Austrian and Hungarian Philosophy: on the Logic of Wittgenstein and Pauler
Total Page:16
File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb
Load more
Recommended publications
-
Call for Papers ANTON MARTY and CONTEMPORARY PHILOSOPHY
Call for Papers ANTON MARTY AND CONTEMPORARY PHILOSOPHY Closing Conference of the SNF Project “Meaning and Intentionality in Anton Marty” June 15-17, 2017 – Geneva Homepage: http://www.unige.ch/lettres/philo/recherche/research-groups/autres-projets/meaning-and- intentionality-anton-marty/ We invite both established and early career scholars to submit papers establishing connections between the philosophy of Anton Marty and contemporary debates in philosophy of language, philosophy of mind and ontology. Please e-mail a full paper suitable for a 45 minutes presentation or a long detailed abstract (at least 1’500 words). Submissions should be formatted and redacted for anonymous review and sent to [email protected]. If they have submitted only an abstract, the selected authors will be asked to submit their full paper one month before the conference. The number of available time slots is limited to 4. Depending on our budget, travel costs of up to 250 EUR and accommodation will be covered. An edited volume containing the contributions presented at the conference is projected. For information, you may contact Hélène Leblanc ([email protected]) or Giuliano Bacigalupo ([email protected]). Important Dates Submission due: 01/12/2016 Notifications to authors: 15/01/2017 Final version due: 15/05/2017 Conference dates: 15-17/06/2017 Conference Description For a long time in the shadows of his teacher Franz Brentano and other well-known pupils of his, e.g. Edmund Husserl and Alexius Meinong, Anton Marty did not receive the attention it deserves. Even if the situation has been partly corrected in recent years, there still is much room for improvement. -
Hungarian Studies Review
Ilona Duczynska meets Ervin Szabo: The making of a revolutionary personality — from theory to terrorism, April-May 1917 Kenneth McRobbie "I'm not against bombs. Not all bombs are bad..." Ilona Duczynska (1969)1 The Unknown City Ilona Duczynska (1897-1978),2 born near Vienna and a resident of Cana- da after 1950, has been called one of Hungary's outstanding revolutionary personalities.3 In the first part of what was to have been an auto- biography,4 she describes, with no little satisfaction, how her "rebellious" nature developed in opposition to her mother's Hungarian gentry family, and then outlines how it became truly revolutionary under the impact of the momentous events of March 1917. Duczynska was just twenty in the late spring of 1917 when she was privileged to spend several weeks in the company of Ervin Szabo (1877-1918). Through Hungary's leading social- ist theoretician, she became exposed, as never before or since, to ques- tions of ideology, and the variety of the conflicting currents of socialist theory. These made little impression, however. What did leave a perma- nent mark were two things that spoke most directly to her nature: Szabo's emphasis upon the importance of the critically thinking individual, and the imperative of action. Duczynska considered herself a socialist, on the basis of her reading, since the age of fifteen. Certainly, she was not uncri- tical5 of the early betrayals of the principles of peace and proletarian internationalism after 1914 by social democratic parties, nor later of the infinitely greater betrayals of Marx's moral injunctions by national com- munist parties and the degenerate Soviet system. -
From Bühler to Wittgenstein1 Kevin Mulligan
On Being Guided, Signals & Rules: from Bühler to Wittgenstein1 Kevin Mulligan (Università della Svizzera italiana & Istituto di studi filosofici, Lugano) Abstract. Kevin Mulligan has examined in several papers and a book the conceptual relations between the descriptions of mind, language and colours in the philosophies of Brentano’s heirs and the descriptions given later by Wittgenstein. In Chapter 12, he looks at what Bühler and Wittgenstein have to say about the phenomenon of being guided by something and two of their favourite examples – reading and our relations to rules. §1 A Guide to Guidance §2 Reading & Guidance §3 Misleading Pictures & Pianolas: Machines & Modality, Rules & Rigidity §4 Early Bühler & Early Wittgenstein on Rule-Awareness §1 A Guide to Guidance Appearances, demonstratives, facts, knowledge, name tags, people, perceptions, pictures (misleading or not), quotation marks, 1 Versions of the material in this paper were presented most recently in Liège (2018 “On Being Guided: Bühler in the Brown Book” and in Vienna (2013). I am grateful to the audiences for their comments. Thanks, too, to Peter Simons for help with engineering terminology. rules, street signs, traffic signals, utterances, written signs, and many, many other things guide, lead, steer, control and influence us. In the writings of Brentano’s heirs and Wittgenstein, we find many verbs for such relations: trigger/auslösen follow/befolgen steer, control/steuern influence/beinflussen guide, lead/führen allow oneself to be led by/sich leiten lassen indicate/anzeigen The philosophers of guidance are Martinak, Marty and Ahlman, Husserl and Scheler, Bühler and Wittgenstein. Wittgenstein and his great predecessor, Bühler, sometimes use the term “signal” (Signal) for the first term of the relation of guidance2. -
Janoušek and Rollinger, the Prague School, Cleaned Up
The Prague School Hynek Janoušek and Robin Rollinger The name the “Prague school of Brentano” refers to three generations of thinkers who temporarily or permanently lived in Prague, bound together by teacher/student relationships, and who accepted the main views of Franz Brentano’s philosophy. In 1879 Carl Stumpf (see CHAP. 31) arrived in Prague to take up a professorship of philosophy at the Charles-Ferdinand University. In 1880 Stumpf’s close friend and also a student of Brentano, Anton Marty (see CHAP. 30), became a professor in the same department. This marks the beginning of the Prague School. The presence of Stumpf and Marty was in fact a dramatic shift in orientation first and foremost in the domain of psychology, for Prague had previously been an enclave of Herbartian psychology, which Brentano had criticized in various respects throughout his Psychology from an Empirical Standpoint (Brentano 1874). In a certain sense their presence even harked back to an earlier time in Prague when Bernard Bolzano was developing a theory of science very much in opposition to the Kantianism of his time. Though Brentano’s philosophy was very different from Bolzano’s in many respects, it was no less anti-Kantian. This was very important at that time, for neo-Kantianism was on the rise in the German-speaking world and even beyond, whereas Stumpf and Marty made efforts to combat this kind of philosophy. Though Stumpf’s sojourn in Prague was considerably shorter-lived than Marty’s, Stumpf published the first volume of his Tone Psychology (Stumpf 1883) during that time. -
Roman Jakobson and the Birth of Linguistic Structuralism
Sign Systems Studies 39(1), 2011 Roman Jakobson and the birth of linguistic structuralism W. Keith Percival Department of Linguistics, The University of Kansas 3815 N. E. 89th Street, Seattle, WA 98115, U.S.A e-mail: [email protected] Abstract. The term “structuralism” was introduced into linguistics by Roman Jakobson in the early days of the Linguistic Circle of Prague, founded in 1926. The cluster of ideas defended by Jakobson and his colleagues can be specified but differ considerably from the concept of structuralism as it has come to be understood more recently. That took place because from the 1930s on it became customary to equate structuralism with the ideas of Ferdinand de Saussure, as expounded in his posthumous Cours de linguistique générale (1916). It can be shown, however, that Jakobson’s group rejected Saussure’s theory for ideological reasons. As the term “structuralism” became more widely used it came to be associated with posi- tivist approaches to linguistics rather than with the original phenomenological orientation that had characterized the Linguistic Circle of Prague. The purpose of this paper is to clarify these different approaches and to suggest that because of its extreme porosity the word “structuralism” is an example of a “terminological pandemic”. More research on the varied uses to which the key terms “structure” and “structuralism” were put will undoubtedly further elucidate this important episode in 20th-century intellectual history. 1. Introduction In this article, I shall examine the early history of linguistic structu- ralism and the role played in it by the Russian philologist and linguist Roman Jakobson (1896–1982). -
Bartók Béla Életének Krónikája Translated by Márta Rubin
BÉLA BARTÓK JNR. Chronicles of Béla Bartók’s Life BÉLA BARTÓK JNR. CHRONICLES OF BÉLA BARTÓK’S LIFE Magyarságkutató Intézet Budapest, 2021 Translation based on Béla Bartók Jnr.’s original Bartók Béla életének krónikája Translated by Márta Rubin Book Editor: Gábor Vásárhelyi Assistant: Ágnes Virághalmy The publication of this book was sponsored by EMMI. A kötet megjelenését az EMMI támogatta. Original edition © Béla Bartók Jnr., 1981 Revised edition © Béla Bartók Jnr.’s legal successor (Gábor Vásárhelyi), 2021 Translation © Márta Rubin, 2021 ISBN 978-615-6117-26-7 CONTENTS Foreword ......................................................7 Preface .......................................................11 Family, Infancy (1855–1889) ....................................15 School Years (1890–1903) .......................................21 Connecting to the Music Life of Europe (1904–1906) ...............71 Settling In Budapest. Systematic Collection of Folk Songs (1907–1913) ................99 War Years (1914–1919) ........................................149 After World War I (1920–1921) .................................189 Great Concert Tours on Two Continents (1922–1931) .............205 Economic Crisis (1932–1933) ..................................335 At The Academy of Sciences. Great Compositions (1934–1938) .....359 World War II. Second and Third American Tour (1939–1945) .......435 Last Journey Home, “… But For Good” (1988) ....................507 Identification List of Place Names ...............................517 FOREWORD FOREWORD I have the honour of being a family member of Béla Bartók Jnr., the author of this book. He was the husband of my paternal aunt and my Godfather. Of our yearly summer vacations spent together, I remember well that summer when one and a half rooms of the two-room-living-room cottage were occupied by the scraps of paper big and small, letters, notes, railway tickets, and other documents necessary for the compilation of this book. -
Theschooloffranzbrenta
THESCHOOLOFFRANZBRENTANO Nijhoff International Philosophy Series VOLUME 52 General Editor: JAN T. J. SRZEDNICKI Editor for volumes on Applying Philosophy: ROBERTO POLl Editor for volumes on Logic and Applying Logic: STANISLAW J. SURMA Editor for volumes on Contributions to Philosophy: JAN T. J. SRZEDNICKI Assistant to the General Editor: DAVID WOOD Editorial Advisory Board: L. Broughton (University of Cambridge); R.M. Chisholm (Brown University, Rhode Island); Mats Furberg (Goteborg University); D.A.T. Gasking (University of Melbourne); H.L.A. Hart (University College, Oxford); S. Komer (University of Bristol and Yale University); H.I. McCloskey (La Trobe University, Bundoora, Melbourne); 1. Passmore (Australian National University, Canberra); A. Quinton (Trinity College, Oxford); Franco Spisani (Centro Superiore di Logica e Scienze Comparate, Bologna); R. Ziedins (Waikato University, New Zealand) The titles published in this series are listed at the end o/this volume. The School of Franz Brentano edited by Liliana Albertazzi University ofTrento. Trento. Italy Massimo Libardi Centro Studifer la Mitteleuro Trento. Trento. Italy and Roberto Poli University ofTrento. Trento. Italy SPRINGER-SCIENCE+BUSINESS MEDIA, B.V. A c.I.P. Catalogue record for this book is available from the Library of Congress. ISBN 978-90-481-4628-4 ISBN 978-94-015-8676-4 (eBook) DOI 10.1007/978-94-015-8676-4 Printed an acid-free paper AII Rights Reserved © 1996 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht Originally published by Kluwer Academic Publishers in 1996 Softcover reprint of the hardcover 1 st edition 1996 No part of the material protected by this copyright notice may be reproduced or utilized in any form or by any means. -
Print This Article
ISSN 1918-7351 Volume 12 (2020) Landgrebe’s Reading of Marty: On Name and Proper Name Charlotte Gauvry Ludwig Landgrebe wrote prolifically and his work dealt with various fundamental phenomenological issues. However, my paper will only focus on one specific aspect of his analysis. I will pay attention to the thoughtful analysis regarding the philosophy of language, developed in his 1934 habilitation thesis, Nennfunktion und Wortbedeutung. Eine Studie über Martys Sprachphilosophie.1 The dissertation was written in Prague under the supervision of Oskar Kraus, a former student of Anton Marty.2 The first part is devoted to the analysis of Marty’s philosophy of language and furnishes a precious analytical commentary of his 1908 Untersuchungen zur Grundlegung der allgemeinen Grammatik und Sprachphilosophie.3 The last two parts of the dissertation are more polemical and raise a number of problems in Marty’s theories. Most of these criticisms are directly influenced by the German psychologist and philosopher of language Karl Bühler,4 who was a reader of Marty too and whose Sprachtheorie was also published in 1934.5 Against this background, it makes sense to consider the young Landgrebe as an “indirect member” of the Brentano 1 Ludwig Landgrebe, Nennfunktion und Wortbedeutung. Eine Studie über Martys Sprachphilosophie (Halle: Akademischer Verlag, 1934). English translation is mine. 2 Anton Marty (1847-1914) is a Swiss-born Austrian philosopher who is considered one of the most faithful students of Franz Brentano (whose teaching he followed in Würzburg). He was especially interested in philosophy of language and applied Brentano’s theory to this new field. -
Hermann Lotze and Franz Brentano Dr
Hermann Lotze and Franz Brentano Dr. Nikolay Milkov 1. The Neo-Brentanists Franz Brentano was not a solitary figure who propounded his philosophy in lonely isolation from other contemporary philosophers in Germany, as some neo-Brentanists have claimed over the last thirty to forty years. The aim in what follows is to correct such misconceptions by establishing that Brentano developed his philosophical psychology while actively engaged in the rich intellectual-historical and academic context of his time—in particular, under the influence of Hermann Lotze. The misleading image of Brentano as a solitary genius promulgated by the likes of Neo-Brentanists such as Barry Smith is analogous to the picture of Gottlob Frege passed off as historical truth by influential Neo-Fregeans—Michael Dummett, for one. In both cases, we find a distinguished thinker portrayed as the reclusive, solitary man of genius. Thanks, however, to the researches of Hans Sluga, Gottfried Gabriel, and others, we now know that in the case of Frege it was as an active player in the culture of nineteenth-century German philosophy that he propounded the innovations in symbolic logic for which he is famous. The same holds for Franz Brentano and the introduction of his philosophical psychology, as we shall see presently by probing and assessing the historical, epistolary, and textual evidence. As opposed to the image of the neo-Brentanists, Brentano in no way saw himself as an intellectually and institutionally isolated thinker, and he certainly never represented himself as such. In perhaps his most important work, Psychology from an empirical Standpoint, Brentano admitted that “his view, at least from one side or the other, had already begun” to be developed by other authors before him (1874, 4). -
Anarchism in Hungary: Theory, History, Legacies
CHSP HUNGARIAN STUDIES SERIES NO. 7 EDITORS Peter Pastor Ivan Sanders A Joint Publication with the Institute of Habsburg History, Budapest Anarchism in Hungary: Theory, History, Legacies András Bozóki and Miklós Sükösd Translated from the Hungarian by Alan Renwick Social Science Monographs, Boulder, Colorado Center for Hungarian Studies and Publications, Inc. Wayne, New Jersey Distributed by Columbia University Press, New York 2005 EAST EUROPEAN MONOGRAPHS NO. DCLXX Originally published as Az anarchizmus elmélete és magyarországi története © 1994 by András Bozóki and Miklós Sükösd © 2005 by András Bozóki and Miklós Sükösd © 2005 by the Center for Hungarian Studies and Publications, Inc. 47 Cecilia Drive, Wayne, New Jersey 07470–4649 E-mail: [email protected] This book is a joint publication with the Institute of Habsburg History, Budapest www.Habsburg.org.hu Library of Congress Control Number 2005930299 ISBN 9780880335683 Printed in the United States of America CONTENTS INTRODUCTION 1 PART ONE: ANARCHIST SOCIAL PHILOSOPHY 7 1. Types of Anarchism: an Analytical Framework 7 1.1. Individualism versus Collectivism 9 1.2. Moral versus Political Ways to Social Revolution 11 1.3. Religion versus Antireligion 12 1.4. Violence versus Nonviolence 13 1.5. Rationalism versus Romanticism 16 2. The Essential Features of Anarchism 19 2.1. Power: Social versus Political Order 19 2.2. From Anthropological Optimism to Revolution 21 2.3. Anarchy 22 2.4. Anarchist Mentality 24 3. Critiques of Anarchism 27 3.1. How Could Institutions of Just Rule Exist? 27 3.2. The Problem of Coercion 28 3.3. An Anarchist Economy? 30 3.4. How to Deal with Antisocial Behavior? 34 3.5. -
2011 Graduate School
Scientific Programme Postgraduate Course “Fundamentality and Perspectivality” Fundamentality and perspectivality in the philosophies of mind and world Philipp Keller, Kevin Mulligan, Gianfranco Soldati, Fabrice Correia May the world be fundamentally perspectival? For centuries, many people, in- and outside of philosophy have been attracted by this idea, but no systematic theory has ever been worked out. Within contemporary academic philosophy, the very idea is quickly dismissed, most of the time, as a form of relativism. Recent work in metaphysics and the philosophies of mind and language has put into question this assumption: in very different contexts, it has been maintained that perspectival phenomena may be metaphysically fundamental. The aim of the present postgraduate course is to pursue these questions, within an educational framework designed to maximise the academic benefits of the participating PhD students, most of which are part of the recently re-launched pro*doc programme „Metaphysics of the Mind“, with the activities of which the course will be closely linked. The research programme of this postgraduate course brings together two important strands in current philosophical research: the metaphysical problem of how to characterise the concept of fundamentality, which has important ramifications in the philosophy of physics, and the epistemological problem of how to account for the perspectivality of our knowledge of the world, of much current interest in the philosophy of mind, language and perception. These two strands correspond to two research projects currently being pursued at eidos, the Genevan Centre for Metaphysics. Topics of the workshops Traditionally, the concept of fundamentality has been taken to be a modal notion: what is fundamental is what does not, and cannot change, what forms the necessary framework within which contingent events take place. -
Husserl, Marty, and the (Psycho)Logical a Priori
1 Husserl, Marty, and the (Psycho)logical A Priori Denis Seron (FNRS, Univ. of Liège BE) Abstract: This paper aims to discuss some aspects of the Marty–Husserl debate about grammar. My suggestion is that the debate is first of all an epistemological debate, that is, a debate about what a priori knowledge is and how it is acquired. The key opposition is between Marty’s Brentanian notion of ‘analytic intuition’ and Husserl’s Bolzanian notion of ideation. As I will argue, the underlying issue is the possibility of a psychological a priori. On the one hand, analytic intuition provides the psychologist with a priori knowledge about empirical facts. On the other hand, ideation provides the logician with entities that are disconnected from empirical facts—entities which are ‘purely logical’. I conclude with some brief remarks on the Brentanian background of both conceptions. --------------------------------------------------------- Kant bequeathed to his successors the bizarre idea that there are two different kinds of a priori knowledge, corresponding to the two higher faculties of the mind, sensibility and reason.1 Some a priori rules are regarded as being of a ‘logical’ nature, while others are not. The first category includes the rules ‘a proposition composed of connectives alone is impossible’ and ‘necessarily all propositions of the form “p and non-p” are false’. The second category includes phenomenological or psychological rules such as ‘green is between blue and yellow’ and ‘a belief with no content is impossible’. But why should there be different kinds of a priori rules? It seems odd to place such a peculiar thing as a priori knowledge into completely different categories.