Landscapes, Surfaces, and Morphospaces: What Are They Good For?

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Landscapes, Surfaces, and Morphospaces: What Are They Good For? CHAPTER 3 Landscapes, Surfaces, and Morphospaces: What Are They Good For? Massimo Pigliucci 3.1 Introduction is precisely what in philosophy of science is meant by reduction; see Brigandt 2008). This time the non- Few metaphors in biology are more enduring fitness axes of the landscape were phenotypic traits, than the idea of Adaptive Landscapes, originally not genetic measures at all. Even more recently, proposed by Sewall Wright (1932) as a way to Lande and Arnold (1983) proposed a mathematical visually present to an audience of typically non- formalism aimed at estimating actual (as opposed mathematically savvy biologists his ideas about the to Simpson’s hypothetical) fitness surfaces, making relative role of natural selection and genetic drift use of standard multiple regression analyses. But in the course of evolution. The metaphor, how- while Simpson was talking about macroevolution- ever, was born troubled, not the least reason for ary change involving speciation, Lande and Arnold which is the fact that Wright presented different were concerned with microevolutionary analyses diagrams in his original paper that simply can- within individual populations of a single species. not refer to the same concept and are therefore In principle, it is relatively easy to see how hard to reconcile with each other (Pigliucci 2008). one can go from individual-genotype landscapes For instance, in some usages, the landscape’s non- to genotypic-frequency landscapes (the two Wright fitness axes represent combinations of individual versions of the metaphor). However, the (implied) genotypes (which cannot sensibly be aligned on a further transition from either of these to pheno- linear axis, and accordingly were drawn by Wright types (either in the Lande–Arnold or in the Simpson as polyhedrons of increasing dimensionality). In version) is anything but straightforward because of other usages, however, the points on the diagram the notorious complexity and non-linearity of the represent allele or genotypic frequencies,andsoare so called genotype–phenotype mapping function actually populations, not individuals (and these can (Alberch 1991; Pigliucci 2010). This is a serious issue indeed be coherently represented along continuous if—as I assume is the case—we wish to use the land- axes). scape metaphor as a unified key to an integrated Things got even more confusing after the land- treatment of genotypic and phenotypic evolution scape metaphor began to play an extended role (as well as of micro- and macroevolution). Without within the Modern Synthesis in evolutionary biol- such unification evolutionary biology would be left ogy and was appropriated by G. G. Simpson (1944) in the awkward position of having two separate to further his project of reconciling macro- and theories, one about genetic change, the other about microevolution, i.e. to reduce paleontology to pop- phenotypic change, and no bridge principles to con- ulation genetics (some may object to the characteri- nect them. zation of this program as a reductive one, but if the One more complication has arisen in more recent questions raised by one discipline can be reframed years, this one concerning Wright-style fitness land- within the conceptual framework of another, that scapes. Work by Gavrilets (2003; see also Chapter 17 26 LANDSCAPES, SURFACES, AND MORPHOSPACES: WHAT ARE THEY GOOD FOR? 27 this volume) and collaborators, made possible by context of the Modern Synthesis (Mayr and Provine the availability of computing power exceeding by 1980) as a theory essentially rooted in (though cer- several orders of magnitudes what was achievable tainly not limited to) population genetics, where throughout the twentieth century, has explored the evolution is often simply defined as change in features of truly highly dimensional landscapes—as allelic frequencies (Futuyma 2006). opposed to the standard two- or three-dimensional Despite some confusion due to the often inter- ones explicitly considered by Wright and by most changeable use of terms like “fitness” and “Adap- previous authors. As it turns out, evolution on tive” Landscape, I will use and build here on the so-called “holey” landscapes is characterized by more rigorous terminology followed by authors qualitatively different dynamics from those sug- such as McGhee (2007) and distinguish the follow- gested by the standard low-dimensional version ing four types of landscapes: of the metaphor—a conclusion that has led some Fitness landscapes. These are the sort of entities authors to suggest abandoning the metaphor alto- originally introduced by Wright and studied in a gether, in favor of embracing directly the results of high-dimensional context by Gavrilets and collabo- formal modeling (Kaplan 2008; though see Plutyn- rators. The non-fitness dimensions are measures of ski 2008 and Chapter 2 for a somewhat different genotypic diversity. The points on the landscape are take). population means, and the mathematical approach In this essay I wish to discuss the implications is rooted in population genetics. of four versions of the metaphor, often referred Adaptive Landscapes. These are the non- to as fitness landscapes, Adaptive Landscapes, fit- straightforward “generalizations” of fitness ness surfaces, and morphospaces. I will argue that landscapes introduced by Simpson, where the moving from one to any of the others is signifi- non-fitness dimensions now are phenotypic traits. cantly more difficult than might at first be surmised, The points on the landscape are populations and that work with morphospaces has been unduly speciating in response to ecological pressures or neglected by the research community. even above-species level lineages (i.e. this is about macroevolution). Fitness surfaces.ThesearetheLande–Arnoldtype 3.2 Four types of landscapes of landscapes, where phenotypic traits are plot- As I mentioned earlier, there are several versions of ted against a surrogate measure of fitness. They the “landscape” metaphor that have proliferated in are statistical estimates used in quantitative genetic the literature since Wright’s original paper. Indeed, modeling, and the points on the landscape can be Wright himself was referring—in that very same either individuals within a population or popu- paper—to at least two conceptions of landscapes, lation means, in both cases belonging to a single one with individual genotypes as the points on the species (i.e. this is about microevolution). (necessarily non-continuous) landscape, the other Morphospaces. These were arguably first intro- with populations identified by gene or genotype duced by Raup (1966), and differ dramatically from frequencies (in a continuous space). I will ignore the other types for two reasons: (a) they do not the distinction between the two types of Wright have a fitness axis; (b) their dimensions, while rep- landscapes for two reasons: first, they are con- resenting phenotypic (“morphological”) traits, are nected in a conceptually straightforward manner, generated via a priori geometrical or mathematical since it is obviously possible to go from individ- models, i.e. they are not the result of observa- ual genotypes to populations of genotypes with- tional measurements. They typically refer to across- out any theoretical difficulty. Second, most of the species (macroevolutionary) differences, though post-Wright literature, including the presentation they can be used for within-species work. of the metaphor in textbooks and the more recent work on “holey” landscapes, is framed in terms Let us take a look in a bit more detail at each type of gene/genotype frequencies, not individual geno- of landscape, to familiarize ourselves with their types. This is understandable within the broader respective similarities and differences. Throughout 28 PART I HISTORICAL BACKGROUND AND PHILOSOPHICAL PERSPECTIVES Iwilluseboththeterminologyjustsummarized work of Cowperthwaite and Meyers (2007) on 30- and the names of the relevant authors, to reduce nucleotide long binary RNA molecules. This is confusion at the cost of some redundancy. The first arguably one of the simpler models of genotype– thing we notice from even a cursory examination phenotype–fitness relations, and it is computation- of the literature is that there are few actual biolog- ally tractable and empirically approachable. Still, ical examples of fitness landscapes (Wright-style) 30-nucleotide binary molecules correspond to a or Adaptive Landscapes (Simpson-style) available, bewildering one billion unique sequences! These while there is a good number of well understood in turn generate “only” about 220,000 unique fold- examples of morphospaces (Raup-style) and partic- ing shapes in a G/U landscape and a “mere” 1000 ularly of adaptive surfaces (Lande–Arnold style). shapes in the A/U landscape, both of which these These differences are highly significant for my dis- authors have tackled. In other words, a genotypic cussion of the metaphor. space of a billion sequences corresponds (obviously Beginning with Wright-type, fitness landscapes, in a many-to-many manner) to a phenotypic space many of the examples in the literature are entirely of thousands to hundreds of thousands of possibil- conceptual, i.e. presented by various authors only ities, each characterized by its own (environment- for heuristic purposes. It should be obvious why dependent, of course) fitness value. it is so: to actually draw a “real” fitness landscape Things get even more complex when we we need a reasonably complete description of the move from RNA to proteins: Wroe et al. (2007) genotype fitness mapping function, i.e. we need have explored evolution in protein structure- → data about the fitness value of each relevant combi- defined phenotypic space, focusing in particular nation of genotypes that we happen to be interested on so-called “promiscuity,” the ability of a given in. For most purposes this is next to impossible. protein to perform two functions because of the Dobzhansky (1970, p. 25) famously put it this way: alternation between multiple thermodynamically stable configurations. Proteins are, of course, much Suppose there are only 1000 kinds of genes in the more complicated biochemical objects than RNA world, each gene existing in 10 different variants or molecules.
Recommended publications
  • What Can We Learn from Fitness Landscapes?
    What can we learn from fitness landscapes? The Harvard community has made this article openly available. Please share how this access benefits you. Your story matters Citation Hartl, Daniel L. 2014. “What Can We Learn from Fitness Landscapes?” Current Opinion in Microbiology 21 (October): 51–57. doi:10.1016/j.mib.2014.08.001. Published Version 10.1016/j.mib.2014.08.001 Citable link http://nrs.harvard.edu/urn-3:HUL.InstRepos:22898356 Terms of Use This article was downloaded from Harvard University’s DASH repository, and is made available under the terms and conditions applicable to Open Access Policy Articles, as set forth at http:// nrs.harvard.edu/urn-3:HUL.InstRepos:dash.current.terms-of- use#OAP Elsevier Editorial System(tm) for Current Opinion in Microbiology Manuscript Draft Manuscript Number: Title: What Can We Learn From Fitness Landscapes? Article Type: 22 Growth&Develop: prokaryotes (2014 Corresponding Author: Dr. Daniel Hartl, Corresponding Author's Institution: First Author: Daniel Hartl Order of Authors: Daniel Hartl Manuscript Click here to view linked References What Can We Learn From Fitness Landscapes? Daniel L. Hartl Department of Organismic and Evolutionary Biology Harvard University Cambridge, Massachusetts 02138 USA Contact information: Email: [email protected], TEL: 617-396-3917 In evolutionary biology, the fitness landscape of set of mutants is the mapping of genotypes onto phenotypes when the phenotype is fitness or some proxy for fitness such as growth rate or drug resistance. When the set of mutants is not too large, it is possible to create every possible combination of mutants and map these to fitness.
    [Show full text]
  • 1. Basis of Fitness Landscape
    Optimisation Origin and definition of fitness landscape Position and goal 1. Basis of fitness landscape Fitness landscape analysis for understanding and designing local search heuristics Sebastien´ Verel LISIC - Universit´edu Littoral C^oted'Opale, Calais, France http://www-lisic.univ-littoral.fr/~verel/ The 51st CREST Open Workshop Tutorial on Landscape Analysis University College London 27th, February, 2017 Optimisation Origin and definition of fitness landscape Position and goal Outline of this part Basis of fitness landscape : introductory example (Done) brief history and background of fitness landscape fundamental definitions Optimisation Origin and definition of fitness landscape Position and goal Mono-objective Optimization Search space : set of candidate solutions X Objective fonction : quality criterion (or non-quality) f : X ! IR X discrete : combinatorial optimization X ⊂ IRn : numerical optimization Solve an optimization problem (maximization) ? X = argmaxX f or find an approximation of X ?. Optimisation Origin and definition of fitness landscape Position and goal Context : black-box optimization x −! −! f (x) No information on the objective definition function f Objective fonction : can be irregular, non continuous, non differentiable, etc. given by a computation or a simulation Optimisation Origin and definition of fitness landscape Position and goal Real-world black-box optimization : first example PhD of Mathieu Muniglia, Saclay Nuclear Research Centre (CEA), Paris x −! −! f (x) (73;:::; 8) −! −! ∆z P Multi-physic simulator Optimisation Origin and definition of fitness landscape Position and goal Search algorithms Principle Enumeration of the search space A lot of ways to enumerate the search space Using exact method : A?, Branch&Bound, etc. Using random sampling : Monte Carlo technics, approx.
    [Show full text]
  • Predictability of a Large Intragenic Fitness Landscape
    On the (un)predictability of a large intragenic fitness landscape Claudia Banka,b,c,1, Sebastian Matuszewskib,c,1, Ryan T. Hietpasd,e, and Jeffrey D. Jensenb,c,2,3 aInstituto Gulbenkian de Ciencia,ˆ 2780-156 Oeiras, Portugal; bSchool of Life Sciences, Ecole Polytechnique Fed´ erale´ de Lausanne, 1015 Lausanne, Switzerland; cSwiss Institute of Bioinformatics, 1015 Lausanne, Switzerland; dEli Lilly and Company, Indianapolis, IN 46225; and eDepartment of Biochemistry & Molecular Pharmacology, University of Massachusetts Medical School, Worcester, MA 01605 Edited by Andrew G. Clark, Cornell University, Ithaca, NY, and approved October 11, 2016 (received for review August 2, 2016) The study of fitness landscapes, which aims at mapping geno- of previously observed beneficial mutations or on the dissection types to fitness, is receiving ever-increasing attention. Novel exper- of an observed adaptive walk (i.e., a combination of muta- imental approaches combined with next-generation sequencing tions that have been observed to be beneficial in concert). (NGS) methods enable accurate and extensive studies of the fitness Secondly, theoretical research has proposed different land- effects of mutations, allowing us to test theoretical predictions scape architectures [such as the House-of-Cards (HoC), the and improve our understanding of the shape of the true under- Kauffman NK (NK), and the Rough Mount Fuji (RMF) model], lying fitness landscape and its implications for the predictability studied their respective properties, and developed a number and repeatability of evolution. Here, we present a uniquely large of statistics that characterize the landscape and quantify the multiallelic fitness landscape comprising 640 engineered mutants expected degree of epistasis (i.e., interaction effects between that represent all possible combinations of 13 amino acid-changing mutations) (10–14).
    [Show full text]
  • Myths and Legends of the Baldwin Effect
    Myths and Legends of the Baldwin Effect Peter Turney Institute for Information Technology National Research Council Canada Ottawa, Ontario, Canada, K1A 0R6 [email protected] Abstract ary computation when there is an evolving population of learning individuals (Ackley and Littman, 1991; Belew, This position paper argues that the Baldwin effect 1989; Belew et al., 1991; French and Messinger, 1994; is widely misunderstood by the evolutionary Hart, 1994; Hart and Belew, 1996; Hightower et al., 1996; computation community. The misunderstandings Whitley and Gruau, 1993; Whitley et al., 1994). This syn- appear to fall into two general categories. Firstly, ergetic effect is usually called the Baldwin effect. This has it is commonly believed that the Baldwin effect is produced the misleading impression that there is nothing concerned with the synergy that results when more to the Baldwin effect than synergy. A myth or legend there is an evolving population of learning indi- has arisen that the Baldwin effect is simply a special viduals. This is only half of the story. The full instance of synergy. One of the goals of this paper is to story is more complicated and more interesting. dispel this myth. The Baldwin effect is concerned with the costs Roughly speaking (we will be more precise later), the and benefits of lifetime learning by individuals in Baldwin effect has two aspects. First, lifetime learning in an evolving population. Several researchers have individuals can, in some situations, accelerate evolution. focussed exclusively on the benefits, but there is Second, learning is expensive. Therefore, in relatively sta- much to be gained from attention to the costs.
    [Show full text]
  • Evolution & Development
    DOI: 10.1111/ede.12315 RESEARCH Developmental structuring of phenotypic variation: A case study with a cellular automata model of ontogeny Wim Hordijk1 | Lee Altenberg2 1Konrad Lorenz Institute for Evolution and Cognition Research, Klosterneuburg, Abstract Austria Developmental mechanisms not only produce an organismal phenotype, but 2University of Hawai‘iatMānoa, they also structure the way genetic variation maps to phenotypic variation. ‘ Honolulu, Hawai i Here, we revisit a computational model for the evolution of ontogeny based on Correspondence cellular automata, in which evolution regularly discovered two alternative Wim Hordijk, Konrad Lorenz Institute for mechanisms for achieving a selected phenotype, one showing high modularity, Evolution and Cognition Research, the other showing morphological integration. We measure a primary variational Martinstrasse 12, 3400 Klosterneuburg, Austria. property of the systems, their distribution of fitness effects of mutation. We find Email: [email protected] that the modular ontogeny shows the evolution of mutational robustness and ontogenic simplification, while the integrated ontogeny does not. We discuss the wider use of this methodology on other computational models of development as well as real organisms. 1 | INTRODUCTION summarize, “almost anything can be changed if it shows phenotypic variation” and “combinations of traits, even The idea that phenotypic variation could ever be those unfavorably correlated, can be changed”). Once the “unbiased” is a historical artifact coming from two main premises of this “pan‐variationism” are accepted, pans- sources: First were the early characterizations of quanti- electionism is the natural conclusion—in other words, if tative genetic variation for single traits or small numbers variation is diffusing in every phenotypic direction, the of traits.
    [Show full text]
  • Evolution in the Weak-Mutation Limit: Stasis Periods Punctuated by Fast Transitions Between Saddle Points on the Fitness Landscape
    Evolution in the weak-mutation limit: Stasis periods punctuated by fast transitions between saddle points on the fitness landscape Yuri Bakhtina, Mikhail I. Katsnelsonb, Yuri I. Wolfc, and Eugene V. Kooninc,1 aCourant Institute of Mathematical Sciences, New York University, New York, NY 10012; bInstitute for Molecules and Materials, Radboud University, NL-6525 AJ Nijmegen, The Netherlands; and cNational Center for Biotechnology Information, National Library of Medicine, NIH, Bethesda, MD 20894 Contributed by Eugene V. Koonin, December 16, 2020 (sent for review July 24, 2020; reviewed by Sergey Gavrilets and Alexey S. Kondrashov) A mathematical analysis of the evolution of a large population occur (9, 10). The long intervals of stasis are punctuated by short under the weak-mutation limit shows that such a population periods of rapid evolution during which speciation occurs, and the would spend most of the time in stasis in the vicinity of saddle previous dominant species is replaced by a new one. Gould and points on the fitness landscape. The periods of stasis are punctu- Eldredge emphasized that PE was not equivalent to the “hopeful ated by fast transitions, in lnNe/s time (Ne, effective population monsters” idea, in that no macromutation or saltation was proposed size; s, selection coefficient of a mutation), when a new beneficial to occur, but rather a major acceleration of evolution via rapid mutation is fixed in the evolving population, which accordingly succession of “regular” mutations that resulted in the appearance of moves to a different saddle, or on much rarer occasions from a instantaneous speciation, on a geological scale.
    [Show full text]
  • Epistasis and the Structure of Fitness Landscapes: Are Experimental Fitness Landscapes Compatible with Fisher’S Geometric Model?
    Epistasis and the structure of fitness landscapes: are experimental fitness landscapes compatible with Fisher’s geometric model? François Blanquart1,2*, Thomas Bataillon1. 1. Bioinformatics Research Centre, Aarhus University. 8000C Aarhus, Denmark. 2. Department of Infectious Disease Epidemiology, Imperial College London, St Mary's Campus, London, United Kingdom. François Blanquart Department of Infectious Disease Epidemiology Imperial College London, St Mary's Campus Norfolk Place, W2 1PG London United Kingdom. [email protected] Key words: fitness landscape, mutational network, epistasis, adaptation, Fisher's geometric model, antibiotic resistance 1 Abstract The fitness landscape defines the relationship between genotypes and fitness in a given environment, and underlies fundamental quantities such as the distribution of selection coefficient, or the magnitude and type of epistasis. A better understanding of variation of landscape structure across species and environments is thus necessary to understand and predict how populations will adapt. An increasing number of experiments investigates the properties of fitness landscapes by identifying mutations, constructing genotypes with combinations of these mutations, and measuring the fitness of these genotypes. Yet these empirical landscapes represent a very small sample of the vast space of all possible genotypes, and this sample is often biased by the protocol used to identify mutations. Here we develop a rigorous statistical framework based on Approximate Bayesian Computation to address these concerns, and use this flexible framework to fit a broad class of phenotypic fitness models (including Fisher’s model) to 26 empirical landscapes representing 9 diverse biological systems. In spite of uncertainty due to the small size of most published empirical landscapes, the inferred landscapes have similar structure in similar biological systems.
    [Show full text]
  • On the Adaptive Disadvantage of Lamarckianism in Rapidly Changing Environments
    On the Adaptive Disadvantage of Lamarckianism in Rapidly Changing Environments Ingo Paenke1,2, Bernhard Sendhoff2, Jon Rowe3, and Chrisantha Fernando3 1 Institute AIFB, University of Karlsruhe, D-76128 Karlsruhe, Germany, E-mail: [email protected] 2 Honda Research Institute Europe GmbH, Carl-Legien-Straße 30, D-63073 Offenbach/Main, Germany, E-mail: [email protected] 3 Systems Biology Centre, University of Birmingham, Birmingham, Edgbaston, B15 2TT, UK, E-mail: [email protected] and [email protected] Abstract. Using a simple simulation model of evolution and learning, this paper provides an evolutionary argument why Lamarckian inheri- tance - the direct transfer of lifetime learning from parent to offspring - may be so rare in nature. Lamarckian inheritance allows quicker ge- netic adaptation to new environmental conditions than non-lamarckian inheritance. While this may be an advantage in the short term, it may be detrimental in the long term, since the population may be less well prepared for future environmental changes than in the absence of Lamar- ckianism. 1 Introduction Natural selection to a first approximation operates with variation that is undi- rected [1]. Lamarck suggested that the results of lifetime learning could be di- rectly passed on to ones offspring [2]. When would we expect directed variation or inheritance of acquired characters to occur? Recent work reveals a range of mechanisms capable of sustaining heritable epigenetic variation [3], pheno- typic memory [4] and neo-Lamarckian inheritance [5], for example: mutational hotspots and adaptive mutations occurring during bacterial stress [6] , chromatin marks that control differentiation in multicellular organisms [7], RNA silencing allowing potential influence by somatic RNA on germ line gene expression [8], inheritance of immune system states by antibody transfer in breast milk [9], and behavioural and symbolic inheritance systems such as food preference, niche con- struction traditions and all information transmission dependent on language [3].
    [Show full text]
  • On the Deformability of an Empirical Fitness Landscape by Microbial Evolution
    On the deformability of an empirical fitness landscape by microbial evolution Djordje Bajica,b,1,2, Jean C. C. Vilaa,b,1, Zachary D. Blountc,d,e, and Alvaro Sáncheza,b,2 aDepartment of Ecology and Evolutionary Biology, Yale University, New Haven, CT 06511; bMicrobial Sciences Institute, Yale University West Campus, West Haven, CT 06516; cBEACON Center for the Study of Evolution in Action, Michigan State University, East Lansing, MI 48824; dDepartment of Microbiology and Molecular Genetics, Michigan State University, East Lansing, MI 48824; and eDepartment of Biology, Kenyon College, Gambier OH 43022 Edited by Marcus W. Feldman, Stanford University, Stanford, CA, and approved September 20, 2018 (received for review May 16, 2018) A fitness landscape is a map between the genotype and its reproduc- fitness peaks and valleys and their connectivity) plays a pivotal role, tive success in a given environment. The topography of fitness land- as it governs the accessibility of evolutionary trajectories (15–17), the scapes largely governs adaptive dynamics, constraining evolutionary role of population structure on evolution (18), the degree of evo- trajectories and the predictability of evolution. Theory suggests that lutionary convergence among populations (19), the expected role of this topography can be deformed by mutations that produce sub- drift, selection, and sex in the evolutionary process (20, 21), the stantial changes to the environment. Despite its importance, the discovery of evolutionary innovations (22), and the predictability of deformability of fitness landscapes has not been systematically stud- evolution (23), a subject of growing importance for the management – ied beyond abstract models, and little is known about its reach and of pathogens and cancer treatment (24 28).
    [Show full text]
  • Resisting Extinction Via the Baldwin Effect
    Surviving the apocalypse: resisting extinction via the Baldwin Effect Ryan Lynch∗ Massachusetts Institute of Technology, 185 Albany St, 02139 Cambridge USA The Baldwin Effect is a means of explaining genetic assimilation in evolutionary theory: a process by which phenotype plasticity can eventually become hard-coded as genetic instinct. Hinton and Nowlan propose an evolutionary model in which the genetic assimilation predicted by the Baldwin effect is observed for static fitness landscapes. In this paper, we explore the behavior of the Hinton- Nowlan model in a dynamic fitness landscape, where the optimal-fitness phenotype evolves in time. Specifically, we examine the ability for Hinton-Nowlan populations to successfully adapt to this changing fitness landscape and prevent extinction events. We find that plasticity helps to accelerate evolutionary selection, and we observe genetic assimilation even in a changing fitness landscape. We see that as a result of this genetic assimilation, plasticity alone is not enough to prevent extinction events, but that genetic mutations are also needed to maintain some non-zero level of genetic variance. Finally, we argue that in order for a population to resist extinction, we should have the characteristic timescale of evolutionary selection . the characteristic timescale of genetic mutation . the characteristic timescale of the changing fitness landscape. I. INTRODUCTION pecially if partially-correct phenotypes are destructive (such as the ability for humans to create weapons with- A fascinating concept that has persisted throughout out the ability to track prey). In other words, evolution the history of evolutionary theory is Lamarckian inher- may need to find a phenotype of 10 1's, but in a land- itance.
    [Show full text]
  • Simulating Natural Selection in Landscape Genetics
    Molecular Ecology Resources (2012) 12, 363–368 doi: 10.1111/j.1755-0998.2011.03075.x Simulating natural selection in landscape genetics E. L. LANDGUTH,* S. A. CUSHMAN† and N. A. JOHNSON‡ *Division of Biological Sciences, University of Montana, Missoula, MT 59812, USA, †Rocky Mountain Research Station, United States Forest Service, Flagstaff, AZ 86001, USA, USA, ‡Department of Plant, Soil, and Insect Sciences and Graduate Program in Organismic and Evolutionary Biology, University of Massachusetts, Amherst, MA 01003, USA Abstract Linking landscape effects to key evolutionary processes through individual organism movement and natural selection is essential to provide a foundation for evolutionary landscape genetics. Of particular importance is determining how spa- tially-explicit, individual-based models differ from classic population genetics and evolutionary ecology models based on ideal panmictic populations in an allopatric setting in their predictions of population structure and frequency of fixation of adaptive alleles. We explore initial applications of a spatially-explicit, individual-based evolutionary landscape genetics program that incorporates all factors – mutation, gene flow, genetic drift and selection – that affect the frequency of an allele in a population. We incorporate natural selection by imposing differential survival rates defined by local relative fitness values on a landscape. Selection coefficients thus can vary not only for genotypes, but also in space as functions of local environmental variability. This simulator enables coupling of gene flow (governed by resistance surfaces), with natural selection (governed by selection surfaces). We validate the individual-based simulations under Wright-Fisher assumptions. We show that under isolation-by-distance processes, there are deviations in the rate of change and equilibrium values of allele frequency.
    [Show full text]
  • Quasi-Species Evolution Maximizes Genotypic Reproductive Value (Not fitness Or flatness)
    bioRxiv preprint doi: https://doi.org/10.1101/2021.02.23.432496; this version posted February 24, 2021. The copyright holder for this preprint (which was not certified by peer review) is the author/funder, who has granted bioRxiv a license to display the preprint in perpetuity. It is made available under aCC-BY 4.0 International license. Quasi-species evolution maximizes genotypic reproductive value (not fitness or flatness) Matteo Smerlak Max Planck Institute for Mathematics in the Sciences, Leipzig, Germany Abstract Growing efforts to measure fitness landscapes in molecular and microbial sys- tems are motivated by a longstanding goal to predict future evolutionary trajec- tories. Sometimes under-appreciated, however, is that the fitness landscape and its topography do not by themselves determine the direction of evolution: under sufficiently high mutation rates, populations can climb the closest fitness peak (survival of the fittest), settle in lower regions with higher mutational robustness (survival of the flattest), or even fail to adapt altogether (error catastrophes). I show that another measure of reproductive success, Fisher's reproductive value, resolves the trade-off between fitness and robustness in the quasi-species regime of evolution: to forecast the motion of a population in genotype space, one should look for peaks in the (mutation-rate dependent) landscape of genotypic reproductive values|whether or not these peaks correspond to local fitness maxima or flat fitness plateaus. This new landscape picture turns quasi-species dynamics into
    [Show full text]