CAHIERSDE TOPOLOGIE ET GÉOMÉTRIE DIFFÉRENTIELLE CATÉGORIQUES

ENRICO M.VITALE The Brauer and Brauer-Taylor groups of a symmetric monoidal category Cahiers de topologie et géométrie différentielle catégoriques, tome 37, no 2 (1996), p. 91-122

© Andrée C. Ehresmann et les auteurs, 1996, tous droits réservés. L’accès aux archives de la revue « Cahiers de topologie et géométrie différentielle catégoriques » implique l’accord avec les conditions générales d’utilisation (http://www.numdam.org/conditions). Toute utilisation commerciale ou impression systématique est constitutive d’une infraction pénale. Toute copie ou impression de ce fichier doit contenir la présente mention de copyright.

Article numérisé dans le cadre du programme Numérisation de documents anciens mathématiques http://www.numdam.org/ CAHIERS DE TOPOLOGIE ET Volume XXXVII-2 (1996) GEOMETRIE DIFFERENTIELLE CA TEGORIQUES

THE BRAUER AND BRAUER -TAYLOR GROUPS OF A SYMMETRIC MONOIDAL CATEGORY by Enrico M. VITALE

Rgsum6. Les groupes de Brauer et de Brauer-Taylor d’une categorie monoidale symetrique C sont definis comme etant les groupes de Picard de categories mon6fdales symetriques convenables construites a partir de C. Si C est la cat6gorie des modules sur un anneau commutatif unitaire, on retrouve les groupes usuels. On utilise cette definition pour construire une suite exacte reliant le groupe de Picard et le groupe de Brauer.

Introduction

If R is a commutative unital , the Brauer group B (R) of R is the group of Morita-equivalence classes of Azumaya R-algebras. Several equivalent definitions of Azumaya R-algebra are known. Most of them can be used to define an Azumaya C-, where C is a symmetric monoidal category satisfying some extra conditions as closure and some kind of completeness. The different Brauer groups which arise in this way are not necessarily isomorphic, but each of them coincides with the Brauer group B(R) if C is the category of modules over R. It is quite surprising that the simplest possible description of B(R), has been neglected in all the previous categorical approaches to the Brauer group (at least at my knowledge). In fact we can define B(R) as the Picard group of the monoidal category of unital of C, taking bimodules as arrows. The author aknowledges support of NATO grant CRG 941330

91 In section 1 we show that this definition is available in a monoidal category C satisfying very weak conditions, that is C must be symmetric and must have stable coequalizers. Then, assuming more on C, we point out that this definition is equivalent to other possible definitions. We close the first section quoting some examples. In to illustrate the usefulness of the simple definition of B(C), in section 2 we obtain, in a quite straightforward way, exact sequences between Brauer groups and Picard groups. when R is a , B(R) is isomorphic to the second étale- group of R. If R is only a commutative unital ring, B(R) is the torsion subgroup of the cohomology group. The full cohomology group is then isomorphic to the so-called Brauer-Taylor group of R. The third and the fourth sections are devoted to a categorical de- scription of the Brauer-Taylor group of a symmetric monoidal category C. It seems to me a nice fact that, even when C is the category of mod- ules over R, this categorical description is simpler than the classical one. I would like to thank F. Borceux for his lectures on the Brauer group at the Category Seminar in Louvain-la-Neuve, and A. Carboni and F. Grandjean for a lot of useful discussion on this topic. I have also benefitted from numerous comments and suggestions the anonimous referee has made on an earlier version of this work.

1 The Brauer group

Let us fix some notations. In all the work C = (C, (&7 I, .... ) is a symmetric monoidal category with stable coequalizers (that is, if

is a coequalizer, then, for each object Z of C,

92 is again a coequalizer; this condition is clearly satisfied if C is closed). A monoid A = (A, MA: A 0 A -A) in C is always associative. If it is unital, we denote by eA: I -·A its unit. A module AI = (M, uM: A 0 1B;1 --+-lvl) in C is always associative, but not necessarily unital. In all the work R is a unital and RMod is the category of unital modules over R. If M is a unital monoid (in Set), the obvious way to build up a group from M is to take the set of invertible elements. This is the so called Picard group Pic( ) of M and it is abelian if M is commutative. If M is a monoidal category, the isomorphism classes of objects form a monoids (M0/ 2) (commutative if M is symmetric). The Picard group Pic(M) of Ji4 is, by definition, the Picard group of the monoid (Mol ry), Now the Brauer group: let C be a symmetric monoidal category as at the beginning of the section. We can build up a new symmetric monoidal category UMon(C) in the following way:

- objects are unital monoids

- arrows are isomorphism classes of unital bimodules

- composition: given two bimodules M: A-B and N: B-C, their composition is MQ9BN: A-C (recall that M0BN is the coequalizer of

- identities: the identity arrow on a monoid A is A itself

- : the tensor of C.

The crucial point is that the tensor product of C gives rise to a functor

We do not prove this fact here, because it follows from lemma 2.3. Let us only observe that it can also be deduced, using the stability of coequalizers, from the following lemma

93 Lemma 1.1 Consider two coequalizers in C

if f and g have a common section (that is if there exists h: Y-X such that h. f = 1Y = h. g) and if the same holds for f’ and g’, then

i.s a coequalizer.

Let me insist on the fact that the commutativity of a diagram in UMOll(C) is up to isomorphisms in C. For example, two unital monoids A and B are isomorphic in UMon(C) (we will say equ2valent) if there ex- ist two unital bimodules M: A - B and N: B - A such that MOBN and N0AM are isomorphic, in C, respectively to A and B. Now we define the first Brauer groups B1 (C) of C as the Picard group of UMon(C) (the reason for the "first" will be clear at the end of the third section). In other words, a unital monoid A is Azumaya if there exists a unital monoid A* such that A 0 A* is equivalent to I. The first Brauer group is then the group of equivalence classes of Azumaya C-monoids. It is known that, if C is RMod, then 81 (C) is the usual Brauer group of R (cf. [35]). Let us now give a glance at the classical definition of Azumaya R- algebra (cf. [2], [19], [25], [28], [35]). An R-algebra A is Azumaya if it satisfies one of the following equivalent conditions:

- there exists an R-algebra A* such that AO A* is Morita-equivalent to R

- A0AD is Morita-equivalent to R (where A° is the opposite algebra of A)

- A is a faithfully projective R-module and the canonical morphism .

is an isomorphism (where LinR (A, A) is the R-module of R-linear transformations from A to A)

94 - A is central and separable.

With this situation in mind, let us look for equivalent definitions of Azumaya C-monoid. We need some notations: the bimodule yA: I - A 0Ao is A with its natural structure of right AOA°-module, the bimodule EA: A°O A-----..I is A with its natural structure of left A O A°-module.

Proposition 1.2 Let A be a unital C-monoid; the following conditions are equivalent: i - A is Azumaya

1i - EA: AO 0 A - I is an isomorphism in UMon(C)

iii - qA : I -AO A° is an isom oxph isrn in UMon (C)

Proof : Recall that, in a monoidal category JIiI, an object X is left ad- joint to an object X * , X -l X * , if there exist two arrows n: I -XOX* and c: X* O X - I such that the following diagrams are commutative

(cf. [18]). Moreover, if X O Y 2 I and Y 0 X rr I , then X -1 Y and unit and counit are invertible (this is a particular case of a 2-categorical argument: given an equivalence, it is always possible to build up an adjoint equivalence (cf. [17]). In UMOll(C) we have that A -1 A° with unit given by 77A: I - A O A° and counit given by EA: A° 0 A -I. If A is Azumaya, then, by uniqueness of the adjoint, A* is equivalent to A° and qA and fA are isomorphisms. The converse implications are obvious. r

To say more on the notion of Azumaya C-monoid, we need some facts which are part of Morita theory. The proof can be found in any of the sources quoted in the first remark at the end of the section.

95 Proposition 1.3 Let P: A-B be a bimodule; the following condi- tions are equivalent:

- P: A - B is an isomorphism in UMon(C)

- the functor between module categories POB-: B - mod-----A - mod induced by P is an equivalence of categories

- the right adjoint PDA-: A - mod- B - mod of Pø B - is an equivalence of categories

- P is faithfully projective as A-module and B is canonically iso- morphic (as monoid of C) to P D A P

D

(Recall that the right adjoint PDA - certainly exists if C is closed and has equalizers. Faithfully projective means that the internal com- positions

are isomorphisms.) We can apply the previous propositions to the bimodules nA : I - A 0Ao and fA: AO 0 A---..I. We obtain respectively:

iv - an unital C-monoid A is Azumaya if and only if it is faithfully projective in C and the canonical arrow A Q9 A°-A D A is an isomorphism

v - an unital C-monoid A is Azumaya if and only if it is faithfully projective in A°OA-mod and the canonical arrow I-A)A°OAA is an isomorphism.

This last characterization needs a comment: when C is RMod, it is equivalent to say that A is central and separable. Central because A)°OAA is the of A. As far as separability is concerned, re- call that A is separable if the multiplication A 0 A -· A admits a section A-linear on the left and on the right. But this is equivalent to

96 say that A is projective in Ao O A-mod. Clearly, A is finitely generated as A° 0 A-module. Finally, Auslander-Goldman theorem asserts that if A is central and separable, then it is a generator for the category A° O A-mod, so that it is faithfully projective in this category (cf. [2]).

Remarks and examples I - Several categorical approaches to Morita theory are available in literature. Among them, the items [3], [13], [20], [26], [31] in the bibliography. Each of them contains (some variant of) proposition 1.3. This proposition is certainly true, for general enriched category theory reasons (cf. [20]), if C is a complete and cocomplete symmetric monoidal closed category. But the assumption on C to develop Morita theory can be weakened. For example, in [26], closure is avoided (but to the detriment of the internal character of the theory) and in [31] symmetry is not required. II - We have just discussed the equivalence between five possible definitions of Azumaya C-monoid. All of them, with the exception of the first one, have been individually considered in other works in which a categorical approach to Brauer group can be found. They are items [11], [12], [15], [26] in the bibliography. Even the definition of separability via the existence of a Casimir-element has been considered in [11] and [26]. III - In the works quoted in the previous remark, several examples of Brauer groups are discussed from a categorical point of view. This means that a group built up "à la Brauer" from a certain gadget is nothing that the Brauer group of a suitable monoidal category. We recall here

- the Brauer group of a commutative ringed space, introduced in [1] and considered in [12] and [15];

- the Brauer-Wall group, introduced in [33] (and generalized in [21]) and considered in [11] and [12];

- the relative Brauer group, introduced in [30] and considered in [23],-

97. - the Brauer group of module algebras for a cocommutative Hopf- algebra, introduced in [22] and considered in [11] and [26].

IV - a quite different example arises if we consider, as base cate- gory, the category SL of sup-lattices instead of the category of abelian groups. A monoid in SL is a quantale so that it is possible to defined the Brauer group of a commutative unital quantale Q as the Brauer group of the monoidal category Q-mod of modules over Q. The corresponding Morita-theory has been studied in [7] and the key notion of faithfully projective Q-module turns out to be the following: a Q-module P is faithfully projective if and only if there exist two sets X and Y such that P is a retract of Qx and Q is a retract of Py (where Qx and P’ are the X-indexed and the Y-indexed powers of Q and P). By the way, the classical Brauer group B(IR) is a small group. This is because an Azumaya R-algebra is, in particular, a faithfully projective R-module and the category of faithfully projective R-modules is small. This is no longer true for Q-modules. It is an open problem to find conditions on C such that the Brauer group of C is small. V - Another example is provided by a commutative algebraic theory T. The models of T constitute a complete and cocomplete symmetric monoidal closed category (cf. [6] and [34]). The corresponding Morita- theory has been studied in [8] and [10]. This example requires some more efforts and will be discussed in detail in a separated paper.

2 Exact sequences

In this section we build up an exact sequence between Picard groups and Brauer groups. Let us consider two symmetric monoidal categories with stable co- equalizers C = (C, O, I, ... ) and D = (D, 0, J, ...) . Let F: C-D be a monoidal functor such that

i - F preserves coequalizers

ii - F is strict on invertible bimodules and on Azumaya C-monoids

98 iii - the morphism J--F(I) is an isomorphism

For such a functor F, it is straightforward to prove the following lemma: Lemma 2.1

- if M: A ----B is an invertible bimodule between two Azumaya C- monoids, then FM: FA - FB is an invertible bimodule between Azumaya D-monoids

- if A M B N- C are invertible bimodules between Azumaya C- monoids, then F(M0BN) is isomorphic to FM0FBFN.

The previous lemma allows us to build up a new symmetric monoidal category F in the following way:

- objects are invertible bimodules of the form X: FA-·FB, where A and B are two specified Azumaya C-monoids

- an arrow between two objects ( : FA - FB) and (Y: FC - FD) is a pair of invertible bimodules M: A -C and N: B - D such that the following diagram is commutative

- composition and identities are the obvious ones

- the tensor product of (X: FA---FB) and (Y:FC---+-FD) is given by (X O Y: P(A Q9 C)-F(BO D))

- the unit of the tensor is given by ( J: FI- FI) .

99 Again a notation: if M is a monoidal category, I(M) is the monoidal subcategory of invertible objects and isomorphisms. Clearly, Pic(M) and Pic(I(M)) are equal. Starting from the functor F: C->D, we can define the following four functors: (1) F:I(C)->I(D) which is simply the restriction of F:C->D (2) Fl: I(D)->F defined by

(observe that an object of the form (X: FI->FI) is invertible with respect to the tensor product of F) (3) F2 : F -> I(UMon(C)) defined by

(4) F:I(UMon(C))->(UMon(D)) defined by

(this definition makes sense by lemma 2.1).

All these functors are strict monoidal functors, so that, passing to the Picard groups, we obtain four group homomorphisms (square brackets are isomorphism classes)

100 Proposition 2.2 The sequence

is a complex; moreover, it is exact in Pic(D) and in 81 (CC). Proof :

- f . f1 = 0 because if X is in I(C), then (FX: FI-FI) is iso- morphic in F to (J: F7->FI); the isomorphism is given by

- fl. f2 = 0 because I@I° is isomorphic (in C and then in UMon((C)) to I

- f2 - 7 = 0 because, if X: FA-FB is an invertible bimodule, then FA@ FB° is equivalent to FB 0 FB° and then to J (recall that B is Azumaya)

- exactness in Pic(D): let Y be an object of I(D) and suppose that [V] E Ker f 1. This means that (Y: FI-FI) and ( J: FI-FI) are isomorphic in F. Let

be the isormorphism in F. One has that Y is isomorphic in D to F(M Q9 N-1) so that [Y] = [F(M @ N-1)] E Im f

101 - exactness in B1(C) : let A be an object of I(UMon(C)) and sup- pose that [A] E Kerf. This means that there exists an invertible bimodule X: F.4 -> FI. One has f2 [X: FA -> FI] = [A @ I°] = [A].

0

Let me now discuss the exactness in Pic(F). Let [X : FA -> FB] be in Ker f2 This means that A 0 BO is equivalent to I. Then A is equivalent to B. Let Y: B -> A be the isomorphism. We have that

is an isomorphism in T. Clearly, if (X: FA----FB) is invertible with respect to the tensor product of F, also (X0FBFY: FA -> FA) is invertible. All this means that, as representative of an element in Ker f2, we can always choose an object of F of the form (X: FA ---- FA). We wonder if [X : FA - FA] is in Im fl . This is not true in general. What is true is that [X : FA - FA] + [F.4": FA° -> FA°] is in Im f1. (Observe that [FA° : FA -> FA°] is in Pic(.F) because (FA° : FA° -> FA°) is invertible with respect to the tensor product of F, the inverse is given by (FA: FA-.FA).) To prove that [X @ FA°: F(A @ A-) F(A 0 A°)] is in Im fl, we can observe that

102 is an isomorphism in F, so that is equal to

It only remains to observe that the elements of the form [FA : FA--FA) constitute a subgroup of Pic(F), say N, and that they are contained in the kernel of f2 (exactly because A is Azumaya). Let us consider the canonical projection rr: Pic(F) -> Pic(F)/ and let us call f’2:Pic(F)/N -> B1 (C) the unique factorization of f2 through 7r. We are ready to prove the following proposition. Proposition 2.3 The sequence

is exact.

Proof: The fact that the sequence is a complex as well as the exact- ness in B1 (C) come from proposition 2.2 because 1r is an epimorphism.

- Exactness in Pic(D) : the argument is the same as in proposition 2.2, but replacing J: FI -> FI by FA: F’A -> FA and M @ N-1 by M @ AN-1.

- Exactness in Pic(F)jN : it follows from the previous discussion since [X: FA - FA] and [X: FA -> FA] + [FA°: FA° -> FA°] are equal in Pic(F)/N.

We have just constructed, in a very elementary way, an exact se- quence between Picard groups and Brauer groups. Another way, clas- sically used to build up such a sequence, is based on standard K- theoretical arguments (cf. [5] and [16]). This is possible also in our categorical framework, via the following proposition. For the defini- tions of the Grothendieck group Ko and of the Whitehead group Kl , the reader can consult [5].

103 Proposition 2.4

i - the Grothendieck group Ko (I (UMon(C))) is isomorphic to B1(C)

ii - the Whitehead group K1(I(UMon(C))) is isomorphic to Pic(C)

Yroof: i - obvious because 7(UMon(C)) is a monoidal groupoid in which each object is invertible; ii - consider the category 52(I(UMon((C))) defined as follows

- objects are endomorphisms X: A -> A in I(UMon(C))

- an arrow is a commutative diagram in 7(UMon(C))

- composition and identities are the obvious ones.

In this category we can define a tensor product of X: A -> A and Y: B -> B by X0Y: A @ B -> A @ B and a composition of X: A -> A and Y: A -> A by X0AY: A -> A. To obtain an isomorphism K1(I(UMon(C))) -> Pic(C), we need a map on objects such that 1) y sends isomorphic objects into isomorphic objects

2) y preserves the tensor product 3) q sends composition into tensor product 4) q is essentially surjective 5) if y(X: A-.A) is isomorphic to I in I((C), then X: A-A is isomorphic to A: A-·A in Q(I(UMon(C)))

104 Conditions 1), 2) and 3) imply the existence of a group homomorphism which is surjective by condition 4). Condition 5), together with lemma 2.5, implies the injectivity of 7. We define 1: Q(I(UMon((C))) -> I((C) by

Let us now verify the five conditions. 1) Let

be an isomorphism in S2(I(UMon((C))). Up to isomorphism in C, y(Y) is

Now observe that, since M is invertible,

105. is a unit for the adjunction A H A° in UMon(C). This implies that there exists a unique invertible bimodule a : A° -> A° such that the following diagram commutes

Finally, the following diagram is commutative in each part, so that y(X) is isomorphic in C to -y(Y).

2) straightforward, using the fact that, given two unital monoids A and B, 1/Atg;B is (isomorphic to) nA @ nB 3) let A-K.-A-X..A be two composable objects of Q(I(UMon(C))). The following diagram is commutative

106 so that 1(X0AY) is isomorphic to 1(X)011(Y), that is to y(X)0 1(Y)

4) let X be an invertible object of C and let A be any Azumaya C- monoid. Then -y of X (9 A: A = I @ A ---+- I 0 A - A is isomorphic to X

5) consider an object X: A-A in Q(I(Umon(C))) such that the following diagram commutes

that is such that q(X) is isomorphic to I. An isomorphism

in S2(I(UMon((C))) can be obtained taking as M the composition

107 Lemma 2.5 Let M be a monoidal groupoid with unital object I and let A be any object of M ; in Ko(Q(M)) one has that the class of idA: A -> A is equal to the class of id/: I -> I, which is the zero of Ko(Q(M)).

Proof:.- Easy from 1.2 in [4]. To obtain an exact sequence between Picard groups and Brauer groups, it only remains to observe that, if F: C -> D is a functor as at the beginning of the section, then the induced functor

is cofinal (cf.[4]). In fact, if A is an object in 7(UMon(B)), then there exists an object B in I(Umon(D)) and an object C in I(UMon((C)) such that F(C) is equivalent to A @ B. It suffices to take A° as B and I as C.

Remarks I - The existence of an exact sequence between Picard groups and Brauer groups has been established also in [15], using K-theoretical ar- guments and working on categories which satisfy an analogue of proposi- tion 1.3. If this proposition holds, then two Azumaya C-monoids A and B are isomorphic in UMon(C) if and only if there exist two faithfully projective objects P and Q such that A (9 (P D P) and B 0 (Q D Q) are isomorphic as monoids in C. In [15] this fact is extensively used. This makes explicit calculations quite different from those presented in this section. II - As far as the assumptions on F: C -> D are concerned, we refer to [15], where these assumptions are discussed in some relevant exam- ples. Let us only observe here that an easy example is provided by the left adjoint of the change of base functor induced by a morphism of unital commutative rings. This left adjoint is, in fact, a strict monoidal functor. III - A careful analysis of the proof of proposition 2.4, as well as the simple proof of proposition 1.2, suggests that a further generalization of the theory can be obtained taking as primitive the bicategory B =

108 UMon(C) and defining C as B(I, 1). Such a theory could be so general to contain, as an example, the categorical Brauer group, taking as B the bicategory of small C-categories and C-distributors. The categorical Brauer group has, for elements, classes of Azumaya C-categories and has been studied, for C = RMod, in [24]. For a more general C, some elementary observations on the categorical Brauer group are contained in [32], but much more remains to do in this direction.

3 The Brauer-Taylor group

The Picard group of R is isomorphic to the first étale-cohomology group of R. On the contrary, the Brauer group is only the torsion ’subgroup of the second étale-cohomology group (cf. [14]). A purely algebraic description of the whole second cohomology group is provided by the Brauer-Taylor group (cf. [29], [27] and [9]). In this and in the next section we look for a categorical description of the Brauer-Taylor group. We will work as at the beginning of the first section. To start, we need some definitions: we want monoids and modules not necessarily unital, but such that some points of Morita theory hold (cf. lemma 4.2). Definition 3.1

a) a monoid A is regular if the canonical map A0AA---+A is an isomorphism

b) a monoid A is splitting if there exists ç A : A ---. A 0 A such that the following diagrams are commutative

c) a module M is regular if the canonical map A 0A M--.M is an isomorphism

109 d) if A is a splitting monoid (with section CPA), a module M is split- ting (with respect to çA) if there exists cpM: M ----. A 0 M such that the following diagrams are commutative

In the next proposition we compare the notions of unital, splitting and regular modules. Proposition 3.2

1) if A is unital and M is unital, then M is splitting (with çM given by e A @ 1 : M = I @ M -> A @ M; in particular, if A is unital, then A is splitting 2) if A is splitting and M is splitting, then M is regular; in particular, if A is splitting, then A is regular 3) if A is splitting and M is regular, then M is splitting 4) if A is unital and M is splitting, then M is unital. Proof. 1): obvious. 2): the associativity of M, the first condition of splitness on A and the splitness of M say exactly that the following diagram is a splitting fork (with sections given by ç M : M -> A 0 M and wA 0 1: A (9 M - A 0 A 0 M) and then 03BCM is an absolute coequalizer

3): if t : A @ A M -> M is the canonical isomorphism, it suffices to define the section cP M: M -> A 0 M as

110 (which is possible because the second condition of splitness on A says that CPA is A-linear on the right). 4): since A is unital, çA : A -> A @ A is given by eA @ 1: A - 1 0 A--+-A 0 A. Then, using the fact that jim is an epimorphism and the second condition of splitness on M, one can prove that ç M : M -----. A 0 M is given by eA @ 1: M ri I @ M -> A @ M. Now the first condition of splitness on M means that M is unital. In definition 3.1, modules are left modules and the second condition on CPA means that it is right linear. Let us say that in this case A is right splitting. One can consider left splitting monoids and the analogue of proposition 3.2 holds for right modules. We call a monoid A bisplitting if its multiplication MA : A 0 A-A admits a right linear section and a left linear section (not necessarily equal). The fundamental example of bisplitting monoids are the elementary algebras which will be studied in the next section. Now the Brauer-Taylor group. Given the symmetric monoidal cate- gory C, we can build up a new symmetric monoidal category SMon(C) in the following way:

- objects are bisplitting monoids

- arrows are isomorphism classes of regular bimudules

- composition: given two bimodules M : A -> B and N: B -> C, their composition is M 0B N: A-·C

- identities: the identity arrow on a monoid A is A itself

- tensor product: the tensor of C. Once again, the crucial point is that the tensor product of C induces a tensor product in SMon(C). We give the proof of this fact in the following lemma.

111 Lemma 3.3 The functor 0: C x C-C induces a functor

Proof: consider the bimodules A ->M B N -> C and D-> X E -> Y F. The actions involved in the proof are 03BC : M @ B -> M, 17: B @ N -> N, (/?: X 0 E -> X and Y: E 0 Y -> Y. We need to prove that

The second object is the codomain of the coequalizer q of the following pair of parallel arrows

Consider also the two coequalizers

(At this point if A and E are unital, one could use lemma 1.1 taking as common sections the units and the proof would be achieved.) Clearly, ?i 0 q2 coequalizes p 0 1 @ ç @ 1 and 1 @ n @ 1 @ y, so that there exists a unique arrow r: (M @ X) @ B @ E(N @ Y) - (M 0B N) @ (X @ E Y) such that q. r = q1 @ q2. Now the problem is to show that q coequalizes the two following pairs of parallel arrows

112 Once this is done, the proof runs as follows: since q coequalizes (2), there exists a unique arrow P2 such that the following diagram commutes

From the previous equation and since q coequalizes (1), an easy diagram chasing shows that there exists a unique arrow PI such that the following diagram commutes

The arrows PI and r give the required isomorphism. It remains to show that q coequalizes (1) and (2). We do the first verification, the second is analogue. Since B is splitting and M is regular, we know from proposition 3.2 that there exists a section B : M -> M @ B for the action 03BC : M 0 B-M. Analogously, there exists a section E: X -X Q5) E for the action ç: X Q5) E -> E. Now to conclude the proof it suffices to write in diagrammatic terms the follow- ing "elementary" argument: if m E M, n E N, x E X, y E Y, e E E and if B (m) == m’ @ b’, c(x) = x’ Q5) e’ with m’ c- M, b’ c- B, x’ c- X, e’ E E, then m®n®x-e®y = m’-b’®n®(x’-e’)-e®y = m’-b’®n®.-(e’-e)®y = m’®b’-n®x’®(e’-e)-y = m’®b’-n®x’®e’-(e-y) = m’-b’®n®x’-e’®e.y = m Q5) n Q5) x 0 e . y.. Now we can define the first Brauer-Taylor group BTI (C) of C as the Picard group of SMon(C). By proposition 3.2, we have that a bimodule between unital monoids is regular if and only if it is unital. This means that UMon(C) is a

113 full monoidal subcategory of SMon(C). This implies that B1(C) is a subgroup of BT1 (C). If we take as C the category RMod, 8Tl (C) is in general bigger than the Brauer-Taylor group of R as defined in [29]. To obtain exactly the Brauer-Taylor group of R we need a further condition on the objects of SMon(C), that is we consider the full monoidal subcategory RSMon(C) of SMon(C) whose objects are bisplitting monoids which contain I as a retract in C. Now we define the second Brauer-Taylor group 872(C) of C as the Picard group of RSMon(C). Clearly we can add the retract condition also in UMon(C) and define in this way the second Brauer group of C. The following two diagrams summarize the situation: in the left one, arrows are full monoidal inclusions; in the right one, arrows are inclusions of subgroups.

If C is RMod, both Bi (C) and B2 (C) coincide with the classical Brauer group of R. As far as 82(C) is concerned, recall that, if a unital R- algebra A is faithfully projective as R-module, then A contains R as a retract; in other words, the invertible objects of UMon(C) are contained in RUMon(C) if we take as C the category of modules over R. (The same argument holds when C is the category of modules over a commutative unital quantale.) Moreover, BT 2 (C) coincides with the usual Brauer- Taylor group of R. This will be proved in the next section.

4 Elementary algebras

Given a morphism k : Y @ X ---.1 in C which admits a section ,s: I -- Y 0 X, we can build up a monoid Ea = (X @ Y, mk) with multi- plication ma given by 1 @ k @ 1 : X @ Y @ X @ Y -> X @ I @ Y = X @ Y. We call Ea the elementary adgebra associated with À. It is a bisplit- ting monoid. And even more: it is a separable monoid, that is mk

114 admits a section wx : Ek -> Ek @ Ex which is at the same time left and right linear. For this, it suffices to define cpa as 1 @ s @ 1 : X @ Y = X 0 I @ Y -> X @ Y 0 X Q9 Y. Clearly, Ea contains I as a retract. If (C is closed and I is regular projective, an example of (not necessar- ily unital) elementary algebra can be obtained taking as Y a generator of C, as X the dual of Y and as A the evaluation (generator means that the internal composition Y @ Y D Y (Y D I) -> I is an isomorphism). In particular, if C is RMod, as Y one can take any (not necessarily fi- nite) power of C. Elementary algebras with unit will be considered in proposition 4.7. The next proposition gives an equivalent description of the first and the second Brauer-Taylor group of C. Proposition 4.1 1) Ek is isomorphic to I in SMon(C) 2) if I is regular projective in C and if E is isomorphic to I in SMon((C), then E is isomorphic (as monoid of C) to a suitable elementary algebra Ea (here regular projective means that each regular epimorphism with codomain I has a section).

Since the additional condition on I is clearly satisfied if we choose as C the category RMod, we can use the previous proposition to prove that in this case the second Brauer-Taylor group of C is the usual Brauer- Taylor group of R. As far as the proof of proposition 4.1 is concerned, we need some points of terminology and some lemmas. Definition 4.2

- a set of pre-equivalence data (or Morita context) is a pair of ar- rows P: A-.B and Q: B -A in SMon(C) together with two bimodule homomorphisms f: P 0B Q--.A and g: Q 0A P -> B

- a set of equivalence data (or strict Morita context) is a set of pre- equivalence data (A, B, P, Q, f, g) such that f and g are bimodule isomorphisms.

115 In other words, (A, B, P, Q, f , g) is a set of equivalence data exactly when the regular bimodules P: A -> B and Q: B -> A give an isomor- phism in SMon(C). Lemma 4.3 If (A, B, P, Q, f , g) is a set of equivalence data, then

constitute an equivalence of categories (where mod-A is the category of regular right A-modules and mod-B is the category of regular right B-modules). In particular, - 0A P is full and faithful. The previous lemma is the trivial part of Morita theory, which clearly holds also for splitting monoids. Lemma 4.4 If (A, B, P, Q, f, g) is a set of equivalence data, with no lost of generality we can suppose f and g associative, that is such that the following diagrams are commutative

Proof : we generalize proposition 3.1 (3) in [5] avoiding units. Let us call t: A Q9 A P- P and t’: P ®n B -> P the canonical isomorphisms, which are bimodule isomorphisms. Consider the bimodule isomorphism u: A ®A P-A 0A P given by (f-1 OA 1p). ( l P f2;;B g) ’ t’ ’ t-1. Since - ®A P: mod-A -> mod-B is full and faithful, u is of the form u’ 0A 1 for an isomorphism u’: A---·A in mod-A. Since u is A-linear on the left and - 0A P is faithful, also u’ is A-linear on the left. If we replace f by f ’ u’, we obtain the first associativity. The second associativity follows from the first one, using once again that - Q9 A P is faithful. Lemma 4.5 If (A, B, P, Q, f, g) is a set of pre-equiYalence data with f and g associative and if f has a left linear section, then f is an isomorphism of bimodules.

116 Proof: let x be the section of f . Using the two associativities of f and g, a diagram chasing argument shows that the following diagram is commutatve

We can now come back to proposition 4.1. Proof of propositions 4.1: 1) : consider an arrow A: Y 0 X -> I with section s: I- Y 0 X and consider the elementary algebra Ea = (X 0 Y, mk) defined at the beginning of the section. To show that Ex is equivalent to I , we build up a set of equivalence data (1, EA, Y, X, f , g) in the following way. The actions are A 01: Y ® Ek = Y ® X ® Y -> I ® Y = Yand 1 @ k : Ek @ X = X @ Y @ X -> X @ I = X. This two modules are splitting (the sections are s 0 1 and 1 0 s) and then, by proposition 3.2, they are regular. As g: X ®I Y-Ex we take the identity. The definition of f is given by the following diagram, where q is the coequalizer,

It is easy to show that f and g are associative. Moreover, f has a section (given by s. q: I - Y 0 X -> Y 0E X) so that, by lemma 4.5, it is an

117 isomorphism. 2): let (E, I, P, Q, f, g) be a set of equivalence data giving the isomor- phism between E and I in SMon(C). Consider the coequalizer

The composite A = q . g: Q 0 P-Q 0E P -> = I is a regular epi- morphism, and then, since I is regular projective, it has a section s : I -> Q @ P. Clearly, the bimodule isomorphism f : P @ Q -> E gives an isomorphism in C between the elementary algebra EA and E. The fact that f is indeed an isomorphism of monoids follows from the asso- ciativity of f and g, which is guaranteed by lemma 4.4. As a consequence of proposition 4.1, we obtain the following de- scription of the first Brauer-Taylor group of C: the group 871(C) is the (possibly large) set of equivalence classes of bisplitting monoids A such that there exists a bisplitting monoid B and an elementary algebra Ex isomorphic (as monoid of C) to A ® B; two monoids A and A’ of this kind are equivalent if there exist two elementary algebras EÀ and Ek, such that A 0 Ek and A’ 0 Ek, are isomorphic (as monoids of C). An analogous description holds for the second Brauer-Taylor group, adding on monoids the condition to contain I as a retract. A warning: to verify in details, via proposition 4.1, that the previous description of the Brauer-Taylor groups of C is equivalent to that given in section 3, one uses everywhere that, if A and B are isomorphic as bisplitting monoids of C, then they are isomorphic in SMon(C). This can be proved as follows: if f: A-B is an isomorphism of monoids and A is right splitting, we can provide B with the structure of a left A-module via A @ B ->f@1 B @ B ->mB B ; to prove that B is regular, we can take as section B f-1 -> A ç A -> A @ A 1@f -> A 0 B (where (PA is the section of mA) . Finally, we can consider the classical case. Corollary 4.6 If C is the category RMod of unital modules over an unital commutative ring R, then BT2(C) is the Brauer-Taylor group of R.

118 Proof: let us recall that, in any abelian category, an object X con- tains an object Y as a direct summand if and only if Y is a retract of X. Now, using our proposition 4.1, the statement follows from proposition 2.2, proposition 3. lo (and its proof) and proposition 4.4 in [29]. In general, in the situation of the previous corollary, BT1 (C) is big- ger than the Brauer-Taylor group of R. This is because, unlike the case of unital monoids, if A and B are splitting monoids such that A @ B is an elementary algebra (and then contains I as a retract), one cannot deduce that A (and B) contains I as a retract. To end the work, let us come back to the Brauer group. Recall that, if C is closed, an object Y is faithfully projective (or a progenerator) if the internal compositions

are isomorphisms. Proposition 4.7 Let C be a closed symmetric monoidal category with coequalizers and suppose I is regular projective. Elementary algebras with unit are exactly monoids of the form Y D Y with Y faithfully projective.

Proof: from our proposition 4.1 and proposition 7.3 in [31], using once again only the trivial part of Morita theory. From propositions 4.1 and 4.7, we obtain an equivalent description of the Brauer groups of C in terms of equivalence classes of unital monoids. It is like the description given for Brauer-Taylor groups, but we can replace elementary algebras by monoids of the form Y D Y with Y faithfully projective. If we specialize this description with RMod for C, we obtain the description of B(R) originally given by Auslander and Goldman in [2].

References

[1] AUSLANDER B: The Brauer group of a ringed space, J. Alge- bra 4 (1966), pp. 220-273.

119 [2] AUSLANDER M. & GOLDMAN O.: The Brauer group of a commutative ring, Trans. Amer. Math. Soc. 97 (1960), pp. 367-409.

[3] BARJA PEREZ J.M.: Teoremas de Morita para triples en cat- egorias cerradas, Alxebra 20 (1978). [4] BASS H.: Topics in Algebraic K-Theory, Tata Institut of Fundamental Research, Bombay (1967). [5] BASS H.: Algebraic K-Theory, W.A. Benjamin Inc. (1968). [6] BORCEUX F.: Handbook of Categorical Algebra 2, Encyclo- pedia of Math. 51, Cambridge University Press (1994). [7] BORCEUX F. & VITALE E.M.: A Morita theorem in topology, Suppl. Rend. Circ. Mat. Palermo II-29 (1992), pp. 353-362. [8] BORCEUX F. & VITALE E.M.: On the notion of bimodel for functorial semantics, Applied Categorical Structures 2 (1994), pp. 283-295.

[9] CAENEPEEL S.: Etale cohomology and the Brauer group, to appear. [10] DUKARM J.: Morita equivalences of algebraic theories, Collo- quium Mathematicum 55 (1988) pp. 11-17.

[11] FERNÁNDEZ VILABOA J.M.: Grupes de Brauer y de Galois de un algebra de Hopf en una categoria cerrada, Alxebra 42 (1985).

[12] FISCHER-PALMQUIST J.: The Brauer group of a closed cate- gory, Proc. Amer. Math. Soc. 50 (1975), pp. 61-67.

[13] FISCHER-PALMQUIST J. & PALMQUIST P.H.: Morita con- texts of enriched categories, Proc. Amer. Math. Soc. 50 (1975), pp. 55-60.

120 [14] GABBER O.: Some theorems on Azumaya algebras, L. N. in Math. 844, Springer-Verlag (1988). Ph. D. [15] GONZÁLEZ RODRÍGUEZ R.: La sucesión exacta ..., Thesis, Santiago de Compostela (1994). [16] HELLER A.: Some exact sequences in algebraic K-theory, Topology 3 (1965), pp. 389-408. [17] KELLY G.M.: Basic concepts of enriched category theories, London Math. Soc. L. N. 64, Cambridge University Press (1982). [18] KELLY G.M. & LAPLAZA M.L.: Coherence for compact closed categories, J. Pure Appl. Algebra 19 (1980), pp. 193- 213.

[19] KNUS M.A. & OJANGUREN M.: Théorie de Descente et Algèbres d’Azumaya, L. N. in Math 389, Springer-Verlag (1974). [20] LINDNER H: Morita equivalences of enriched categories, Cahiers Top. Géo. Diff. XV-4 (1974), pp. 377-397.

[21] LONG F.W.: A generalization of Brauer group of graded al- gebras, Proc. London Math. Soc. 29 (1974), pp. 237-256.

[22] LONG F.W.: The Brauer group of dimodule algebras, J. Al- gebra 30 (1974), pp. 559-601. [23] LÓPEZ LÓPEZ M.P. & VILLANUEVA NOVOA E.: The Brauer group of the category (R, 03C3)-Mod, Proc. First Belgian-Spanish week on Algebra and Geometry (1988). [24] MITCHELL B.: Separable algebroids, Memoirs A.M.S. vol. 57 n. 333 (1985).

[25] ORZECH M. & SMALL C.: The Brauer Group of a commutative Ring, L. N. in Pure and Appl. Math 11, Mar- cel Dekker (1975).

121 [26] PAREIGIS B.: Non additive ring and module theory IV: the Brauer group of a symmetric monoidal category, L. N. in Math. 549, Springer-Verlag (1976), pp. 112-133.

[27] RAEBURN I. & TAYLOR J.L.: The bigger Brauer group and étale cohomology, Pacific J. Math. 119 (1985), pp. 445-463.

[28] SCHACK S.D.: Bimodules, the Brauer group, Morita equiva- lence and cohomology, J. Pure Appl. Algebra 80 (1992), pp. 315-325.

[29] TAYLOR J.L.: A bigger Brauer group, Pacific J. Math. 103 (1982), pp. 163-203.

[30] VERSCHOREN A. The Brauer group of a quasi-affine schema, L. N. in Math. 917, Springer-Verlag (1982), pp. 260-278. [31] VITALE E.M.: Monoidal categories for Morita theory, Cahiers Top. Géo. Diff. Catégoriques XXXIII-4 (1992), pp. 331-343. [32] VITALE E.M.: Groupe de Brauer et distributeurs, talk at Journée de Catégories et Géométrie, Dunkerque (1995).

[33] WALL C.T.C.: Graded Brauer groups, J. Reine Angew. Math. 213 (1964), pp.187-199. [34] WRAITH G.: Algebraic Theories, Aarhus University L. N. Se- ries 22 (1970).

[35] ZELINSKI D.: Brauer groups, L. N. in Pure and Appl. Math. 26, Marcel Dekker (1977).

Enrico M. Vitale Laboratoire LANGAL, Faculte de Sciences Universite du Littoral quai Freycinet 1, B.P. 5526 59379 Dunkerque, France vitale@lma. univ-littoral.fr

122