3. Strategic Moves 3.1 Gametrees and Subgame Perfection What If

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

3. Strategic Moves 3.1 Gametrees and Subgame Perfection What If R.E.Marks 1998 Lecture 9-1 R.E.Marks 1998 Lecture 9-2 If Alpha preempts Beta, by making its capacity decision before Beta does, then use the game tree: 3. Strategic Moves 3.1 Game Trees and Subgame Perfection Alpha What if one player moves ®rst? Use a game tree, in which the players, their actions, and the timing of their actions are L S DNE explicit. Allow three choices for each of the two players, Alpha and Beta: Do Not Expand (DNE), Small, and Large expansions. Beta Beta Beta The payoff matrix for simultaneous moves is: The Capacity Game L S DNE L S DNE L S DNE Beta DNE Small Large ________________________________ 0 12 18 8 16 20 9 15 18 L L L L 0 8 9 12 16 15 18 20 18 DNE $18, $18 $15, $20 $9, $18 _L_______________________________L L L L L L L Figure 1. Game Tree, Payoffs: Alpha's, Beta's Alpha L L L L Small________________________________ $20, $15 $16, $16 $8, $12 L L L L Use subgame perfect Nash equilibrium, in which L L L L each player chooses the best action for itself at LargeL $18, $9L $12, $8L $0, $0 L _L_______________________________L L L each node it might reach, and assumes similar behaviour on the part of the other. TABLE 1. The payoff matrix (Alpha, Beta) R.E.Marks 1998 Lecture 9-3 R.E.Marks 1998 Lecture 9-4 3.1.1 Backward Induction 3.2 Threats and Credible Threats, or Why Commitment Is Important (See Bierman & Fernandez, Ch. 5) With complete information (all know what each Two ®rms, Able and Baker, are competing in an has done), solve this by backward induction: oligopolistic industry (an industry with few sellers who are engaged in a strategic ªdanceº). 1. From the end (®nal payoffs), go up the tree to the ®rst parent decision nodes. Able, the dominant ®rm, is contemplating its capacity strategy, with two options: 2. Identify the best (i.e. the highest payoff) decision for the deciding player at each node. · ªAggressive,º a large and rapid increase in The choice at each node is part of the player's capacity aimed at increasing its market share, optimal strategy. and 3. ªPruneº all branches from the decision node · ªSoft,º no change in the ®rm's capacity. in 2. Put payoffs at new end = best decision's Baker, a smaller competitor, faces a similar choice. payoffs The table shows the NPV (net present value) 4. Do higher decision nodes remain? associated with each combination of strategies: If ªnoº, then ®nish. 5. If ªyesº, then go to step 1. Baker 6. For each player, the collection of best Aggressive Soft decisions at each decision node of that player ___________________________ → L L L best strategies of that player. Aggressive 12.5, 4.5 16.5, 5 _L__________________________L L Able L L L The simultaneous game (payoff matrix) L L L equilibrium is Alpha: Small; Beta: Small. Soft_L__________________________ 15, 6.5L 18, 6 L The sequential game (game tree) equilibrium is Alpha: Large; Beta: Do Not Expand. TABLE 2. Simultaneous Payoffs (Able, Baker) In the sequential game, Alpha's capacity choice has commitment value: gives Alpha (in this case) ®rst-mover advantage. R.E.Marks 1998 Lecture 9-5 R.E.Marks 1998 Lecture 9-6 There is a unique Nash equilibrium: Able chooses Soft and Baker chooses Aggressive, to give a payoff A to Able of 15. But from Able's point of view, this combination is A S not as good as if both Able and Baker chose Soft → Able's payoff of 18. But without Baker's cooperation, this outcome will B B not be reached. What if Able committed to choose Aggressive whatever Baker chose? If this were credible, A S A S then Baker would choose Soft (for a higher payoff of 5, over 4.5), which in turn would give Able a payoff of 16.5. 12.5 16.5 15 18 4.5 5 6.5 6 How to commit to Aggressive on Able's part? Figure 2. Sequential Payoffs (Able, Baker) It's not enough to announce it or even to promise1 it: not a credible move, since Baker knows that {Able: Aggressive, Baker: Soft} is a subgame Soft is a dominant strategy for Able: no matter perfect Nash equilibrium of the sequential game. what Baker does, Able's payoff is higher if it's Soft. Able may be able to credibly commit by One way is for Able to make a preemptive move, demonstrating that it was rewarding its managers by accelerating its decision process and on market share rather than the NPV pro®t of the aggressively expanding its capacity before Baker payoffs: more pro®table for the managers to go for decides what to do: turns a simultaneous capacity aggressively, even if the company's payoff interaction into a sequential game: appears lower. Paradoxically, Able's position is strengthened if it can reduce its options and tie itself to Aggressive. _________ In¯exibility can have value: strategic 1. Talk is cheap ... because supply exceeds demand. commitments that limit choices can actual improve one's position. R.E.Marks 1998 Lecture 9-7 R.E.Marks 1998 Lecture 9-8 How? 3.2.1 Subgame Perfect Equilibria By altering one's rivals' expectations of about how Nash Equilibria from non-credible threats are poor one will compete, and so altering their decisions. predictors of behaviour. By committing to what seems an inferior decision A subgame: is a smaller game within a larger (Aggression), Able alters Baker's expectations and game with two special properties: its action, to Able's advantage. 1. once players begin playing the subgame, they Commitments must be credible and communicated do so for the rest of the game; and understandable to be of value. 2. the players all know when they are playing · By their nature, strategic commitments the subgame. (threats or promises) are intended to change others' expectations and behaviour; others The subgame's subroot node: the initial node: the must wonder whether the committed player subgame consists of the subroot and all its mightn't fall back on the uncommitted best successors Ð property 1. action: it's nothing but a bluff. If every information set that contains a decision · The movie Dr Strangelove describes a Russian node of the subgame does not contain decision commitment Ð The Doomsday Machine Ð to nodes that are not part of the subgame Ð property respond to any incursion into Soviet airspace 2. with an attack of nuclear missiles on the U.S. The subgame preserves the original game's: Unfortunately, the Russian have overlooked telling the Americans about it ... · set of players, · The rivals' managers must understand the · order of play, implications for their own ®rms' payoffs of · set of possible actions, and Able's ability to price low with its excess capacity. · information sets. To be truly credible, the commitment must be Rational behaviour in the full game should be irreversible: very costly to stop or reverse. rational in the subgame. Non-credible threats are ignored. R.E.Marks 1998 Lecture 9-9 R.E.Marks 1998 Lecture 9-10 Defn: A strategy pro®le is a subgame-perfect 3.2.2 An example: side payments equilibrium2 (SGPE) of a game G if this strategy A sequential game, in which there may be ªside pro®le is also a N.E. for every subgame of G. paymentsº from one player to another: With perfect information (singleton information C sets), the SGPE = those from backwards induction (B.I.). W E B.I. eliminates non-credible threats, so a N.E. ⇔ a SGPE, with perfect information. R R The real power of SGPE occurs when there is not perfect information Ð when players are not always aware of what their opponent did N S N S (modelled by multi-node information sets). So long as there is perfect information, backwards 1,12,±2 ±2,2 0,0 induction results in Nash equilibria that are S.G.P. Side Payments 1 (R,C) The second mover, R, has the following option: · Before his move, he can promise or threaten to reduce his payoff to any positive number or zero by adding the same amount to C's payoff. · This can only happen at one ®nal outcome (only one of NE, NW, SE, or SW). · This is a promise (or threat) of a side payment _________ What would happen without the promise of a side payment? 2. Reinhart Selten received the 1994 Nobel Prize in Economics for his development of this concept. What would happen with such a promise? R.E.Marks 1998 Lecture 9-11 R.E.Marks 1998 Lecture 9-12 3.2.3 Another example: side payments 3.3 A Menu of Strategic Moves A second game tree with side payments possible: 3.3.1 Threats and Promises · An unconditional move may give a strategic C advantage to a player able to seize the initiative and move ®rst. W E · Possible for a second mover to gain similar strategic advantage by commitment to a response rule: ªIf you do/don't act like this, then 4,2 R I'll do/not act like that.º The rule must be in place and clearly communicated beforehand. N S · Two sorts of response rules: threats and promises. 1,1 2,3 · A threat is a response rule that punishes others who fail to cooperate with you. Side Payments 2 (R,C) Ð Compellent threats to induce action (hijacker).
Recommended publications
  • Labsi Working Papers
    UNIVERSITY OF SIENA S.N. O’ H iggins Arturo Palomba Patrizia Sbriglia Second Mover Advantage and Bertrand Dynamic Competition: An Experiment May 2010 LABSI WORKING PAPERS N. 28/2010 SECOND MOVER ADVANTAGE AND BERTRAND DYNAMIC COMPETITION: AN EXPERIMENT § S.N. O’Higgins University of Salerno [email protected] Arturo Palomba University of Naples II [email protected] Patrizia Sbriglia §§ University of Naples II [email protected] Abstract In this paper we provide an experimental test of a dynamic Bertrand duopolistic model, where firms move sequentially and their informational setting varies across different designs. Our experiment is composed of three treatments. In the first treatment, subjects receive information only on the costs and demand parameters and on the price’ choices of their opponent in the market in which they are positioned (matching is fixed); in the second and third treatments, subjects are also informed on the behaviour of players who are not directly operating in their market. Our aim is to study whether the individual behaviour and the process of equilibrium convergence are affected by the specific informational setting adopted. In all treatments we selected students who had previously studied market games and industrial organization, conjecturing that the specific participants’ expertise decreased the chances of imitation in treatment II and III. However, our results prove the opposite: the extra information provided in treatment II and III strongly affects the long run convergence to the market equilibrium. In fact, whilst in the first session, a high proportion of markets converge to the Nash-Bertrand symmetric solution, we observe that a high proportion of markets converge to more collusive outcomes in treatment II and more competitive outcomes in treatment III.
    [Show full text]
  • 1 Sequential Games
    1 Sequential Games We call games where players take turns moving “sequential games”. Sequential games consist of the same elements as normal form games –there are players, rules, outcomes, and payo¤s. However, sequential games have the added element that history of play is now important as players can make decisions conditional on what other players have done. Thus, if two people are playing a game of Chess the second mover is able to observe the …rst mover’s initial move prior to making his initial move. While it is possible to represent sequential games using the strategic (or matrix) form representation of the game it is more instructive at …rst to represent sequential games using a game tree. In addition to the players, actions, outcomes, and payo¤s, the game tree will provide a history of play or a path of play. A very basic example of a sequential game is the Entrant-Incumbent game. The game is described as follows: Consider a game where there is an entrant and an incumbent. The entrant moves …rst and the incumbent observes the entrant’sdecision. The entrant can choose to either enter the market or remain out of the market. If the entrant remains out of the market then the game ends and the entrant receives a payo¤ of 0 while the incumbent receives a payo¤ of 2. If the entrant chooses to enter the market then the incumbent gets to make a choice. The incumbent chooses between …ghting entry or accommodating entry. If the incumbent …ghts the entrant receives a payo¤ of 3 while the incumbent receives a payo¤ of 1.
    [Show full text]
  • Essays on Equilibrium Asset Pricing and Investments
    Institute of Fisher Center for Business and Real Estate and Economic Research Urban Economics PROGRAM ON HOUSING AND URBAN POLICY DISSERTATION AND THESIS SERIES DISSERTATION NO. D07-001 ESSAYS ON EQUILIBRIUM ASSET PRICING AND INVESTMENTS By Jiro Yoshida Spring 2007 These papers are preliminary in nature: their purpose is to stimulate discussion and comment. Therefore, they are not to be cited or quoted in any publication without the express permission of the author. UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA, BERKELEY Essays on Equilibrium Asset Pricing and Investments by Jiro Yoshida B.Eng. (The University of Tokyo) 1992 M.S. (Massachusetts Institute of Technology) 1999 M.S. (University of California, Berkeley) 2005 A dissertation submitted in partial satisfaction of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in Business Administration in the GRADUATE DIVISION of the UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA, BERKELEY Committee in charge: Professor John Quigley, Chair Professor Dwight Ja¤ee Professor Richard Stanton Professor Adam Szeidl Spring 2007 The dissertation of Jiro Yoshida is approved: Chair Date Date Date Date University of California, Berkeley Spring 2007 Essays on Equilibrium Asset Pricing and Investments Copyright 2007 by Jiro Yoshida 1 Abstract Essays on Equilibrium Asset Pricing and Investments by Jiro Yoshida Doctor of Philosophy in Business Administration University of California, Berkeley Professor John Quigley, Chair Asset prices have tremendous impacts on economic decision-making. While substantial progress has been made in research on …nancial asset prices, we have a quite limited un- derstanding of the equilibrium prices of broader asset classes. This dissertation contributes to the understanding of properties of asset prices for broad asset classes, with particular attention on asset supply.
    [Show full text]
  • Finitely Repeated Games
    Repeated games 1: Finite repetition Universidad Carlos III de Madrid 1 Finitely repeated games • A finitely repeated game is a dynamic game in which a simultaneous game (the stage game) is played finitely many times, and the result of each stage is observed before the next one is played. • Example: Play the prisoners’ dilemma several times. The stage game is the simultaneous prisoners’ dilemma game. 2 Results • If the stage game (the simultaneous game) has only one NE the repeated game has only one SPNE: In the SPNE players’ play the strategies in the NE in each stage. • If the stage game has 2 or more NE, one can find a SPNE where, at some stage, players play a strategy that is not part of a NE of the stage game. 3 The prisoners’ dilemma repeated twice • Two players play the same simultaneous game twice, at ! = 1 and at ! = 2. • After the first time the game is played (after ! = 1) the result is observed before playing the second time. • The payoff in the repeated game is the sum of the payoffs in each stage (! = 1, ! = 2) • Which is the SPNE? Player 2 D C D 1 , 1 5 , 0 Player 1 C 0 , 5 4 , 4 4 The prisoners’ dilemma repeated twice Information sets? Strategies? 1 .1 5 for each player 2" for each player D C E.g.: (C, D, D, C, C) Subgames? 2.1 5 D C D C .2 1.3 1.5 1 1.4 D C D C D C D C 2.2 2.3 2 .4 2.5 D C D C D C D C D C D C D C D C 1+1 1+5 1+0 1+4 5+1 5+5 5+0 5+4 0+1 0+5 0+0 0+4 4+1 4+5 4+0 4+4 1+1 1+0 1+5 1+4 0+1 0+0 0+5 0+4 5+1 5+0 5+5 5+4 4+1 4+0 4+5 4+4 The prisoners’ dilemma repeated twice Let’s find the NE in the subgames.
    [Show full text]
  • Experimental Game Theory and Its Application in Sociology and Political Science
    Journal of Applied Mathematics Experimental Game Theory and Its Application in Sociology and Political Science Guest Editors: Arthur Schram, Vincent Buskens, Klarita Gërxhani, and Jens Großer Experimental Game Theory and Its Application in Sociology and Political Science Journal of Applied Mathematics Experimental Game Theory and Its Application in Sociology and Political Science Guest Editors: Arthur Schram, Vincent Buskens, Klarita Gërxhani, and Jens Großer Copyright © òýÔ Hindawi Publishing Corporation. All rights reserved. is is a special issue published in “Journal of Applied Mathematics.” All articles are open access articles distributed under the Creative Commons Attribution License, which permits unrestricted use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original work is properly cited. Editorial Board Saeid Abbasbandy, Iran Song Cen, China Urmila Diwekar, USA Mina B. Abd-El-Malek, Egypt Tai-Ping Chang, Taiwan Vit Dolejsi, Czech Republic Mohamed A. Abdou, Egypt Shih-sen Chang, China BoQing Dong, China Subhas Abel, India Wei-Der Chang, Taiwan Rodrigo W. dos Santos, Brazil Janos Abonyi, Hungary Shuenn-Yih Chang, Taiwan Wenbin Dou, China Sergei Alexandrov, Russia Kripasindhu Chaudhuri, India Rafael Escarela-Perez, Mexico M. Montaz Ali, South Africa Yuming Chen, Canada Magdy A. Ezzat, Egypt Mohammad R, Aliha, Iran Jianbing Chen, China Meng Fan, China Carlos J. S. Alves, Portugal Xinkai Chen, Japan Ya Ping Fang, China Mohamad Alwash, USA Rushan Chen, China István Faragó, Hungary Gholam R. Amin, Oman Ke Chen, UK Didier Felbacq, France Igor Andrianov, Germany Zhang Chen, China Ricardo Femat, Mexico Boris Andrievsky, Russia Zhi-Zhong Chen, Japan Antonio J. M. Ferreira, Portugal Whye-Teong Ang, Singapore Ru-Dong Chen, China George Fikioris, Greece Abul-Fazal M.
    [Show full text]
  • Chapter 16 Oligopoly and Game Theory Oligopoly Oligopoly
    Chapter 16 “Game theory is the study of how people Oligopoly behave in strategic situations. By ‘strategic’ we mean a situation in which each person, when deciding what actions to take, must and consider how others might respond to that action.” Game Theory Oligopoly Oligopoly • “Oligopoly is a market structure in which only a few • “Figuring out the environment” when there are sellers offer similar or identical products.” rival firms in your market, means guessing (or • As we saw last time, oligopoly differs from the two ‘ideal’ inferring) what the rivals are doing and then cases, perfect competition and monopoly. choosing a “best response” • In the ‘ideal’ cases, the firm just has to figure out the environment (prices for the perfectly competitive firm, • This means that firms in oligopoly markets are demand curve for the monopolist) and select output to playing a ‘game’ against each other. maximize profits • To understand how they might act, we need to • An oligopolist, on the other hand, also has to figure out the understand how players play games. environment before computing the best output. • This is the role of Game Theory. Some Concepts We Will Use Strategies • Strategies • Strategies are the choices that a player is allowed • Payoffs to make. • Sequential Games •Examples: • Simultaneous Games – In game trees (sequential games), the players choose paths or branches from roots or nodes. • Best Responses – In matrix games players choose rows or columns • Equilibrium – In market games, players choose prices, or quantities, • Dominated strategies or R and D levels. • Dominant Strategies. – In Blackjack, players choose whether to stay or draw.
    [Show full text]
  • Coalitional Stochastic Stability in Games, Networks and Markets
    Coalitional stochastic stability in games, networks and markets Ryoji Sawa∗ Department of Economics, University of Wisconsin-Madison November 24, 2011 Abstract This paper examines a dynamic process of unilateral and joint deviations of agents and the resulting stochastic evolution of social conventions in a class of interactions that includes normal form games, network formation games, and simple exchange economies. Over time agents unilater- ally and jointly revise their strategies based on the improvements that the new strategy profile offers them. In addition to the optimization process, there are persistent random shocks on agents utility that potentially lead to switching to suboptimal strategies. Under a logit specification of choice prob- abilities, we characterize the set of states that will be observed in the long-run as noise vanishes. We apply these results to examples including certain potential games and network formation games, as well as to the formation of free trade agreements across countries. Keywords: Logit-response dynamics; Coalitions; Stochastic stability; Network formation. JEL Classification Numbers: C72, C73. ∗Address: 1180 Observatory Drive, Madison, WI 53706-1393, United States., telephone: 1-608-262-0200, e-mail: [email protected]. The author is grateful to William Sandholm, Marzena Rostek and Marek Weretka for their advice and sugges- tions. The author also thanks seminar participants at University of Wisconsin-Madison for their comments and suggestions. 1 1 Introduction Our economic and social life is often conducted within a group of agents, such as people, firms or countries. For example, firms may form an R & D alliances and found a joint research venture rather than independently conducting R & D.
    [Show full text]
  • Econstor Wirtschaft Leibniz Information Centre Make Your Publications Visible
    A Service of Leibniz-Informationszentrum econstor Wirtschaft Leibniz Information Centre Make Your Publications Visible. zbw for Economics Stör, Lorenz Working Paper Conceptualizing power in the context of climate change: A multi-theoretical perspective on structure, agency & power relations VÖÖ Discussion Paper, No. 5/2017 Provided in Cooperation with: Vereinigung für Ökologische Ökonomie e.V. (VÖÖ), Heidelberg Suggested Citation: Stör, Lorenz (2017) : Conceptualizing power in the context of climate change: A multi-theoretical perspective on structure, agency & power relations, VÖÖ Discussion Paper, No. 5/2017, Vereinigung für Ökologische Ökonomie (VÖÖ), Heidelberg This Version is available at: http://hdl.handle.net/10419/150540 Standard-Nutzungsbedingungen: Terms of use: Die Dokumente auf EconStor dürfen zu eigenen wissenschaftlichen Documents in EconStor may be saved and copied for your Zwecken und zum Privatgebrauch gespeichert und kopiert werden. personal and scholarly purposes. Sie dürfen die Dokumente nicht für öffentliche oder kommerzielle You are not to copy documents for public or commercial Zwecke vervielfältigen, öffentlich ausstellen, öffentlich zugänglich purposes, to exhibit the documents publicly, to make them machen, vertreiben oder anderweitig nutzen. publicly available on the internet, or to distribute or otherwise use the documents in public. Sofern die Verfasser die Dokumente unter Open-Content-Lizenzen (insbesondere CC-Lizenzen) zur Verfügung gestellt haben sollten, If the documents have been made available under an Open gelten abweichend von diesen Nutzungsbedingungen die in der dort Content Licence (especially Creative Commons Licences), you genannten Lizenz gewährten Nutzungsrechte. may exercise further usage rights as specified in the indicated licence. https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-nd/4.0/ www.econstor.eu VÖÖ Discussion Papers VÖÖ Discussion Papers · ISSN 2366-7753 No.
    [Show full text]
  • Cooperation Spillovers in Coordination Games*
    Cooperation Spillovers in Coordination Games* Timothy N. Casona, Anya Savikhina, and Roman M. Sheremetab aDepartment of Economics, Krannert School of Management, Purdue University, 403 W. State St., West Lafayette, IN 47906-2056, U.S.A. bArgyros School of Business and Economics, Chapman University, One University Drive, Orange, CA 92866, U.S.A. November 2009 Abstract Motivated by problems of coordination failure observed in weak-link games, we experimentally investigate behavioral spillovers for order-statistic coordination games. Subjects play the minimum- and median-effort coordination games simultaneously and sequentially. The results show the precedent for cooperative behavior spills over from the median game to the minimum game when the games are played sequentially. Moreover, spillover occurs even when group composition changes, although the effect is not as strong. We also find that the precedent for uncooperative behavior does not spill over from the minimum game to the median game. These findings suggest guidelines for increasing cooperative behavior within organizations. JEL Classifications: C72, C91 Keywords: coordination, order-statistic games, experiments, cooperation, minimum game, behavioral spillover Corresponding author: Timothy Cason, [email protected] * We thank Yan Chen, David Cooper, John Duffy, Vai-Lam Mui, seminar participants at Purdue University, and participants at Economic Science Association conferences for helpful comments. Any remaining errors are ours. 1. Introduction Coordination failure is often the reason for the inefficient performance of many groups, ranging from small firms to entire economies. When agents’ actions have strategic interdependence, even when they succeed in coordinating they may be “trapped” in an equilibrium that is objectively inferior to other equilibria. Coordination failure and inefficient coordination has been an important theme across a variety of fields in economics, ranging from development and macroeconomics to mechanism design for overcoming moral hazard in teams.
    [Show full text]
  • 570: Minimax Sample Complexity for Turn-Based Stochastic Game
    Minimax Sample Complexity for Turn-based Stochastic Game Qiwen Cui1 Lin F. Yang2 1School of Mathematical Sciences, Peking University 2Electrical and Computer Engineering Department, University of California, Los Angeles Abstract guarantees are rather rare due to complex interaction be- tween agents that makes the problem considerably harder than single agent reinforcement learning. This is also known The empirical success of multi-agent reinforce- as non-stationarity in MARL, which means when multi- ment learning is encouraging, while few theoret- ple agents alter their strategies based on samples collected ical guarantees have been revealed. In this work, from previous strategy, the system becomes non-stationary we prove that the plug-in solver approach, proba- for each agent and the improvement can not be guaranteed. bly the most natural reinforcement learning algo- One fundamental question in MBRL is that how to design rithm, achieves minimax sample complexity for efficient algorithms to overcome non-stationarity. turn-based stochastic game (TBSG). Specifically, we perform planning in an empirical TBSG by Two-players turn-based stochastic game (TBSG) is a two- utilizing a ‘simulator’ that allows sampling from agents generalization of Markov decision process (MDP), arbitrary state-action pair. We show that the em- where two agents choose actions in turn and one agent wants pirical Nash equilibrium strategy is an approxi- to maximize the total reward while the other wants to min- mate Nash equilibrium strategy in the true TBSG imize it. As a zero-sum game, TBSG is known to have and give both problem-dependent and problem- Nash equilibrium strategy [Shapley, 1953], which means independent bound.
    [Show full text]
  • Formation of Coalition Structures As a Non-Cooperative Game
    Formation of coalition structures as a non-cooperative game Dmitry Levando, ∗ Abstract We study coalition structure formation with intra and inter-coalition externalities in the introduced family of nested non-cooperative si- multaneous finite games. A non-cooperative game embeds a coalition structure formation mechanism, and has two outcomes: an alloca- tion of players over coalitions and a payoff for every player. Coalition structures of a game are described by Young diagrams. They serve to enumerate coalition structures and allocations of players over them. For every coalition structure a player has a set of finite strategies. A player chooses a coalition structure and a strategy. A (social) mechanism eliminates conflicts in individual choices and produces final coalition structures. Every final coalition structure is a non-cooperative game. Mixed equilibrium always exists and consists arXiv:2107.00711v1 [cs.GT] 1 Jul 2021 of a mixed strategy profile, payoffs and equilibrium coalition struc- tures. We use a maximum coalition size to parametrize the family ∗Moscow, Russian Federation, independent. No funds, grants, or other support was received. Acknowledge: Nick Baigent, Phillip Bich, Giulio Codognato, Ludovic Julien, Izhak Gilboa, Olga Gorelkina, Mark Kelbert, Anton Komarov, Roger Myerson, Ariel Rubinstein, Shmuel Zamir. Many thanks for advices and for discussion to participants of SIGE-2015, 2016 (an earlier version of the title was “A generalized Nash equilibrium”), CORE 50 Conference, Workshop of the Central European Program in Economic Theory, Udine (2016), Games 2016 Congress, Games and Applications, (2016) Lisbon, Games and Optimization at St Etienne (2016). All possible mistakes are only mine. E-mail for correspondence: dlevando (at) hotmail.ru.
    [Show full text]
  • Finding Strategic Game Equivalent of an Extensive Form Game
    Finding Strategic Game Equivalent of an Extensive Form Game • In an extensive form game, a strategy for a player should specify what action the player will choose at each information set. That is, a strategy is a complete plan for playing a game for a particular player. • Therefore to find the strategic game equivalent of an extensive form game we should follow these steps: 1. First we need to find all strategies for every player. To do that first we find all information sets for every player (including the singleton information sets). If there are many of them we may label them (such as Player 1’s 1st info. set, Player 1’s 2nd info. set, etc.) 2. A strategy should specify what action the player will take in every information set which belongs to him/her. We find all combinations of actions the player can take at these information sets. For example if a player has 3 information sets where • the first one has 2 actions, • the second one has 2 actions, and • the third one has 3 actions then there will be a total of 2 × 2 × 3 = 12 strategies for this player. 3. Once the strategies are obtained for every player the next step is finding the payoffs. For every strategy profile we find the payoff vector that would be obtained in case these strategies are played in the extensive form game. Example: Let’s find the strategic game equivalent of the following 3-level centipede game. (3,1)r (2,3)r (6,2)r (4,6)r (12,4)r (8,12)r S S S S S S r 1 2 1 2 1 2 (24,8) C C C C C C 1.
    [Show full text]