Hobbes's Constitutional Theory-Dyzenhaus.Pdf

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Hobbes's Constitutional Theory-Dyzenhaus.Pdf EDITORIAL Leviathan COMMITTEE FOR Rethinking Or The Matter, Forme, the & Power of a Common- Western Tradition Wealth Ecclesiasticall David Bromwich Yale University and Civill Gerald Graff University of Illinois at Chicago Geoffrey Hartman Yale University Samuel Lipman (deceased) THOMAS HOBBES The New Criterion Gary Saul Morson Northwestern University Edited and with an Introduction J aroslav Pelikan by Ian Shapiro (deceased) Yale University with essays by Marjorie Perloff John Dunn Stanford University David Dyzenhaus Richard Rorty Stanford University Elisabeth Ellis Alan Ryan Bryan Garsten New College, Oxford Ian Shapiro Yale University Yale Frank M. Turner UNIVERSITY Yale University Allen W. Wood PRESS Stanford University New Haven and London Contributors Published with assistance from the Louis Stern Memorial Fund. John Dunn is Fellow of King's College and Professor of Political Theory at the University of Cambridge. Copyright© 2010 by Yale University. All rights reserved. David Dyzenhaus is Professor of Law and Philosophy at the University of This book may not be reproduced, in whole or in part, Toronto. including illustrations, in any form (beyond that Elisabeth Ellis is Associate Professor of Political Science at Texas A&M copying permitted by Sections 107 and 108 of the U.S. University. Copyright Law and except by reviewers for the public press), without written permission from the publishers. Bryan Garsten is Associate Professor of Political Science at Yale University. Yale University Press books may be purchased in quantity for educational, Ian Shapiro is Sterling Professor of Political Science and Henry R. Luce business, or promotional use. For information, please Director of the MacMillan Center for International and Area Studies at Yale e-mail [email protected]. University. Printed in the United States of America. ISBN: 978-0-300- I 1838-4 (pbk.) Library of Congress Control Number: 2009938243 A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library. This paper meets the requirements of ANSI/NISO Z39-48-1992 (Permanence of Paper). 452 John Dunn 31. Richard Tuck, "Hobbes and Locke on Toleration," in ed. Mary Dietz, HOBBES'S CONSTITUTIONAL THEORY Thomas Hobbes and Political Theory (Kansas: University of Kansas Press, 1990), pp. 153-7!. 32. Dunn, The History, chap. 4· DAVID DYZENHAUS 33. John Dunn, ed., The Economic Limits to Modern Politics (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1990); Albert Hirschman, The Passions and the Interests (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1977); eds. Istvan Hont and Michael Ignatieff, Wealth and Virtue (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1983); and Istvan Hont, Jealousy ofTrade (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 2005). Hobbes's Leviathan is a wonderfully written, complex argument about how 34· Dunn, The Cunning. to design an enduring political order. It was first published during the "Engagement Controversy" following the English Civil War, when the parliamentary victors caused a crisis of conscience for the losing side ­ including Hobbes, an avowed royalist- by requiring a public promise of allegiance to their new government. We can therefore read the book as an extended justification for such "engagement." 1 Hobbes's arguments remain relevant to us today, because they are perennially relevant: people will always wonder about the relationship between power and authority, about the question, "What can make the exercise of political power authoritative such that I should obey its dictates, even when their content seems to me to be incorrect?" Hobbes's radical answer to this question is that subjects are obliged to obey whatever sovereign power rules over them (whether democratic a - sembly, aristocracy, or monarch) so long as that power can provide th em with "Protection."2 Exactly what he means, I will argue, can be understood only through a close examination of Leviathan's somewhat neglected di s­ cussions of law and legal theory. There Hobbes explains how the relation­ ship between sovereign and subject is mediated by law and law, in his view, has two parts. First, there is the extensive set of natural, unwritten laws that he claims are obligatory even in the state of nature,3 and which are al­ together obligatory in civil society. Second, he maintains that sovereign commands constitute a set of civil or enacted laws that subjects are also obliged to obey. Hobbes claims that these two kinds of law "contain each other, and arc of equall extent." 4 However, the fact that the sovereign seems to ha ve authority to enact whatever law he pleases creates the possibility of a clash between obligations in cases where the sovereign enacts a law that contra­ dicts a precept of the law of nature. Modem commentators on Leviathan have by and large insi sted on the civil law's supremacy, a trend exemplified by eminent Hobbes scholar 454 David Dyzenhaus Hobbes's Constitutional Theory 455 Quentin Skinner and his influential school. Skinner insists that classics of uals, now subjects, have duties to the sovereign but no rights against him. political theory have to be understood in their own immediate context, if we Only in the limiting case, when the sovereign actually threatens the con­ want to avoid anachronistically foisting our questions on theirs.5 In part, tinued survival of a particular individual, does that subject cease as a matter this is because he holds that the arguments of the classics have to be inter­ of IUs or her right to self-preservation to owe the sovereign obedience. preted in the light of the understandings of the audience of the particular Skinner and these phllosophers share not only a similar interpretation of author. That audience, familiar with the political controversies of the day Leviathan, but a similar disregard for significant chunks of the text which and with the tropes and nuances of political discourse of its time, is an support what we might think of as a natural law reading of Hobbes, one invaluable interpretive resource. To understand a classic of political thought which says that one's obligation to the sovereign is based not on his power is an exercise in careful reading of the text, situated firmly in its context. On but on his compliance with the laws of nature. Notably, Hobbism cannot this basis, Skinner concludes that Hobbes is best interpreted as sharing the easily account for Hobbes's lengthy discussion of natural law in chapter rs, views of those contemporary "Hobbists" who either associated themselves nor for much of his discussion of civil law and the role of judges in inter­ or were associated with his works. We should read Hobbes, that is, as preting the law, both natural and civil, in chapter 26. In addition, these someone whose reduction of morality to self-interest and belief in human­ chapters resonate with extensive and emphatic statements in other chapters ity's fundamentally anti-social nature leads him to argue that we are under a which clearly support a natural law reading. virtually unconditional obligation to obey our sqvereign- the person or To the extent that philosophers who support Hobbisll} do look at what body who has a monopoly of political power. Legitimacy flows thus from Hobbes actually says in these discussions, their allegiance to Hobbism facts about power-a de facto sovereign is by definition a de iure sov­ forces them to resolve any textual difficulties in ways that seem to strain ereign. Generally speaking, Skinner concerns himself with Hobbes's laws Hobbes's claims. For example, on Hobbes's list of the "Immutable and of nature only to explain how it is that a subject might irrevocably assume Eternall" 10 laws of nature is law 15-that safe conduct must be given to the obligation to obey almost any sovereign command.6 mediators, people who are appointed to bring about peace by mediating The Hobbist interpretation has of course much textual support in Levia­ between the antagonists. 11 If the civil law is simply the commands of the than. Hobbes often argues that since any order is better than the misery of sovereign whom one is under (by definition) a prior obligation to obey, and the state of nature, it is rational to give one's obedience to one's sovereign, the sovereign commands that all mediators be executed on sight, it follows as long as he is in fact providing one with the kind of protection - enforce­ from Hobbism that one is under an obligation to kill mediators, despite able laws that safeguard one's survival- so manifestly absent in the state of one's knowledge of the laws of nature, a knowledge in which, Hobbes nature.? Hobbes knows that some will object that it is odd that his argument argues, a sovereign is under a duty to instruct his subjects. 12 Indeed, it delivers us from the state of nature into the hands of someone who has the seems to follow that the command, "kill all mediators," is the correct discretion to act as a tyrant, that is, "that the Condition of Subjects is very interpretation of Hobbes's claim that the law of nature requires safe conduct miserable; as being obnoxious to the lusts, and other irregular passions of for mediators, because subjects must assume that their access to the laws of him, or them that have so unlimited a Power in their hands." His answer nature is through the content of the sovereign's enactments.13 seems to be that those who have understood the horrors of the state of nature This result is not only odd but it reduces the complexity of Hobbes's or of civil war, will know that order-any order - is better than chaos, as argument to something so crude that one might wonder why Leviathan is long as they are equipped by "Morall and Civill Science" (the lesson of regarded as a classic.
Recommended publications
  • Hobbes and Vattel in Crimea: a Natural Law Critique of the Russian Annexation Juan Martir Xavier University
    Xavier Journal of Undergraduate Research Volume 2 Article 6 2014 Hobbes and Vattel in Crimea: A Natural Law Critique of the Russian Annexation Juan Martir Xavier University Follow this and additional works at: https://www.exhibit.xavier.edu/xjur Recommended Citation Martir, Juan (2014) "Hobbes and Vattel in Crimea: A Natural Law Critique of the Russian Annexation," Xavier Journal of Undergraduate Research: Vol. 2 , Article 6. Available at: https://www.exhibit.xavier.edu/xjur/vol2/iss1/6 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by Exhibit. It has been accepted for inclusion in Xavier Journal of Undergraduate Research by an authorized editor of Exhibit. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Hobbes and Vattel in Crimea: A Natural Law Critique of the Russian Annexation Juan Martir In March 2014, the Russian government—upon learning the people of Crimea voted overwhelmingly by a referendum to secede from Ukraine—announced that it would annex the territory. The international community was shocked. United States Secretary of State John Kerry condemned the move as a revival of outmoded power politics: “You don’t just in the 21st century behave in 19th century fashion by invading another country on a completely trumped-up pretext.”1 This paper argues that, even by earlier standards in international politics, this move by Russia would be considered illegitimate or imprudent. By looking at the incident through the natural law theories of Thomas Hobbes and Emer de Vattel, the annexation would be considered imprudent: by the former because it threatens domestic harmony and is completely illegitimate, and by the latter because it is a blatant violation of the rights of the Ukrainian polity.
    [Show full text]
  • The Reception of Hobbes's Leviathan
    This is a repository copy of The reception of Hobbes's Leviathan. White Rose Research Online URL for this paper: https://eprints.whiterose.ac.uk/71534/ Version: Published Version Book Section: Parkin, Jon (2007) The reception of Hobbes's Leviathan. In: Springborg, Patricia, (ed.) The Cambridge Companion to Hobbes's Leviathan. The Cambridge Companions to Philosophy, Religion and Culture . Cambridge University Press , Cambridge , pp. 441-459. https://doi.org/10.1017/CCOL0521836670.020 Reuse Items deposited in White Rose Research Online are protected by copyright, with all rights reserved unless indicated otherwise. They may be downloaded and/or printed for private study, or other acts as permitted by national copyright laws. The publisher or other rights holders may allow further reproduction and re-use of the full text version. This is indicated by the licence information on the White Rose Research Online record for the item. Takedown If you consider content in White Rose Research Online to be in breach of UK law, please notify us by emailing [email protected] including the URL of the record and the reason for the withdrawal request. [email protected] https://eprints.whiterose.ac.uk/ jon parkin 19 The Reception of Hobbes’s Leviathan The traditional story about the reception of Leviathan was that it was a book that was rejected rather than read seriously.1 Leviathan’s perverse amalgamation of controversial doctrine, so the story goes, earned it universal condemnation. Hobbes was outed as an athe- ist and discredited almost as soon as the work appeared. Subsequent criticism was seen to be the idle pursuit of a discredited text, an exer- cise upon which young militant churchmen could cut their teeth, as William Warburton observed in the eighteenth century.2 We need to be aware, however, that this was a story that was largely the cre- ation of Hobbes’s intellectual opponents, writers with an interest in sidelining Leviathan from the mainstream of the history of ideas.
    [Show full text]
  • Hobbes' Leviathan. the Irresistible Power of a Mortal
    Gabriel L. Negretto * Hobbes’ Leviathan. The Irresistible Power of a Mortal God No one on earth is his equal a creature without fear. He looks down on the highest. He is king over all proud beasts. Job. 41, 24 0. Introduction In different and complex ways, the philosophy and science of the XVII cen- tury moved away from the recognition of a divine authority in the interpretation of human events to an exclusively naturalistic account of this world. Hobbes has been widely regarded as the most representative figure of this process. At a time where religious beliefs were considered to be the prime motive of human behav- ior, Hobbes’ mature work, the Leviathan, depicted men as egoistic calculators whose overriding concern was the pursuit of private advantage. Following this premise, Hobbes rejected the idea that politics is subordinated to the attainment of the ultimate good in spiritual life and proposed that the supreme authority in this world is a secular state whose sole end is the protection of physical life. In this vein, traditional interpreters have maintained that although half of the Levia- than is devoted to theological arguments, theology is either irrelevant or plays a secondary role for its central naturalistic arguments. I will argue, against the traditional interpretation, that theological arguments are crucial to understand Hobbes’ views on the foundations of political obligation and state authority. While rejecting the idea that Hobbes was essentially a moral- ist or a thinker deeply influenced by religion, I wish to propose that he used the scriptures and religion as part of a strategy of persuasion aimed at creating a sta- ble political authority in a world were religious beliefs were still important com- ponents of human action.
    [Show full text]
  • Separation of Powers in Thought and Practice?
    SEPARATION OF POWERS IN THOUGHT AND PRACTICE? Jeremy Waldron * Abstract: The rationale of the separation of powers is often elided with the rationale of checks and balances and with the rationale of the disper- sal of power generally in a constitutional system. This Essay, however, fo- cuses resolutely on the functional separation of powers in what M.J.C. Vile called its “pure form.” Reexamining the theories of Locke, Montesquieu, and Madison, this Essay seeks to recover (amidst all their tautologies and evasions) a genuine case in favor of this principle. The Essay argues that the rationale of the separation of powers is closely related to that of the rule of law: it is partly a matter of the distinct integrity of each of the sepa- rated institutions—judiciary, legislature, and administration. But above all, it is a matter of articulated governance (as contrasted with com- pressed undifferentiated exercises of power). Introduction My topic is the separation of powers, conceived as a political prin- ciple for evaluating the legal and constitutional arrangements of a modern state. What is this principle and why is it important? The ques- tion takes us in interesting directions if we distinguish the separation of powers from two other important principles that are commonly associ- ated, if not identified with it. These other principles are, first , the prin- ciple of the division of power—counseling us to avoid excessive concen- trations of political power in the hands of any one person, group, or agency; and, second, the principle of checks and balances—holding that the exercise of power by any one power-holder needs to be balanced and checked by the exercise of power by other power-holders.
    [Show full text]
  • Hobbes, Aristotle, and Human Happiness
    Hobbes, Aristotle, and Human Happiness During his life in philosophy Thomas Hobbes engaged in several debates. Among his sparring partners the dearest to him was not a contemporary (such as Descartes, White, Bramhall, or Wallis) but Aristotle. This article explores the tension between Hobbes and Aristotle as it appears in metaphysics (including the study of nature), ethics (including psychology), and politics. The article will close with a comparison of their conceptions of human happiness. First impressions would suggest that Hobbes’s ridicule of Aristotle is thoroughly intended and his appreciation of the Philosopher sensationally low: And I beleeve that scarce any thing can be more absurdly said in natural Philosophy, than that which now is called Aristotles Metaphysics; nor more repugnant to Government, than much of that hee hath said in his Politiques; nor more ignorantly, than a great part of his Ethiques.1 Hobbes’s phrasing is certainly impressive, but if the claims he makes are left unspecified, they remain merely words. Having said that, when explicating Hobbes’s position toward Aristotle and Aristotelianism two issues must be taken into consideration: the exact target and the exact content of Hobbes’s criticism.2 The interrelations between Hobbes and Aristotle and Hobbes and Aristotelianism have been studied at great length and in detail.3 To summarise the major conclusion in Hobbes’s own words: vain-philosophy or spiritual darkness derive “partly from Aristotle, partly from Blindnesse of understanding”.4 It is fairly clear that Hobbes’s primary target is a combination of selected Aristotelian doctrines and their adaptation to the Catholic dogma, or, to follow his own coinage, “Aristotelity”.5 To be content with this, I think, is to overlook the nuances of Hobbes’s position.
    [Show full text]
  • Thomas Hobbes's "Leviathan": a Study in Interpretation
    University of Montana ScholarWorks at University of Montana Graduate Student Theses, Dissertations, & Professional Papers Graduate School 1962 Thomas Hobbes's "Leviathan": A study in interpretation John Anthony Long The University of Montana Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarworks.umt.edu/etd Let us know how access to this document benefits ou.y Recommended Citation Long, John Anthony, "Thomas Hobbes's "Leviathan": A study in interpretation" (1962). Graduate Student Theses, Dissertations, & Professional Papers. 5590. https://scholarworks.umt.edu/etd/5590 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Graduate School at ScholarWorks at University of Montana. It has been accepted for inclusion in Graduate Student Theses, Dissertations, & Professional Papers by an authorized administrator of ScholarWorks at University of Montana. For more information, please contact [email protected]. THOMAS HOBBES*S LEVIATHAN: A STUDY IN INTERPRETATION by JOHN ANTHONY LONG B*A., Montana State University, 1961 Presented in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Master of Arts MONTANA STATE UNIVERSITY 1962 Approved by: hairman, Board of Examiners Dean, Graduate School SEP 1 8 1962 Date UMI Number: EP41054 All rights reserved INFORMATION TO ALL USERS The quality of this reproduction is dependent upon the quality of the copy submitted. In the unlikely event that the author did not send a complete manuscript and there are missing pages, these will be noted. Also, if material had to be removed, a note will indicate the deletion. Dissertation Publishing UMI EP41054 Published by ProQuest LLC (2014). Copyright in the Dissertation held by the Author.
    [Show full text]
  • "Leviathan"? He Wanted an Image of Strength and Power to Stand Metaphorically for the Commonwealth and Its Sovereign
    Leviathan as Metaphor SAMUELI. MINTZ Why did Hobbes name his masterpiece "Leviathan"? He wanted an image of strength and power to stand metaphorically for the commonwealth and its sovereign. So much is clear. Nevertheless the title seems odd. Why didn't he call the book by its subtitle, "The Matter, Forme and Power of a Common- wealth" ? This subtitle, precise and denotative, like a description in a book catalogue, would have been a title in the hands of almost any other political philosopher of the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries. We think of Bodin's Six Books of the Republic, of Locke's Two Treatises of Government. Doubt- less there were exceptions: Harrington's Common-Wealth of Oceana is one; but Harrington belongs also to the genre of utopian romance. It is Hobbes who stamped his book with the name of a myth, rich in traditional associa- tions ; also, in a sense I hope to make clear, it is a 'poetic' name; and, what no one can dispute, it is memorable. Leviathan was the great sea-beast of the Book of Job whom only God could tame and whose power was contrasted by God with Job's weakness. In Isaiah 27 : 1, Leviathan is referred to as "the piercing serpent," "that crooked serpent... and dragon in the sea" who is dispatched by God's mighty sword. Hobbes chose the Jobian Leviathan, an image of neutral or benign power, over the figure of evil in Isaiah. The two Biblical Leviathans, from Job and from Isaiah, became objects of mythical accretion, interpretation, and etymological speculation in a long tradition.
    [Show full text]
  • Phil 452B/652B Spring 2013 History of Early Modern Ethics W 1:30-3:20 Pm Stephen Darwall 306 CH Th 2-4Pm and by Appt [email protected]
    Phil 452b/652b Spring 2013 History of Early Modern Ethics W 1:30-3:20 pm Stephen Darwall 306 CH Th 2-4pm and by appt [email protected] Hobbes’s Leviathan (1651) shook ethics’ traditional foundations and forced those who would defend morality against what they saw to be Hobbes’ nihilism to do so in a framework that, like Hobbes’s, took seriously the emerging worldview of modern science. Thus began a period of exciting and fruitful moral philosophy that stretched through the end of the eighteenth century and into the nineteenth. Indeed, debates now current in moral philosophy almost always can be traced back to origins during this period. This course will be a study of several of the central writers and texts of this “enlightenment” and post-enlightenment period. In addition to Hobbes, we shall read Hutcheson, Butler, Hume, Kant, Bentham, and Adam Smith, and end with a radical critic of this broad tradition: Nietzsche. Books ordered through Yale Bookstore Thomas Hobbes, Leviathan, ed. E. M. Curley, Hackett, ISBN 9780872201774 Francis Hutcheson, An Inquiry into the Original of Our Ideas of Beauty and Virtue, ed. Leidhold, Liberty Classics, ISBN 9780865977747 (pdf available at http://files.libertyfund.org/files/858/0449_LFeBk.pdf) Bishop Joseph Butler, Sermons, ed. Darwall, Hackett, ISBN 9780915145614 David Hume, A Treatise of Human Nature, ed. Norton and Norton, Oxford, ISBN 9780198751724 Adam Smith, The Theory of Moral Sentiments, ed. Raphael and Macfie, Liberty Classics, ISBN 9780865970120 (pdf available at http://files.libertyfund.org/files/192/0141-01_Bk.pdf) Immanuel Kant, The Critique of Practical Reason, ed.
    [Show full text]
  • A Companion to the Essential Leviathan: a Modernized Edition
    A Companion to The Essential Leviathan: A Modernized Edition Nancy A. Stanlick and Daniel P. Collette Authors’ Note: This online companion to The Essential Leviathan: A Modernized Edition was written with three goals in mind. The first is to provide a summary of primary contents of the chapters of Leviathan for people wishing to obtain a working overview of them. The second is to provide critical and analytical commentary on topics, concepts, and principles that are particularly interesting or problematic with respect to Hobbes' work. The third is to encourage the reader who comes to this companion prior to reading Hobbes' Leviathan to appreciate the importance of the work and to engage themselves in his arguments. We believe that doing so will be both an enjoyable as well as a profitable experience for those reading Hobbes for the first time. For those who have already read Leviathan and for those who are new to it, we are hopeful that this online companion will provide to the reader some useful (while necessarily selective) additional clarifications, critical evaluations, and commentary. Introduction Hobbes, along with René Descartes, is arguably a so-called “father” of modern Western philosophy. Descartes has historically been honored with this title, but Hobbes and Descartes were contemporaries, and both ushered in philosophies that rejected Aristotelianism and the authoritarianism of the Middle Ages. Their positions, while not identical by any means, both include and are largely defined by traits that became characteristic of the Modern era such as individualistic thinking, reliance upon reason rather than tradition, respect for and use of the methods of modern science, and a rejection of the relics of authoritarianism that hindered the progress of knowledge.
    [Show full text]
  • Reading and Writing in the Text of Hobbes's Leviathan Gary Shapiro University of Richmond, [email protected]
    University of Richmond UR Scholarship Repository Philosophy Faculty Publications Philosophy 4-1980 Reading and Writing in the Text of Hobbes's Leviathan Gary Shapiro University of Richmond, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: http://scholarship.richmond.edu/philosophy-faculty- publications Part of the Ethics and Political Philosophy Commons, and the Philosophy of Language Commons Recommended Citation Shapiro, Gary. "Reading and Writing in the Text of Hobbes's Leviathan."Journal of the History of Philosophy 18, no. 2 (April 1980): 147-57. doi:10.1353/hph.2008.0004. This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Philosophy at UR Scholarship Repository. It has been accepted for inclusion in Philosophy Faculty Publications by an authorized administrator of UR Scholarship Repository. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Reading and Writing in the Text of Hobbes's Leviathan GARY SHAPIRO CRITICS HAVE OFTEN SUGGESTED that Hobbes is a paradigm case of a philosopher whose own style of writing violates the norms he sets down for rational discourse. Philosophy, he says, "professedly rejects not only the paint and false colors of language, but even the very ornaments and graces of the same." More specifically he says that metaphors must be "utterly excluded" from "the rigorous search of truth.., seeing they openly professe deceit, to admit them into counsel, or reasoning, were manifested folly.'" Nevertheless, attention focuses on his flair for the dramatic or metaphorical, as in the great raise en scene that is the state of nature or in the overriding metaphor in which the state is regarded as an artificial man.
    [Show full text]
  • Human Nature and Human Knowledge: Part I of Leviathan
    Human Nature and Human Knowledge: Part I of Leviathan In Thomas Hobbes' Introduction to Leviathan, mechanistic materialism1 is a central feature of the development of his moral, social, political, and theological views. Hobbes likens the functioning of a political state to that of a human (or other) being. In this view Hobbes was influenced by William Harvey’s discovery of the circulation of blood and the burgeoning knowledge of the time in human anatomy and other physical sciences. Hobbes describes the political “body” and its parts in physicalistic terms and indicates that his work on government will proceed on the basis of cause-and-effect and the model of science applied to physical bodies. Similarly, for his moral and political doctrines, Hobbes’ arguments proceed on the basis of a “scientific” analysis of human beings. It is also important that Hobbes insists that if we will understand what he has written in Leviathan, we should read ourselves (that is, understand oneself) in order to know what other human beings desire and why they do what they do. This instruction is an early and clear indication of the individualistic thinking that manifests itself in a number of ways throughout Hobbes' Leviathan. With respect to individualism, Hobbes’ claim that one ought to “Read thyself” to know the nature of man is of special note. Hobbes' philosophical project depends on the observational truth that most people behave in predictable and similar ways, and if we are to know the nature of human behavior, expectations, desires, goals, and actions, all performed by people to reach goals, we need only to look inside ourselves.
    [Show full text]
  • The Rise and Fall of the Separation of Powers
    Copyright 2012 by Northwestern University School of Law Printed in U.S.A. Northwestern University Law Review Vol. 106, No. 2 THE RISE AND FALL OF THE SEPARATION OF POWERS Steven G. Calabresi, Mark E. Berghausen & Skylar Albertson ABSTRACT—The U.S. Constitution’s separation of powers has its origins in the British idea of the desirability of a Mixed Regime where the King, the Lords, and the Commons all checked and balanced one another as the three great estates of the realm. Aristotle, Polybius, Cicero, St. Thomas Aquinas, and Machiavelli all argued that Mixed Regimes of the One, the Few, and the Many were the best forms of regimes in practice because they led to a system of checks and balances. The Enlightenment killed off the Mixed Regime idea forever because hereditary office-holding by Kings and Lords became anathema. The result was the birth of a functional separation of legislative, executive, and judicial power as an alternative system of checks and balances to the Mixed Regime. For better or worse, however, in the United States, Congress laid claim to powers that the House of Lords and the House of Commons historically had in Britain, the President laid claim to powers the King historically had in Britain, and the Supreme Court has functioned in much the same way as did the Privy Council, the Court of Star Chamber, and the House of Lords. We think these deviations from a pure functional separation of powers are constitutionally problematic in light of the Vesting Clauses of Articles I, II, and III, which confer on Congress, the President, and the courts only the legislative, executive, and judicial power.
    [Show full text]