Introduction Transcending Structure-Agency in the Study of Organizations

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Introduction Transcending Structure-Agency in the Study of Organizations Introduction Transcending Structure-Agency in the Study of Organizations Vita Peacock and Philip Kao What is the relation between our own daily perspectives of two foundational fi gures in activity and the organizations that almost all the study of organizations: Émile Durkheim of us are members of? This seemingly simple and Max Weber. For Durkheim, an analysis question has dominated the social study of of social structure was the key to understand- organizations for over a century, and the re- ing individual behaviour. The family, the law, sponses to it can be very broadly parcelled religion, and economic and political life con- out into three alternative perspectives. The stituted such ‘structures’, enforcing their col- fi rst argues that this organization, (whether lective will through ‘social facts’ (Durkheim a school, a university, a corporation, a union, 1982: 50), which produced the social being of or any other substantial social group) has a their members. These structures and their ma- determinate relationship to our activity within terial expressions produced the relationship of it, being larger and more powerful than we human beings to one other: their ‘solidarity’ are as individuals. The second maintains that (Durkheim 1997). One’s relative ‘integration’ through our activity and exchange with other into, and ‘regulation’ by, these structures could individuals within them, we in fact co-consti- even determine diff erent forms of suicide, tute such groups. The third perspective seeks previously conceived to be the most unam- to get around the predominance of one over biguous case of individual choice (Durkheim the other, by asserting that both elements of 1952). For Durkheim, the ‘thoughts to be found this relationship are in dialectical synthesis. in the consciousness of individuals’ were ir- Welcome to the Möbius strip of the so-called relevant (1982: 54). When individuals became ‘structure-agency problem’, which continues part of social groups they were helplessly to drive organizational theorists in dizzying transformed: becoming part of a qualitatively circles. Emerging from a workshop hosted by distinct unitary mass, which guided their ac- the Department of Anthropology at Univer- tions accordingly. sity College London in July 2012, we ask in Weber, meanwhile, took a diff erent tack; this Special Issue: has the ‘structure-agency his emphasis on interpreting the ‘actions’ of problem’ itself become a problem? Is the time ‘agents’ was in fact almost antithetical to Dur- for ‘rethinking’ this binary fi nally past (Reed kheim’s structure (Runciman 1993: 7–42). The 1997)? Is now the moment to snip the strip to a priori existence and determinacy of supra- see in which directions its severed ends might personal entities were no longer to be taken lead us? for granted, but rather ‘all events or states Before reaching for the scissors, a brief and of aff airs … remain meaningless if no agent schematic synopsis of the problem – as defi ned has consciously endowed them with mean- by its most infl uential intermediaries – will be ing’ (ibid.: 10). For Weber, collectives had to necessary.1 The story begins with the divergent be constituted by the discrete social actions Anthropology in Action, 20, no. 2 (Summer 2013): 1–5 © Berghahn Books and the Association for Anthropology in Action ISSN 0967-201X (Print) ISSN 1752-2285 (Online) doi:10.3167/aia.2013.200201 AiA | Vita Peacock and Philip Kao of its individuals, who elected to accord them the agent’s class location) which produced signifi cance or otherwise. No bonds of ‘soli- the habitus (ibid.: 54), as well as the habitus darity’ were presumed in advance; and any itself as an ordering principle – his emphasis abstract formation such as ‘state’, ‘church’, is wholeheartedly placed within the body of or ‘marriage’ – some of the central tenets of the actor. To exist, organizations had to be Durkheim’s structure – were regarded as reifi - inhabited by individuals so inscribed. It was cations, which only became relevant for the so- the habitus that enabled them to ‘att ain full re- ciologist if actors considered them to be (ibid.: alization’ (ibid.: 57); contra Durkheim, organi- 30). The work of abstraction for Weber was not zations possessed no sui generis extrinsic life. to understand individual behaviour through Giddens, meanwhile, was more change- the lens of structural determinants – as Dur- oriented in emphasis, as opposed to Bour- kheim apprehended diff erent forms of suicide dieu’s orientation towards reproduction. Like – but to uncover collective logics through an Bourdieu, Giddens’ agent is one who acts in interpretation of individual actions, such as his the world (‘Agency refers to doing’) (1984: famous descriptions of various forms of ‘au- 10); yet while ‘habitus’ reiterates dispositions thority’ (Weber 1979). Weber’s methodological learnt in childhood and beyond, Giddens’ individualism placed the ‘actor’ or ‘agent’ at agent is one who decides – in his words – to the centre of the social universe. ‘make a diff erence’ (ibid.: 14). Agency is thus It is Weber’s proposition that human be- inextricably linked to power, the causal start- haviour is irreducibly ‘stochastic’ (Hacking ing point in a chain reaction which may lead 1990) and so the ‘agent’ should come fi rst, to historical change. Structure, meanwhile, is that essentially came to defi ne organizational a purely abstract formation: a ‘virtual order’ of analysis as the twentieth century marched transformative relations (ibid.: 17). It consists on. While Durkheim’s structure – particularly of rules of morality and conduct that can only in its later metaphysical expression (2008) – be approximated by acting subjects. According found favour with subsequent generations of to Giddens, the dualism of ‘agency’ and ‘struc- anthropologists, Weber’s ‘interpretive sociol- ture’ is a fallacy, as both are part of the same ogy’, which he argued could only be applied duality: ‘the duality of structure’ (ibid.: 25). His to what was culturally familiar and therefore solution, ‘structuration’, takes the same line as capable of comprehension (Runciman 1993: Bourdieu in its emphasis on practice, but plays 19), shaped the latt er discipline under which upon the paradox that actors may be both organizational analysis largely fell (Scott 1959; enabled and constrained by the Janus-faced Parsons 1968). quality of such duality. In the 1970s and 1980s – emblematic of the Finally, in the 1990s and beyond, holistic no- postmodern taste for antinomies – two infl u- tions of constraint have appeared to evaporate ential social theorists sought to resolve the entirely. Bourdieu and Giddens’ focus on the opposition between ‘agent’ and ‘structure’ by indeterminacy of action, opened the doors to asserting the inextricability of their union. The elaborations of ‘agency’ and ‘creativity’ which more well-known of these is Pierre Bourdieu defi ed structural explanation (Law 1994; Rap- and his theorization of the embodied accu- port 2009); members of organizations were mulation of inherited dispositions he called purported to inhabit a hyper-immanent world the ‘habitus’ (1990: 54). While much of his of constant happenings (Kondo 1990; Zaloom discussion revolves around structure – which 2006). Such conceptual moves have eff ectively through his Marxist lens meant the ‘deter- ‘collapsed structure into agency’ (Reed 1997: minate class of conditions of existence’ (the 21); thus Weber’s perspective won out, while social and material circumstances arising from Durkheim’s disintegrated into disrepute. Al- 2 | Introduction | AiA ways a reliable source of contemporary doxa, there are other dynamics and social facts that undergraduates are now outraged at the re- can speak truth to power. morseless collective bias of the latt er’s orienta- Like Bashkow (2004), we fi nd it produc- tion, appalled by his neglect of ‘the individual’ tive to reanimate a Boasian conception of and their independent activity. boundaries, especially those that are erected The current state of play can be illustrated and dismantled by people inhabiting par- by the comparatively long reign of ‘actor-net- ticular organizations. By shift ing the focus work’ analysis (Law and Hassard 1999). Bruno towards boundaries, ethnographers can show Latour – its most vociferous advocate – drew how certain contexts lead to action and mean- his scholarly genealogy from Gabriel Tarde ing that is not always given nor foreclosed in instead of Durkheim (interestingly Weber was various institutional/bureaucratic orderings. also infl uenced by Tarde), and pronounced the This perspective does not necessarily amount death of ‘the social’ as Durkheim understood to delimiting freedom in action, creativity or it (Latour 2005). In Latour’s materialist view, resistance, but rather illuminates the inter- the social only becomes real if actively traced, faces that mould the processes and histories and so the work of the social analyst should be of organizations and organizational ‘selves’. ‘a sociology of associations’ (ibid.: 160) – one The concept of boundaries is fruitful as it which ignores abstractions and focuses instead demarcates types of relationships, and con- on the way ‘actors’ forge and interact with textualizes claims of ownership, belonging, ‘networks’. He thus applied this methodology authority, legitimacy, and accountability. By to the organizations he has examined (Latour doing so, we can improve our study of organi- and Woolgar 1979; Latour 2010). Latour’s most zations by recognizing the relational nature of radical proposition was that there are eff ec- decision-making, interaction and other aspects tively no value-laden milieu which prefi gure of organizational work and life that are op- the ways these ‘actor-networks’ emerge: in erationalized both across and because of them. his words ‘we have to try to keep the social Likewise, exploring the eff ects of boundaries domain completely fl at’ (Latour 2005: 171). rather than those of ‘structures’ or ‘agents’, Thus for Latour the ‘structure-agency prob- may generate pragmatic solutions to forms of lem’ is resolved through the total rejection of dysfunction, ineff ectiveness or malaise which structure, and its substitution for a universally can permeate organizational life.
Recommended publications
  • Social Action Projects MAKING a DIFFERENCE K-4
    5-8 social action projects MAKING A DIFFERENCE K-4 All rights reserved. Any reproduction in whole or in part without the prior written consent of the Canadian Teachers’ Federation and The Critical Thinking Consortium is prohibited. However, schools and non-profit organizations may reproduce material from Social Action Projects: Making a Difference, in all or in part, for educational purposes only. This resource was originally developed in English and translated into French. The English and French versions of this document may offer alternate resources and links. To obtain additional copies or information, please contact the: Canadian Teachers’ Federation 2490 Don Reid Drive Ottawa, ON K1H 1E1 Tel.: (613) 232-1505 Toll-free: (866) 283-1505 Fax: (613) 232-1886 Email: [email protected] www.ctf-fce.ca © 2010, Canadian Teachers Federation and The Critical Thinking Consortium ISBN 0-88989-398-5 5-8 social action projects MAKING A DIFFERENCE Students studied the community water supply and WRITING identified sources of harmful pollutants. They wrote an FOR A LOCAL article for the local newspaper explaining their findings NEWSPAPER and offering ideas to help avoid future problems. Students collected books from all of their friends PROVIDING FOR and family and started a library at the local children’s CHILDREN IN hospital for kids who can’t go out to get books because THE HOSPITAL they are too ill. Elementary students sent “friendship boxes” filled SUPPLYING with letters, school supplies, artwork and other SCHOOLS items to schools in Mexico, Guatemala, El Salvador, AROUND THE and Nicaragua. The project has grown such that WORLD 2000 schools have sent supplies and computers to schools in need.
    [Show full text]
  • Structure and Agency: an Analysis of the Impact of Structure on Group Agents Elizabeth Kaye Victor University of South Florida, [email protected]
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Scholar Commons | University of South Florida Research University of South Florida Scholar Commons Graduate Theses and Dissertations Graduate School January 2012 Structure and Agency: An Analysis of the Impact of Structure on Group Agents Elizabeth Kaye Victor University of South Florida, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: http://scholarcommons.usf.edu/etd Part of the American Studies Commons, and the Ethics and Political Philosophy Commons Scholar Commons Citation Victor, Elizabeth Kaye, "Structure and Agency: An Analysis of the Impact of Structure on Group Agents" (2012). Graduate Theses and Dissertations. http://scholarcommons.usf.edu/etd/4246 This Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by the Graduate School at Scholar Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Graduate Theses and Dissertations by an authorized administrator of Scholar Commons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Structure and Agency: An Analysis of the Impact of Structure on Group Agents by Elizabeth Kaye Victor A dissertation submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy Department of Philosophy College of Arts and Sciences University of South Florida Co-Major Professor: Rebecca Kukla, Ph.D. Co-Major Professor: Stephen Turner, Ph.D. Colin Heydt, Ph.D. Bryce Hueber, Ph.D Douglas Jesseph, Ph.D. Walter Nord, Ph.D. Date of Approval: May 16, 2012 Keywords: Group Agency, Business Ethics, Corporate Social Responsibility, Ethics, Human Resource Management Copyright © 2012, Elizabeth Kaye Victor Dedication I would like to dedicate this dissertation to my father and friend, Joe.
    [Show full text]
  • Evolutionary Stability of Social Norms in a Socio-Economic Equilibrium Model, Diskussionsbeiträge - Serie I, No
    A Service of Leibniz-Informationszentrum econstor Wirtschaft Leibniz Information Centre Make Your Publications Visible. zbw for Economics Grüner, Hans Peter Working Paper Evolutionary stability of social norms in a socio- economic equilibrium model Diskussionsbeiträge - Serie I, No. 276 Provided in Cooperation with: Department of Economics, University of Konstanz Suggested Citation: Grüner, Hans Peter (1994) : Evolutionary stability of social norms in a socio-economic equilibrium model, Diskussionsbeiträge - Serie I, No. 276, Universität Konstanz, Fakultät für Wirtschaftswissenschaften und Statistik, Konstanz This Version is available at: http://hdl.handle.net/10419/68921 Standard-Nutzungsbedingungen: Terms of use: Die Dokumente auf EconStor dürfen zu eigenen wissenschaftlichen Documents in EconStor may be saved and copied for your Zwecken und zum Privatgebrauch gespeichert und kopiert werden. personal and scholarly purposes. Sie dürfen die Dokumente nicht für öffentliche oder kommerzielle You are not to copy documents for public or commercial Zwecke vervielfältigen, öffentlich ausstellen, öffentlich zugänglich purposes, to exhibit the documents publicly, to make them machen, vertreiben oder anderweitig nutzen. publicly available on the internet, or to distribute or otherwise use the documents in public. Sofern die Verfasser die Dokumente unter Open-Content-Lizenzen (insbesondere CC-Lizenzen) zur Verfügung gestellt haben sollten, If the documents have been made available under an Open gelten abweichend von diesen Nutzungsbedingungen die in der dort Content Licence (especially Creative Commons Licences), you genannten Lizenz gewährten Nutzungsrechte. may exercise further usage rights as specified in the indicated licence. www.econstor.eu Universiiat [\ Koristanz —hvf^— r1—nr 7\ / \ A/\ f N Fakultat fur Wirtschaftswissenschaften und Statistik Hans Peter Gruner Evolutionary Stability of Social Norms in a Socio-Economic Equilibrium Model Diskussionsbeitrage Postfach 5560 Serie I — Nr.
    [Show full text]
  • The Social Action Frame of Reference: an Historical Map and Analysis
    Philosophica 36,1985 (2), pp. 135-150. 135 THE SOCIAL ACTION FRAME OF REFERENCE: AN HISTORICAL MAP AND ANALYSIS Nkeonye Otakpor I An unprecedented interest in "social action" theory has developed in Western Europe and North America in the last ten to fifteen years and it can be seen as representing just one of the many attacks that have been mounted on the dominant paradigm of western sociology and philosophy - the structuralist/functionalist school epitomised by the works of Talcott Parsons. 1 It would assist the exposition of what is distinctive about the "social action" perspective if the latter is opposed to the dominent tradition in a brief historical account of certain strands of sociological and philo­ sophical thought. In the process, I will attempt to explain what I understand to be meant by the various but related terms which are found in accounts of the structural - functionalist, and "social action" approaches to the study of society. Structural-functionalism can be seen as the culmination of a sociological discourse which holds that the social sciences may develop along identical lines as those of the natural sciences. The ro'ots of such an epistemology can be traced, at least, as far back as the mid-eighteenth century when Montesquieu published his L 'Esprit des LOis, 2 and the intellectual history of the succeeding two centuries is littered with the names of those who attempted to follow in his wake. In this context, the names of Henri Saint Simon and his acolyte Augustin Comte are perhaps the most important. Often credited as the founders of sociology, 3 both Saint Simon and Comte considered themselves to be positivists and by this they meant that they were intent on a science of society which is free from all vestiges of religion and metaphysics.
    [Show full text]
  • Chapter 1 Political Socialization: a Conceptual and Theoretical
    Poliltical Socialization : A Conceptual and Theoretical Construction 1 Chapter 1 Political Socialization: A Conceptual and Theoretical Construction 1.1 Introduction “The development of the concept of Political Socialization was necessitated by the complex happenings in several parts of the world. The national explosion in the Middle East, Africa, and Asia resulting in the birth of new states; the loss of dominance of the nations of the Atlantic community and the consequent diffusion of international power and influence challenged the fundamental structure of the government after the Second World War. The newly born states of Asia and Africa were confronted with the problem of nation building. They experienced difficulties in the process. It was realized that the cultural aspects of political development should also to be taken into account for nation building and political culture of a nation is the result of process of political socialization. This made the study of political socialization important and significant for all people and all societies.”1 “Political socialization gained importance in the middle of the last century. Herbert Hyman coined the word ‘Political Socialization’ in his writings in 1959. This led to systematic studies in the field of political socialization.”2 The twenty first century is characterized by radical changes due to the advent of globalization and emergence of new models of development. The exogenous forces of Globalization and Modernization have resulted into widespread transformation in the socio- economic, cultural and political system across nations Poliltical Socialization : A Conceptual and Theoretical Construction 2 of the world. The political, social and economic systems in India are also undergoing major transformation and significant changes can be seen in the normative and existential order of the society.
    [Show full text]
  • Theory for Explaining and Comparing the Dynamics of Education in Transitional Processes
    Part 1: Comparative Education & History of Education 37 Johannes L van der Walt Theory for Explaining and Comparing the Dynamics of Education in Transitional Processes Abstract Countries all over the world find themselves in the throes of revolution, change, transition or transformation. Because of the complexities of these momentous events, it is no simple matter to describe and evaluate them. This paper suggests that comparative educationists apply a combination of three theories as a lens through which such national transitions could be viewed: transitology, social action theory and critical theory. The strengths and weaknesses of each are discussed. Keywords: national transformation, education system, method of analysis, transitology, social action theory, critical theory Problem statement Virtually every country in the world has undergone some form of upheaval and change in the course of its history, some even more than once. These turbulent conditions go by a variety of names such as revolution, transformation, transition, change and as “transitional transformation” (Prica, 2007: 164). Such transformations can last up to five decades or more before “normality” seems to settle in again (Johannsen, 2000: 3; Cowes, 2002: 422). Since such upheavals affect large numbers of individuals and their relations, even entire communities, education in all its forms (informal, formal and non-formal), also politics, the economy, social structures and agriculture and so on, they are by their very nature complex phenomena and hence their dynamics very difficult to analyse, understand and compare. Due to this complexity, education systems experts and comparative educationists have need of an “instrument” to help them analyse the historical events and the educational ramifications associated with social and political upheaval.
    [Show full text]
  • The Relationships Between Organizational Socialization and Argumentation
    The Relationships between Organizational Socialization and Argumentation Chun-Te Lin, Assistant Professor, Taipei College of Maritime Technology, Taiwan Chun-Ling Lu, Associate Professor, Takming University of Science and Technology, Taiwan ABSTRACT Socialization could use for prediction or explanation of people behaviors. Some researches indicated that more organizational socialization leads to less argumentation. On the contrary, there are also other researches showed that employees in an organization might use argumentation as a mean for specific goal or purpose, those phenomena showed that more organizational socialization leads to more argumentation. We wonder which one is in reality? It became the research problem of this study. This study hypothesis is that more organizational socialization leads to more argumentation. Authors implemented survey to be examined. Study results indicated that higher organizational socialization and middle organizational socialization those two groups compare with lower organizational socialization will lead to more argumentation when conflict happened between employees. These results do not consist with previous study findings. Keywords: argumentation, social desirability, organizational socialization INTRODUCTION Scholar has indicated that Organizational socialization research exist-tage, context, and or content [44]. [4] Who argued that stage models as learning processes and stage model equivalent to the process of individual’s socialize. The newcomers’ adaptation over the course of their socialization process can also be perceived as a learning process [8, 9, 36]. Organizational socialization tactics influence newcomers' adjustment and find newcomer socialization very important for involving both learning processes and relationship-building opportunities [17]. [11] Study result thought high social-desirability of individuals is lower argumentativeness. But [12] in the “Elementary forms of social activity” thought competition is one of social actions.
    [Show full text]
  • Pragmatism, Ontology and Philosophy of the Social Sciences in Practice
    To appear in Philosophy of the Social Sciences | Revised draft, 2016-05-25 – please do not cite! Pragmatism, Ontology and Philosophy of the Social Sciences in Practice Simon Lohse Institute of Philosophy / Centre for Ethics and Law in the Life Sciences Leibniz Universität Hannover Am Klagesmarkt 14-17, 30159 Hannover, Germany Email: [email protected] Abstract In this paper, I will discuss two prominent views on the relevance and irrelevance of ontological investigations for the social sciences respectively, namely ontological foundationalism and anti- ontological pragmatism. I will argue that both views are unsatisfactory. The subsequent part of the paper will introduce an alternative role for ontological projects in the philosophy of the social sciences that fares better in this respect by paying attention to the ontological assumptions of actual social scientific theories, models and related explanatory practices. I will illustrate and support this alternative through discussion of three concrete cases. Keywords Social ontology, explanation, philosophy of science in practice, pragmatism, ontological foundationalism 1 To appear in Philosophy of the Social Sciences | Revised draft, 2016-05-25 – please do not cite! 1 Introduction This paper1 aims to contribute to the debate revolving around the relevance of ontological projects in the philosophy of the social sciences (POSS). More precisely, the paper is an attempt to respond to those neo-pragmatist philosophers who contest the usefulness of ontological investigations for the social sciences tout court and, hence, propose that we should stop pursuing ontological projects in POSS in favour of epistemological and methodological investigations (Kivinen and Piiroinen 2006, 2007; Van Bouwel and Weber 2008; Tsilipakos 2012).2 My goal here is to defend the view that ontological investigations of a certain kind can indeed be relevant for the social sciences.
    [Show full text]
  • Thesis Ecological Libertarianism
    THESIS ECOLOGICAL LIBERTARIANISM: THE CASE FOR NONHUMAN SELF-OWNERSHIP Submitted by Zachary Nelson Department of Political Science In partial fulfillment of the requirements For the Degree of Master of Arts Colorado State University Fort Collins, Colorado Spring 2016 Master’s Committee: Advisor: David McIvor Sandra Davis Lynn Hempel Copyright by Zachary Tyler Nelson 2016 All Rights Reserved ABSTRACT ECOLOGICAL LIBERTARIANISM: THE CASE FOR NONHUMAN SELF-OWNERSHIP The field of environmental political theory has made great gains in its relatively short existence as an academic discipline. One area in which these advancements can be noticed is the strong discussion surrounding the foundations, institutions, and processes of Western liberalism and the relationship of these elements to issues of environmentalism. Within this discussion has manifested the bedrock assumption that the underlying components of classical liberalism – namely individualism, negative liberties, and instrumental rationality – preclude or greatly hinder progress toward securing collective environmental needs. This assumption has great intuitive strength as well as exhibition in liberal democracies such as the United States. However, in using this assumption as a launchpad for reconsidering elements of liberalism, scholars have inadvertently closed alternate routes of analysis and theorization. This thesis aims to explore one such alternate route. Libertarianism, the contemporary reincarnation of classical liberalism, has been generally disregarded in policy and academic realms due to its stringent and inflexible adherence to self- interest, instrumental rationality, and individualism; in discussions of environment, these complaints are only augmented. These criticisms have been validated by a libertarian scholarship that emphasized nature as a warehouse of resources specifically suited for human use.
    [Show full text]
  • Subaltern Agency and Political Context Tamis Parron Unversidade D
    Vol. 13, No. 2, Winter 2016, Review / Reseña Dale T. Graden. Disease, Resistance, and Lies: the Demise of the Transatlantic Slave Trade to Brazil and Cuba. Baton Rouge: Louisiana State University, 2014. A Certain View of History, or History Itself? Subaltern Agency and Political Context Tamis Parron Unversidade de São Paulo In a 1966 edition of the Times Literary Supplement historian E. P. Thompson complained that the history of “common people has been something other than—and distinct from—English History Proper”. Thompson’s dated complaint, entitled “History from below”, launched a significant historiographical shift that has since undergone such a great change that the rare specimen Thompson searched has been institutionalized in history department worldwide under the name of “social history”1. Associated with different fields of Social Sciences—Sociology in the 1970s, Anthropology and Cultural Studies in the following decades—, the ever-changing history from below has become popular and covered a wide range of research 1 E. P. Thompson, “History from below”, Times Literary Supplement (April 7, 1966). Reproduced in Dorothy Thompson (ed.). The Essential E. P. Thompson (New York: The New Press, 2001), 481-489. Parron topics, from British labor to women in nineteenth-century Iran to black slavery in the New World. In spite of their variety, the multiple streams of social history currently practiced share some basic tenets. They describe concrete social actions by common people that suggest that abstract sociological categories designed to analyze political and economic processes fail to accommodate the plural complexity of social life. In addition, social historians argue that social systems have motions, and that such motions derive mainly from the agency of subaltern actors.
    [Show full text]
  • Are Distributions Really Structures? a Critique of the Methodology of Max Weber
    ARE DISTRIBUTIONS REALLY STRUCTURES? A CRITIQUE OF THE METHODOLOGY OF MAX WEBER Harriet Friedmann* Research Paper No. 63 *Harvard University and Centre for Urban and Community Studies University of Toronto The first draft of this paper was much improved through the criticisms and suggestions of Stephen Berkowitz, Ron Brieger, George Homans, and Harrison White. The final version emerged after several drafts, each of which benefited greatly from the detailed criticism and enthusiastic encouragement of Karen Anderson, Barry Edginton, Leslie Howard, Jack Wayne, and Barry Wellman. I wish also to express my appreciation to William Michelson and L.S. Bourne who have generously made available the facilities of the Centre for Urban and Community Studies, University of Toronto. July, 1974 Abstract Two conceptions of social structure can be distinguished: structural approaches analyze the patterns of relations among units, while distributional approaches seek to depict social structure through determining the distributions of characteristics of the units. Through explicitly developing the analytic method of constructing organized social forms from probabilistically conceived social actions, Weber systematically defined the aggregative and distributional logic which underlies much contemporary sociology. An examination of some of his most important work -- the study of bureaucracy, class and status, and charisma -- reveals that Weber abandoned his methodological strictures in favour of a more structural approach when the substantive and theore­ tical analysis required it. An understanding of the limitations of dis­ tributional conceptions of social structure points to theoretical and methodological approaches through which sociologists can build on both the distributive and the structural aspects of Weber's work. Are Distributions Really Structures? A Critique of the Methodology of Max Weber The most fundamental concept in sociology is social structure.
    [Show full text]
  • Postmodern Free Expression: a Philosophical Rationale for the Digital Age Stephen M
    Marquette Law Review Volume 100 Article 3 Issue 4 Summer 2017 Postmodern Free Expression: A Philosophical Rationale for the Digital Age Stephen M. Feldman University of Wyoming Follow this and additional works at: http://scholarship.law.marquette.edu/mulr Part of the Constitutional Law Commons, First Amendment Commons, and the Law and Philosophy Commons Repository Citation Stephen M. Feldman, Postmodern Free Expression: A Philosophical Rationale for the Digital Age, 100 Marq. L. Rev. 1123 (2017). Available at: http://scholarship.law.marquette.edu/mulr/vol100/iss4/3 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Journals at Marquette Law Scholarly Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Marquette Law Review by an authorized editor of Marquette Law Scholarly Commons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. 39332-mqt_100-4 Sheet No. 5 Side A 07/17/2017 08:32:28 ͷͷ͵ͳǦͺ͵ǦͶ͵Ǧͻ ͳǦͶʹ͵ ͷͲ͵͹ͷͻͷȋȌ ͹Ȁͳ͵ȀʹͲͳ͹ͺǣ͵͹ ͳͲͲ ʹͲͳ͹ Ͷ POSTMODERN FREE EXPRESSION: A PHILOSOPHICAL RATIONALE FOR THE DIGITAL AGE Ǥ ȗ Three philosophical rationales—search-for-truth, self-governance, and self-fulfillment—have animated discussions of free expression for decades. Each rationale emerged and attained prominence in American jurisprudence in specific political and cultural circumstances. Moreover, each rationale shares a foundational commitment to the classical liberal (modernist) self. But the three traditional rationales are incompatible with our digital age. In particular, the idea of the classical liberal self enjoying maximum liberty in a private sphere does not fit in the postmodern information society. The time for a new rationale has arrived.
    [Show full text]