Extimate Technology

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Extimate Technology Extimate Technology This book investigates how we should form ourselves in a world satu- rated with technologies that are profoundly intruding in the very fabric of our selfhood. New and emerging technologies, such as smart technological environ- ments, imaging technologies and smart drugs, are increasingly shaping who and what we are and influencing who we ought to be. How should we adequately understand, evaluate and appreciate this development? Tackling this question requires going beyond the persistent and stubborn inside-outside dualism and recognizing that what we consider our “in- side” self is to a great extent shaped by our “outside” world. Inspired by various philosophers – especially Nietzsche, Peirce and Lacan – this book shows how the values, goals and ideals that humans encounter in their environments not only shape their identities but also can enable them to critically relate to their present state. The author argues against understanding technological self-formation in terms of making ourselves better, stronger and smarter. Rather, we should conceive it in terms of technological sublimation, which redefines the very notion of human enhancement. In this respect the author introduces an alternative, more suitable theory, namely Technological Sublimation Theory (TST). Extimate Technology will be of interest to scholars and advanced students working in philosophy of technology, philosophy of the self, phenomenology, pragmatism and history of philosophy. Ciano Aydin is Full Professor of Philosophy of Technology, Head of the Department of Philosophy and Vice-Dean of the Faculty of Behavioural, Management and Social Sciences (BMS) at the University of Twente, The Netherlands. He has published in Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society, Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, Journal of Medicine and Philosophy, Philosophy and Technology, and other journals. See www.cianoaydin.nl for more information about his c urrent research. Routledge Studies in Contemporary Philosophy Caring for Liberalism Dependency and Liberal Political Theory Edited by Asha Bhandary and Amy R. Baehr Language and Phenomenology Edited by Chad Engelland The Philosophy and Psychology of Ambivalence Being of Two Minds Edited by Berit Brogaard and Dimitria Electra Gatzia Concepts in Thought, Action, and Emotion New Essays Edited by Christoph Demmerling and Dirk Schröder Towards a Philosophical Anthropology of Culture Naturalism, Reflectivism, and Skepticism Kevin M. Cahill Examples and Their Role in Our Thinking Ondřej Beran Extimate Technology Self-Formation in a Technological World Ciano Aydin Modes of Truth The Unified Approach to Truth, Modality, and Paradox Edited by Carlo Nicolai and Johannes Stern Practices of Reason Fusing the Inferentialist and Scientific Image Ladislav Koreň For more information about this series, please visit: https://www.routledge. com/Routledge-Studies-in-Contemporary-Philosophy/book-series/SE0720 Extimate Technology Self-Formation in a Technological World Ciano Aydin NEW YORK AND LONDON First published 2021 by Routledge 52 Vanderbilt Avenue, New York, NY 10017 and by Routledge 2 Park Square, Milton Park, Abingdon, Oxon, OX14 4RN Routledge is an imprint of the Taylor & Francis Group, an informa business © 2021 Ciano Aydin The right of Ciano Aydin to be identified as author of this work has been asserted by him in accordance with sections 77 and 78 of the Copyright, Designs and Patents Act 1988. The Open Access version of this book, available at www. taylorfrancis.com, has been made available under a Creative Commons Attribution-Non Commercial-No Derivatives 4.0 license. Trademark notice: Product or corporate names may be trademarks or registered trademarks, and are used only for identification and explanation without intent to infringe. Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data A catalog record for this title has been requested ISBN: 978-0-367-68728-1 (hbk) ISBN: 978-1-003-13940-9 (ebk) Typeset in Sabon by codeMantra To Nur, Zeno, Daniël and Helena Contents Acknowledgments xi Introduction 1 From Inside to Outside and from Outside to Inside 1 Understanding Human-Technology Relations 4 Extimate Technology and Self-Formation 7 Research Question 11 Outline of the Book 12 PART I What Is the Self? 15 1 The Essentialist and Dualist Self and Why It Cannot Be Sustained 18 1.1 Aristotle’s Grounding of Essentialism 18 1.2 Descartes’ Elevation of the Self to an Independent Substance 24 1.3 Why the Essentialist Approach Is Alluring but Untenable 31 2 From “Self” to “Self-Formation” 41 2.1 Nietzsche’s Will to Power as an Anti-Essentialist Ontology 41 2.2 Peirce’s Phenomenological and Pragmatist Categories as Basis for an Interactionist Account of Self-Formation 52 Conclusion Part I 74 viii Contents PART II Is Self-Formation in a Technological World Possible? 83 3 The Autonomous Self and the Determined Self 86 3.1 Kantian Notions of Autonomy and Responsibility 86 3.2 Freedom and Determination in the Context of Social Psychology and Neuroscience 91 3.3 The Inside-Outside Distinction as a Blind Spot in Free Will Debates 95 4 The Artifactual Mind 100 4.1 The Extended Mind Thesis and the Parity Principle 102 4.2 Challenging the Notion of Introspection and Blurring the Criteria of What it Means to Be “Internal” 103 4.3 EMT, Second-Wave EM Theorists and the “Inside–Outside” Distinction 107 4.4 The Artifactual Mind 111 4.5 AMT, Normative Technologies and the Question of Self-Formation 120 5 Brain Imaging Technologies and Critical Self-Formation 124 5.1 Brain Imaging Technologies as Functional Evidence in Free Will Debates 126 5.2 Technological Inscription from Camera Obscura to fMRI 128 5.3 From Self-Determination to Self-Formation 136 5.4 Brain Imaging Technologies, Extrospection and Self-Formation 141 6 How Critical Is Critical Self-Formation? 147 6.1 Are our Longer-Term Goals and Ideals Ultimately Determined by Society? 148 6.2 Are our Cognitive and Neurological Means to Form Ourselves Determined by Institutions? 151 6.3 Reinterpreting Freedom as Self-Formation 153 Conclusion Part II 160 Contents ix PART III How Should We Technologically Form Ourselves? 165 7 Technological Self-Formation as Enhancement 168 7.1 Transhumanists and Their Ideal Human 169 7.2 Nietzsche’s Overhuman 172 7.3 Sounding Out Hollow Idols 178 7.4 Reframing “Enhancement” 187 8 The Technological Uncanny as a Permanent Structure of Selfhood 191 8.1 The Uncanny Valley 193 8.2 An Alternative Explanation of the Uncanny Valley, or the Importance of “Minor Differences” 197 8.3 The Otherness of the Self as “Extimacy” 199 8.4 Being “Closed Open” for Technology 203 8.5 Alterity in Selfhood and the Question of Technological Self-Formation 206 9 Self-Formation as Sublimation and the Question Concerning Technology 210 9.1 Sublimation as Substitution of Raw Drives for Social Valuations 211 9.2 Sublimation as Organizing Drives Around a Disruptive Void 214 9.3 Sublimation as Imposing Form to Great Diversity 224 9.4 Technological Sublimation Theory 235 10 Technological Sublimation Theory Applied to Three Technological Fields 243 10.1 Self-formation as Sublimation in Smart Technological Environments 244 10.2 Self-formation as Sublimation through Brain Imaging Technologies 253 10.3 Self-formation as Sublimation with Smart Drugs 263 Conclusion Part III 273 Epilogue: Groundwork for a Philosophy of Existential Technology 279 Text Abbreviations 285 References 287 Index 313 Acknowledgments The book incorporates reworked versions of the following texts: Aydin, Ciano. (2007). “Nietzsche on Reality as Will to Power: To- ward an ‘Organization-Struggle Model’.” Journal of Nietzsche Stud- ies 33: pp. 25–48 (©The Pennsylvania State University Press; reworked in Chapter 2); Aydin, Ciano. (2009). “On the Significance of Ideals. Peirce and the Good Life.” Transactions of the C.S. Peirce Society 45: pp. 422–443 (©Indiana University Press; reworked in Chapter 2); Aydin, Ciano. (2015). “The Artifactual Mind: Overcoming the ‘Inside-Outside’ Dualism in the Extended Mind Thesis and Recognizing the Techno- logical Dimension of Cognition.” Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 14(7): pp. 3–94 (©Springer; reworked in Chapter 4); Aydin, Ciano. (2018). “From Camera Obscura to fMRI: How Brain Imaging Technologies Mediate Free Will.” In Postphenomenological Methodol- ogies: New Ways in Mediating Techno-Human Relationships (Jesper Aagaard, Jan Kyrre Berg Friis, Jessica Sorenson, Oliver Tafdrup, and Cathrine Hasse, eds). Lanham/Boulder/New York/London: Lexington Books (©Rowman & Littlefield; reworked in Chapter 5); Aydin, Ciano, and de Boer, Bas. (2020). “Brain Imaging Technologies as Source for Extrospection: Self-formation through Critical Self-identification.” Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 19: 729–745 (©Springer; reworked in Chapter 5 and 6); Aydin, Ciano. (2017). “The Posthuman as Hollow Idol: A Nietzschean Critique of Human Enhancement.” Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 42(3): pp. 304–327 (©Oxford University Press; reworked in Chapter 7); Aydin, Ciano. (forthcoming). The Tech- nological Uncanny as a Permanent Structure of Selfhood. In Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Technology (Shannon Vallor, ed.). Oxford University Press (©Oxford University Press; reworked in Chapter 8). I would like to thank the respective publishers and journals for their kind permissions to reuse this copyrighted material. IEEE I thank for permission to use the uncanny valley graph from Mori, Masahiro. (2012). The Uncanny Valley, IEEE Robotics and Automation Magazin 19: pp. 98–100 (Figure 8.1 included in Chapter 8). This book has a long history and originated from a seemingly simple idea that became an obsession: in Western culture and philosophy, the xii Acknowledgments notes are often mistaken for the melody (after Bergson). Different forms of dualism, essentialism and reductionism, which are also reflected in our views of technology, seem to be manifestations of this misconcep- tion. This book is an attempt to uncover and disentangle this confusion and to provide a more appropriate framework for understanding how technologies shape the human self. I am indebted to everyone who contributed to the realization of this book, if “only” by creating the conditions under which it could be writ- ten.
Recommended publications
  • Manzotti Pepperell New Mind
    Draft: AI & Society “A Faustian Exchange: What is to be human in the era of Ubiquitous Technology The New Mind: Thinking Beyond the Head Riccardo MANZOTTI*, Robert PEPPERELL** *Institute of Consumption, Communication and Behavior IULM University, Via Carlo Bo, 8, 16033 Milano [email protected] **Cardiff School of Art & Design Howard Gardens, Cardiff CF24 0SP, UK [email protected] Abstract Throughout much of the modern period the human mind has been regarded as a property of the brain, and therefore something confined to the inside of the head — a view commonly known as 'internalism'. But recent works in cognitive science, philosophy, and anthropology, as well as certain trends in the development of technology, suggest an emerging view of the mind as a process not confined to the brain but spread through the body and world — an outlook covered by a family of views labeled 'externalism'. In this paper we will suggest there is now sufficient momentum in favour of externalism of various kinds to mark a historical shift in the way the mind is understood. We dub this emerging externalist tendency the 'New Mind'. Key properties of the New Mind will be summarized and some of its implications considered in areas such as art and culture, technology, and the science of consciousness. 1 Introduction For much of recorded human history, in both the European and Asian traditions, the question of how to understand that most ever present yet elusive properties of our existence — that fact that we have conscious minds — has occupied some of our greatest thinkers and provoked endless controversy.
    [Show full text]
  • What Is That Thing Called Philosophy of Technology? - R
    HISTORY AND PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE AND TECHNOLOGY – Vol. IV - What Is That Thing Called Philosophy of Technology? - R. J. Gómez WHAT IS THAT THING CALLED PHILOSOPHY OF TECHNOLOGY? R. J. Gómez Department of Philosophy. California State University (LA). USA Keywords: Adorno, Aristotle, Bunge, Ellul, Feenberg, Habermas, Heidegger, Horkheimer, Jonas, Latour, Marcuse, Mumford, Naess, Shrader-Frechette, artifact, assessment, determinism, ecosophy, ends, enlightenment, efficiency, epistemology, enframing, ideology, life-form, megamachine, metaphysics, method, naturalistic, fallacy, new, ethics, progress, rationality, rule, science, techno-philosophy Contents 1. Introduction 2. Locating technology with respect to science 2.1. Structure and Content 2.2. Method 2.3. Aim 2.4. Pattern of Change 3. Locating philosophy of technology 4. Early philosophies of technology 4.1. Aristotelianism 4.2. Technological Pessimism 4.3. Technological Optimism 4.4. Heidegger’s Existentialism and the Essence of Technology 4.5. Mumford’s Megamachinism 4.6. Neomarxism 4.6.1. Adorno-Horkheimer 4.6.2. Marcuse 4.6.3. Habermas 5. Recent philosophies of technology 5.1. L. Winner 5.2. A. Feenberg 5.3. EcosophyUNESCO – EOLSS 6. Technology and values 6.1. Shrader-Frechette Claims 6.2. H Jonas 7. Conclusions SAMPLE CHAPTERS Glossary Bibliography Biographical Sketch Summary A philosophy of technology is mainly a critical reflection on technology from the point of view of the main chapters of philosophy, e.g., metaphysics, epistemology and ethics. Technology has had a fast development since the middle of the 20th century , especially ©Encyclopedia of Life Support Systems (EOLSS) HISTORY AND PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE AND TECHNOLOGY – Vol. IV - What Is That Thing Called Philosophy of Technology? - R.
    [Show full text]
  • Design Without Causality: Heidegger's Impossible
    DESIGN WITHOUT CAUSALITY: HEIDEGGER’S IMPOSSIBLE CHALLENGE FOR ECOLOGICALLY SUSTAINABLE ARCHITECTURE GLEN HILL Faculty of Architecture, Design and Planning University of Sydney NSW 2006, Australia [email protected] Abstract Deploying Martin Heidegger’s thinking on technology, this paper attempts to show an internal contradiction inherent in our technologically oriented approach to sustainable design. Heidegger’s thinking on technology, which has had an influence both on the ecological movement and on architecture, situates the problematic shift toward modern technology at the beginning of the enlightenment with the emergence of new understandings of both the subject and the object. Each of these revolutionary understandings contribute to the reframing of nature as knowable and (therefore) controllable. Nature thus moves from a position of mystery and wonder to that of a disenchanted, predictable system, allowing the appearance of a technological orientation in which nature is framed in advance as something simply manipulable for our benefit. Unlike the Classical Realist account of nature that emerged from the enlightenment separation of subject and object, Heidegger’s formulation of the real, of nature, does not allow the same confidence in causality and control. However, design, as the engine of technological innovation in modernity, appears inseparable from the modern technological understanding of causality and control and the framing of nature as a mere resource. This problematises the possibility that design, as it is currently conceived, can contribute to achieving an ecological sustainable relation to nature. Keywords: technology, Heidegger, ecological, sustainable, design. 1 Introduction Any discussion of technology would be incomplete without consideration of the thinking of Martin Heidegger.
    [Show full text]
  • The Speculative Neuroscience of the Future Human Brain
    Humanities 2013, 2, 209–252; doi:10.3390/h2020209 OPEN ACCESS humanities ISSN 2076-0787 www.mdpi.com/journal/humanities Article The Speculative Neuroscience of the Future Human Brain Robert A. Dielenberg Freelance Neuroscientist, 15 Parry Street, Cooks Hill, NSW, 2300, Australia; E-Mail: [email protected]; Tel.: +61-423-057-977 Received: 3 March 2013; in revised form: 23 April 2013 / Accepted: 27 April 2013 / Published: 21 May 2013 Abstract: The hallmark of our species is our ability to hybridize symbolic thinking with behavioral output. We began with the symmetrical hand axe around 1.7 mya and have progressed, slowly at first, then with greater rapidity, to producing increasingly more complex hybridized products. We now live in the age where our drive to hybridize has pushed us to the brink of a neuroscientific revolution, where for the first time we are in a position to willfully alter the brain and hence, our behavior and evolution. Nootropics, transcranial direct current stimulation (tDCS), transcranial magnetic stimulation (TMS), deep brain stimulation (DBS) and invasive brain mind interface (BMI) technology are allowing humans to treat previously inaccessible diseases as well as open up potential vistas for cognitive enhancement. In the future, the possibility exists for humans to hybridize with BMIs and mobile architectures. The notion of self is becoming increasingly extended. All of this to say: are we in control of our brains, or are they in control of us? Keywords: hybridization; BMI; tDCS; TMS; DBS; optogenetics; nootropic; radiotelepathy Introduction Newtonian systems aside, futurecasting is a risky enterprise at the best of times.
    [Show full text]
  • Classical Ethics in A/IS
    The IEEE Global Initiative on Ethics of Autonomous and Intelligent Systems Classical Ethics in A/IS We applied classical ethics methodologies to considerations of algorithmic design in autonomous and intelligent systems (A/IS) where machine learning may or may not reflect ethical outcomes that mimic human decision-making. To meet this goal, we drew from classical ethics theories and the disciplines of machine ethics, information ethics, and technology ethics. As direct control over tools becomes further removed, creators of autonomous systems must ask themselves how cultural and ethical presumptions bias artificially intelligent creations. Such introspection is more necessary than ever because the precise and deliberate design of algorithms in self-sustained digital systems will result in responses based on such design. By drawing from over two thousand years’ worth of classical ethics traditions, we explore established ethics systems, including both philosophical traditions (utilitarianism, virtue ethics, and deontological ethics) and religious and culture-based ethical systems (Buddhism, Confucianism, African Ubuntu traditions, and Japanese Shinto) and their stance on human morality in the digital age.1 In doing so, we critique assumptions around concepts such as good and evil, right and wrong, virtue and vice, and we attempt to carry these inquiries into artificial systems’ decision-making processes. Through reviewing the philosophical foundations that define autonomy and ontology, we address the potential for autonomous capacity of artificially intelligent systems, posing questions of morality in amoral systems and asking whether decisions made by amoral systems can have moral consequences. Ultimately, we address notions of responsibility and accountability for the decisions made by autonomous systems and other artificially intelligent technologies.
    [Show full text]
  • Why We Need a Philosophy of Engineering: a Work in Progress
    Why we need a philosophy of engineering: a work in progress STEVEN L. GOLDMAN Departments of Philosophy and History, Lehigh University, Bethlehem, PA 18015, USA Engineering problem solving employs a contingency based form of reasoning that stands in sharp contrast to the necessity based model of rationality that has dominated Western philosophy since Plato and that underlies modern science. The concept ‘necessity’ is cognate with the concepts ‘certainty’, ‘universality’, ‘abstractness’ and ‘theory’. Engineering by contrast is characterised by wilfulness, particularity, probability, concreteness and prac- tice. The identification of rationality with necessity has impoverished our ability to apply reason effectively to action. This article locates the contingency based reasoning of engineer- ing in a philosophical tradition extending from pre-Socratic philosophers to American pragmatism, and suggests how a contingency based philosophy of engineering might enable more effective technological action. For reasons that have been at the heart of Western culture from its beginnings in ancient Greece, engineering has been treated dismissively by intellectuals and in particular by philosophers.1 The reasons reflect deeply rooted prejudices that have been sustained for well over two thousand years. Of special relevance to the persistent underestimation of engineering is the low value historically placed by intellectuals on the contingent, the probable, the particular, the contextual and the temporal. Conversely, philosophers especially have placed a high value on the necessary, the certain, the universal, the context independent and the timeless. This hierarchisation subordinates practice, values, emotion and will to theory, value neutral principles and deductive logic in ways that leave us ill equipped to deal rationally with life.
    [Show full text]
  • Toward a Philosophy of Technology Author(S): Hans Jonas Source: the Hastings Center Report, Vol
    Toward a Philosophy of Technology Author(s): Hans Jonas Source: The Hastings Center Report, Vol. 9, No. 1 (Feb., 1979), pp. 34-43 Published by: The Hastings Center Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/3561700 . Accessed: 26/10/2011 18:53 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at . http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. The Hastings Center is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to The Hastings Center Report. http://www.jstor.org KNOWLEDGE,POWER & THE BIOLOGICALREVOLUTION Toward a Philosophy of Technology by HANS JONAS the world furnishedwith them looks. A third, overarching themeis the moralside of technologyas a burdenon human A re there philosophicalaspects to technology?Of responsibility,especially its long-termeffects on the global course there are, as there are to all things of importancein conditionof man and environment.This-my own mainpre- humanendeavor and destiny.Modern technology touches on occupation over the past years-will only be touched upon. almost everythingvital to man's existence-material, men- tal, and spiritual.Indeed, what of man is not involved?The I. The FormalDynamics of Technology way he lives his life and looks at objects,his intercoursewith the worldand with his peers,his powersand modes of action, First some observationsabout technology'sform as an kinds of goals, states and changesof society, objectivesand abstractwhole of movement.We are concernedwith char- forms of politics (includingwarfare no less than welfare), acteristicsof moderntechnology and thereforeask firstwhat the sense and qualityof life, even man'sfate and that of his distinguishesit formallyfrom all previoustechnology.
    [Show full text]
  • D1.3 Title: Roadmap
    BNCI Horizon 2020 FP7-ICT-2013-10 609593 Nov 2013–Apr 2015 Deliverable: D1.3 Title: Roadmap Work package: WP1 Due: M9 Type: PU1 ☐ PP2 ☐ RE3 ☐ CO4 Main author: Clemens Brunner (TUG) Other authors: Gernot R. Müller-Putz (TUG) Mariska Van Steensel (UMCU) Begonya Otal (BDIGITAL) Floriana Pichiorri (FSL) Francesca Schettini (FSL) Ruben Real (UNIWUE) Maria Laura Blefari (EPFL) Johannes Höhne (TUB) Mannes Poel (UT) Abstract: This deliverable describes the current state of the roadmap document. Keywords: Roadmap 1 Public 2 Restricted to other program participants 3 Restricted to a group specified by the consortium 4 Confidential, only for members of the consortium 1 Table of Contents 1Introduction .............................................................................................................................. 3 2The Project ............................................................................................................................... 3 3The Consortium ........................................................................................................................ 4 4What is a BCI? ......................................................................................................................... 4 5Who can use a BCI? ................................................................................................................. 6 6Future opportunities and synergies ........................................................................................... 8 7Executive summary ...............................................................................................................
    [Show full text]
  • Heidegger, Marcuse and the Philosophy of Technology
    [Text of a lecture based on the Preface to Heidegger and Marcuse: The Catastrophe and Redemption of History (Routledge, 2005)] Heidegger, Marcuse and the Philosophy of Technology Andrew Feenberg Heidegger is often considered to be the most important continental philosopher of the 20th Century. He is certainly one of the most controversial. Despite his politics, Heidegger had four Jewish students who went on to brilliant careers as social philosophers, Hannah Arendt, Hans Jonas, Karl Löwith, and Herbert Marcuse. I had the good fortune to study with Marcuse and have been influenced by his thought, although I am by no means a "Marcusean." Several years ago I decided to investigate the links between Heidegger and Marcuse more closely and discovered to my surprise that they share a common interpretation of Aristotle, an interpretation that seems to originate in Heidegger's early courses which Marcuse attended. I have followed up this connection in a book entitled Heidegger and Marcuse: The Catastrophe and Redemption of History. This lecture will review some of the main themes of this book. *** I arrived in La Jolla, California in the fall of 1965 as a graduate student in philosophy. One of my reasons for coming was what I had heard of Herbert Marcuse. He was not yet famous but he was well known and what was known about him intrigued me. I was interested in phenomenology, but a philosopher wild enough to synthesize Marx and Freud was wild enough for a young graduate student looking for an alternative to the positivism then dominating American philosophy. At the first opportunity I asked Professor Marcuse to help me study Martin Heidegger’s Being and Time.
    [Show full text]
  • Information and Causality Phyllis Illari and Federica Russo 1 Philosophy
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by UCL Discovery Information and causality Phyllis Illari and Federica Russo 1 Philosophy of causality meets information Philosophical theorizing has been concerned at least since ancient Greek thinkers with the problem of connecting events as causes and effects. For Aristotle causes are first principles that explain the ‘why of things’, but they are also ‘efficient’ in that they are the ‘source of change or rest’. In this sense Aristotelian efficient causation is very close to the attempts made by contemporary philosophy of science to give an account of how something gives rise to something else. Recent debates in philosophy of causality have highlighted that it is one thing to establish that C causes E and another thing to establish how C causes E. This derives from the work of Hall (2004), who distinguishes two concepts of causation – dependence (that) and production (how) – and is followed up by philosophers interested in analyzing the different evidential components (dependence or association (that) and production or mechanisms (how)) which enter into causal assessment (Russo and Williamson, 2007, Illari, 2011a, Clarke et al., 2014). Recent philosophical literature exploring how C causes E has focused on examining the ways in which mechanisms explain such connections. Here, we will focus on understanding production, which is broader in scope, as will become clear. Concerning how C and E are connected, so far we have two dominant accounts. One is in terms of physical processes, characterized using concepts from physics such as conserved quantities.
    [Show full text]
  • Just a Tool? John Dewey's Pragmatic Instrumentalism and Educational
    Just a Tool? John Dewey’s Pragmatic Instrumentalism and Educational Technology By © 2018 Mike Bannen Submitted to the graduate degree program in Social & Cultural Studies in Education and the Graduate Faculty of the University of Kansas in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy. Chair: Suzanne Rice, Ph.D. John L. Rury, Ph.D. Argun Staatcioglu, Ph.D. Heidi Hallman, Ph.D. Joe E. O’Brien, Ed.D. Date Defended: 31 January 2018 The dissertation committee for Mike Bannen certifies that this is the approved version of the following dissertation: Just a Tool? John Dewey’s Pragmatic Instrumentalism and Educational Technology Chairperson: Suzanne Rice, Ph.D. Date Approved: 31 January 2018 ii Abstract This dissertation examines how John Dewey’s philosophy of knowledge might be used to consider the aims of contemporary educational technologies. While significant scholarship exists examining the historical and philosophical importance of Dewey’s contributions to American progressive education, much less scholarship has focused on examining the relationship between Dewey’s theory of knowledge and his thoughts regarding the purposes and aims of educational technologies. I argue that because many of Dewey’s ideas were heavily influenced by the material and social changes of the industrial revolution, his theories about knowledge, technology, and education offer a unique perspective when considering the educational significance of digital technologies. This dissertation is guided by two central questions: (1) What is the relationship between Dewey’s philosophy of knowledge, his philosophy of technology, and his philosophy of education? (2) How might Dewey’s ideas about the relationship between knowledge, technology, and education help educators, students, and policy makers think about the aims and uses of digital technologies in contemporary educational contexts? I begin by examining Dewey’s pragmatically instrumental account of knowledge.
    [Show full text]
  • DES 03452- PHILOSOPHY of TECHNOLOGY Harvard University Graduate School of Design Course Syllabus – Spring 2014
    DES 03452- PHILOSOPHY OF TECHNOLOGY Harvard University Graduate School of Design Course Syllabus – Spring 2014 Robert Silman Office hours by appointment: 111 Devonshire Street Mon. - Fri., 9:00 - 5:00 Boston, MA 02109 Tel. (617) 695-6700, ext. 116 E-mail: [email protected] "Technology is a branch of moral philosophy, not of science." (Paul Goodman, Week No. 6) (T) Text: Scharff, Robert C. and Dusek, Val. Philosophy of Technology – The Technological Condition. Blackwell Publishing, Malden, MA. 2003 (iSites) Reading to be found on iSites under DES 03452 (www) Internet on-line source material Date Week Topic 1 Introduction. Our responsibilities as designers of the built environment. Defining technology. Reading: (iSites) Jonas, Hans. The Imperative of Responsibility. pp. 1-24, 38-43, 201- 204. (iSites) Kline, Stephen J . “What is Technology?” pp. 210-212. (iSites) Feibelman, James K. "Pure Science, Applied Science and Technology: An Attempt at Definitions." pp. 33-41. (In Mitcham and Mackey, Philosophy and Technology.) Related typologies: Affordable Housing, Sustainable Design 2 Historical Perspective Reading: (T) Mitcham, Carl. “Three Ways of Being-With Technology.” pp. 490-506. (T) Bacon, Francis. “On the Idols, the Scientific Study of Nature, and the Reformation of Education.” pp. 25-37. (T) Comte, Auguste. “The Nature and Importance of the Positive Philosophy. pp. 45-59. (T) **Optional Reading**: Aristotle. “On ‘Techné’ and ‘Epistémé’.” pp. 19-24. Related typologies: Historic Preservation 3 Classical vs. Heidegger’s View of Technology Reading: Aristotle. Physics II. Lines 194b16-195b30, 198a14-198b9. (Chaps. 3 and 7). (T) Heidegger, Martin. "The Question Concerning Technology." pp. 252- 264. (iSites) Dreyfus, Hubert.
    [Show full text]