the paradox was part of the philosophical discussion of the Megarian School. Which version of the paradox was formulated by Eubulides is unknown, but according to some hints given by Aristotle and an incorrect version given by Cicero1, the version was probably as follows: The paradox is created from the Liar sentence ‘I am lying’.
    [Show full text]
  • Defense of Reductionism About Testimonial Justification of Beliefs
    Page 1 Forthcoming in Noûs A Defense of Reductionism about Testimonial Justification of Beliefs TOMOJI SHOGENJI Rhode Island College Abstract This paper defends reductionism about testimonial justification of beliefs against two influential arguments. One is the empirical argument to the effect that the reductionist justification of our trust in testimony is either circular since it relies on testimonial evidence or else there is scarce evidence in support of our trust in testimony. The other is the transcendental argument to the effect that trust in testimony is a prerequisite for the very existence of testimonial evidence since without the presumption of people’s truthfulness we cannot interpret their utterances as testimony with propositional contents. This paper contends that the epistemic subject can interpret utterances as testimony with propositional contents without presupposing the credibility of testimony, and that evidence available to the normal epistemic subject can justify her trust in testimony. I. Introduction There has recently been a considerable interest in anti-reductionism about testimonial justification of beliefs, according to which we cannot justify our trust in testimony by perceptual and memorial evidence.1 The reason for the interest is not the enticement of skepticism. Recent anti-reductionists hold that we are prima facie justified in trusting testimony simply because it is testimony. This means that there is a presumption in favor of testimony that it is credible unless contrary evidence is available. I will use the term “anti-reductionism” to refer to this non-skeptical version of anti-reductionism about testimonial justification. The more traditional position is reductionism, of which the most prominent advocate is David Hume.
    [Show full text]
  • False Dilemma Wikipedia Contents
    False dilemma Wikipedia Contents 1 False dilemma 1 1.1 Examples ............................................... 1 1.1.1 Morton's fork ......................................... 1 1.1.2 False choice .......................................... 2 1.1.3 Black-and-white thinking ................................... 2 1.2 See also ................................................ 2 1.3 References ............................................... 3 1.4 External links ............................................. 3 2 Affirmative action 4 2.1 Origins ................................................. 4 2.2 Women ................................................ 4 2.3 Quotas ................................................. 5 2.4 National approaches .......................................... 5 2.4.1 Africa ............................................ 5 2.4.2 Asia .............................................. 7 2.4.3 Europe ............................................ 8 2.4.4 North America ........................................ 10 2.4.5 Oceania ............................................ 11 2.4.6 South America ........................................ 11 2.5 International organizations ...................................... 11 2.5.1 United Nations ........................................ 12 2.6 Support ................................................ 12 2.6.1 Polls .............................................. 12 2.7 Criticism ............................................... 12 2.7.1 Mismatching ......................................... 13 2.8 See also
    [Show full text]
  • Following the Argument Where It Leads
    Following The Argument Where It Leads Thomas Kelly Princeton University [email protected] Abstract: Throughout the history of western philosophy, the Socratic injunction to ‘follow the argument where it leads’ has exerted a powerful attraction. But what is it, exactly, to follow the argument where it leads? I explore this intellectual ideal and offer a modest proposal as to how we should understand it. On my proposal, following the argument where it leaves involves a kind of modalized reasonableness. I then consider the relationship between the ideal and common sense or 'Moorean' responses to revisionary philosophical theorizing. 1. Introduction Bertrand Russell devoted the thirteenth chapter of his History of Western Philosophy to the thought of St. Thomas Aquinas. He concluded his discussion with a rather unflattering assessment: There is little of the true philosophic spirit in Aquinas. He does not, like the Platonic Socrates, set out to follow wherever the argument may lead. He is not engaged in an inquiry, the result of which it is impossible to know in advance. Before he begins to philosophize, he already knows the truth; it is declared in the Catholic faith. If he can find apparently rational arguments for some parts of the faith, so much the better: If he cannot, he need only fall back on revelation. The finding of arguments for a conclusion given in advance is not philosophy, but special pleading. I cannot, therefore, feel that he deserves to be put on a level with the best philosophers either of Greece or of modern times (1945: 463). The extent to which this is a fair assessment of Aquinas is controversial.1 My purpose in what follows, however, is not to defend Aquinas; nor is it to substantiate the charges that Russell brings against him.
    [Show full text]
  • The Problem of Induction
    The Problem of Induction Gilbert Harman Department of Philosophy, Princeton University Sanjeev R. Kulkarni Department of Electrical Engineering, Princeton University July 19, 2005 The Problem The problem of induction is sometimes motivated via a comparison between rules of induction and rules of deduction. Valid deductive rules are necessarily truth preserving, while inductive rules are not. So, for example, one valid deductive rule might be this: (D) From premises of the form “All F are G” and “a is F ,” the corresponding conclusion of the form “a is G” follows. The rule (D) is illustrated in the following depressing argument: (DA) All people are mortal. I am a person. So, I am mortal. The rule here is “valid” in the sense that there is no possible way in which premises satisfying the rule can be true without the corresponding conclusion also being true. A possible inductive rule might be this: (I) From premises of the form “Many many F s are known to be G,” “There are no known cases of F s that are not G,” and “a is F ,” the corresponding conclusion can be inferred of the form “a is G.” The rule (I) might be illustrated in the following “inductive argument.” (IA) Many many people are known to have been moral. There are no known cases of people who are not mortal. I am a person. So, I am mortal. 1 The rule (I) is not valid in the way that the deductive rule (D) is valid. The “premises” of the inductive inference (IA) could be true even though its “con- clusion” is not true.
    [Show full text]
  • “Forms of Philosophical Skepticism”
    “Forms of Philosophical Skepticism” James Conant Handout of Quotations, Examples, and Other Things I. Russell and the Nomads 1. Bertrand Russell’s Table Any statement as to what it is that our immediate experiences make us know is very likely to be wrong. It seems to me that I am now sitting in a chair, at a table of a certain shape, on which I see sheets of paper with writing or print…. All this seems to be so evident as to be hardly worth stating, except in answer to a man who doubts whether I know anything. Yet all this may be reasonably doubted, and all of it requires much careful discussion before we can be sure that we have stated it in a form that is wholly true. To make our difficulties plain, let us concentrate attention on the table. To the eye it is oblong, brown and shiny, to the touch it is smooth and cool and hard; when I tap it, it gives out a wooden sound…. [Then Russell proceeds to consider each of these qualities of the table.] The shape of the table is no better. … [T]he 'real' shape is not what we see; it is something inferred from what we see. And what we see is constantly changing in shape as we, move about the room; so that here again the senses seem not to give us the truth about the table itself, but only about the appearance of the table. … Thus it becomes evident that the real table, if there is one, is not the same as what we immediately experience by sight or touch or hearing.
    [Show full text]
  • Explorations in Ancient and Modern Philosophy: Volume 1 M
    Cambridge University Press 978-0-521-75072-1 - Explorations in Ancient and Modern Philosophy: Volume 1 M. F. Burnyeat Frontmatter More information EXPLORATIONS IN ANCIENT AND MODERN PHILOSOPHY M. F. Burnyeat taught for fourteen years in the Philosophy Depart- ment of University College London, and then for eighteen years in the Classics Faculty at Cambridge, twelve of them as the Laurence Professor of Ancient Philosophy, before migrating to Oxford in 1996 to become a Senior Research Fellow in Philosophy at All Souls Col- lege. The studies, articles and reviews collected in these two volumes of Explorations in Ancient and Modern Philosophy were all written, and all but two published, before that decisive change. Whether designed for a scholarly audience or for a wider public, they range from the Presocratics to Augustine, from Descartes and Bishop Berkeley to Wittgenstein and G. E. Moore. Their subject- matter falls under four main headings: ‘Logic and Dialectic’, and ‘Scepticism Ancient and Modern’, which are contained in this first volume; ‘Knowledge’ and ‘Philosophy and the Good Life’ make up the second volume. The title ‘Explorations’ well expresses Burnyeat’s ability to discover new aspects of familiar texts, new ways of solving old problems. In his hands the history of philosophy becomes itself a philosophical activity. m. f. burnyeat is an Honorary Fellow of Robinson College, Cambridge, and an Emeritus Fellow of All Souls College, Oxford. He is also a Fellow of the British Academy and a Foreign Honorary Member of the American Academy of Arts and Sciences, and was awarded a CBE for his services to scholarship in 2007.
    [Show full text]
  • Dissoi Logoi: Neosophistic Rhetoric and the Possibility of Critical Pedagogy
    CHAPTER ONE Dissoi Logoi: Neosophistic Rhetoric and the Possibility of Critical Pedagogy Some say that the good is one thing and the bad the other, but others say that they are the same, and that a thing might be good for some persons but bad for oth- ers, or at one time good and at another time bad for the same person. —Sprague (279)1 The title of this chapter is taken directly from an anonymous sophistic treatise called Dissoi Logoi, or Dialexeis, and is traced back to the subsequent end of the Peloponnesian War (Sprague 279). I use this treatise as a convenient means to segue into my discussion of the infusion of sophistic rhetorical practices and the- ory into rhetoric and composition. The anonymous author of this treatise articulates the notion of contradiction as an inevitable consequence of discourse, and such notions of inherent contra- dictions have become standard rhetoric, the accepted a priori assumptions of postmodern discourses—an understanding that 1 2 Emancipatory Movements in Composition truth and knowledge are contingent upon circumstance and lan- guage. “Truth,” Richard Rorty writes, “cannot be out there— cannot exist independently of the human mind—because sen- tences cannot so exist or be out there. The world is out there, but descriptions of the world are not”(5). This chapter will explore how the convergence of sophistic rhetoric with contemporary composition theory helps us to envision an alternate discourse model, based on notions of logos, antilogike, mythos, and ethos. Let me begin with a disclaimer about my employment of sophistic rhetoric as a springboard for discussion about cultural studies, feminism, postcolonial studies, and composition: as Edward Schiappa has pointed out, scholars do not know exactly who the sophists were nor what unified their particular rhetoric as specifically “sophistic” (“Sophistic” 5).
    [Show full text]