Glory Over Sublimity: Karl Barth'S Theological Aesthetics

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Glory Over Sublimity: Karl Barth'S Theological Aesthetics HeyJ •• (2016), pp. ••–•• GLORY OVER SUBLIMITY: KARL BARTH’S THEOLOGICAL AESTHETICS SCOTT A. KIRKLAND Trinity College, Melbourne, Australia INTRODUCTION: DISPLACING THE SUBJECT OF SUBLIME INTUITION My contention is that Barth deliberately reframes theologically the Kantian conditions for per- ception of the beautiful and the sublime by dispossessing the subject of the normative universal- ity she maintains in Kant’s system of knowing. Barth frames beauty and sublimity instead in terms of the givenness of divine being for us in the form of the Son of God incarnate. Beauty no longer is a subjective apriori; it is rather a product of divine self-giving. Barth therefore finds ways to speak of creaturely participation in this beauty through the playful language of ‘joy’ and ‘happiness’ in the Spirit. We shall focus on Church Dogmatics [hereafter CD] paragraph 31.3, on divine glory; it is here that Barth enters into one of the few explicit discussions of theological aesthetics in the CD. Barth seeks to heal the disjunction created between the beautiful and the good in the second and third critiques by re-thinking the relationship between divine action and divine beauty, see- ing God’s beauty as his action. Beauty [Schon€ ], derived from divine glory [Herrlichkeit], is the crowning moment of CD II.1, the final perfection to be explicated. This is significant, as glory is seen as the exposition of the form of God’s coming in its superfluousness. Glory is God’s hiddenness as it is the revelation of his fullness in a dizzying light. Throughout CD II.1, each of the perfections serves to illuminate another; with none seen in isolation, each is continually destabilised by the excess of God’s revelatory activity. Divine beauty becomes then for Barth a way of speaking about the positive plentitude of the divine life manifest in the coming of Jesus Christ. Beauty has a determinate ‘form’; it is not a stepping off point into a sublime formless- ness, as Kant would have it. To use an aesthetic metaphor Barth was fond of, it is as if the dis- cussion of divine eternity and glory recapitulates the earlier movements of the volume, bringing everything to a glorious crescendo in praise of the overflowing abundance of divine self- revelation. And, yet, as we shall see, this is necessarily a movement into divine hiddenness: just as the light of God’s glory is dizzyingly bright, so each single conceptual movement is continu- ally displaced by the next in a perpetual movement of interrogation—each perfection spills over into the other as we seek to explicate the simple act of God. SUBLIMITY, MODERNITY, AND THE UNIVERSALISATION OF SUBJECTIVITY For Kant taste [Geschmach], the faculty by which we make aesthetic judgements, is not predi- cated upon the beautiful object, for beauty [Schon€ ] resides not in the object but in the activation of the faculty of taste, and what Kant names a non-cognitive ‘free play’ [Freispiel]between imagination and understanding. The judgement of taste is ‘not a cognitive judgement, hence not VC 2016 Trustees for Roman Catholic Purposes Registered. Published by John Wiley & Sons Ltd, 9600 Garsington Road, Oxford OX4 2DQ, UK and 350 Main Street, Malden, MA 02148, USA. 2 SCOTT A. KIRKLAND a logical one, but is rather aesthetic, by which is understood one whose determining ground can- not be other than subjective.’1 This object-less construction of beauty is only interested in the object, therefore, insofar as it excites ‘free play’—which is to say, insofar as the object conforms to the subject. Consequently, the beautiful is to be distinguished from the agreeable [angene- hem], something we are interested in for the sake of the gratification of some desire. Taste is dis- tinguished from this more appetitive pleasure by a lack of interest in the object, for the object is of no significance insofar as it can fleetingly arouse desire in me, but rather is beautiful insofar as it arouses my disinterested aesthetic faculties to the free play of the imagination and understanding.2 The ‘non-cognitive’ subjective location of aesthetic judgements means that they bypass any empirical or moral judgement of the object. Kant can then distinguish between the good and the beautiful in important ways, and yet find a way to unite them again in the subject. The judge- ment of taste is understood as contemplative, that is, ‘a judgement that is indifferent with regard to the existence of an object’3 and so it simply finds pleasure without being, so to speak, diverted to a concept. The disinterestedness of the faculty of taste allows us to disentangle the beautiful from the merely agreeable. If taste is disinterested, the object in which it finds pleasure is not arrived at by satisfaction in the agreeable form in the object as such.4 Hence, the judge- ment of beauty is ‘free’, for ‘no interest, neither that of the senses, nor that of reason, extorts approval’.5 Here there is a similarity to moral judgement in that, just as aesthetic judgement is free and able to locate the beautiful in its freedom from interest, moral judgement too must be freed from interest in submission to moral law: ‘For where moral law speaks, there is, objec- tively, no longer any free choice with regard to what is to be done’.6 The two modes of judge- ment, therefore, are bound together in the way they are able to universalise subjectivity, and so move the subject toward subjectively universal ends—the end in itself of free play in beauty, and the end of moral action. Yet, the judgement of the beautiful and the judgement of the good remain entirely different, united only in the subject herself, not in the object. The beautiful, like the moral in the second critique, becomes a further way of instantiating a ‘subjective universality’.7 For Kant, if we are able to establish that all rational human agents share the same faculties of judgement, we can establish that, when we apprehend the beautiful disinterestedly, others who approach the same object will attain to a similar pleasure. This is, importantly, the way back to the object. For, we must speak ‘as if beauty were a property of the object’,8 even though beauty is subjectively grounded. The universal remains subjectivity, for it is only in the assumption of subjective universality that I can overcome what could so easily become a solipsistic relativity. Kant, then, argues that there is nothing that is beautiful, the beau- tiful is only a state of disinterested contemplative consciousness. Yet, precisely because of this disinterestedness, we are able to assume that others, similarly disinterested, would have the same experience of pleasure in their apprehension of the given object. To conclude with this brief survey of Kant, we come to the sublime [Erhanben]. Sublimity assumes the same bypass of the subject’s cognitive faculties that judgements of beauty assume. The difference being the sublime brings something to bear in the subject other than the free play of (the rather more tame) beauty. The sublime is divided into two categories, the mathematical and the dynamic. The sublime in general is concerned with that which is ‘absolutely great’ [schlechthin gross]; the mathematical sublime is concerned with ‘greatness’ [Grose-sein€ ]as ‘magnitude’ [eine Grose sein]. This is not mathematical in the sense that it is intuitive of con- cepts (i.e., numbers or mathematical symbols—which may be beautiful for thinkers like Leibnitz or Spinoza), but in that magnitude is ‘intuited by the eye’ and becomes aesthetically overwhelming. Kant employs the example of St Peter’s Basilica, where ‘there is a feeling of the inadequacy of his [the subject’s] imagination for presenting the ideas of a whole, in which the GLORY OVER SUBLIMITY: KARL BARTH’S THEOLOGICAL AESTHETICS 3 imagination reaches its maximum and, in the effort to extend it, sinks back into itself, but is thereby transported into an emotionally moving satisfaction.’9 The dynamic sublime is con- cerned with lack of control natural power has over the perceiving subject. This is bound up with the kind of fear we feel before natural disasters, or nature’s displays of power (the kind of things the Romantics loved: volcanoes, cyclones, bush fires, etc.). Yet, we consider the ‘object fearful without being afraid of it’ when we realise resistance would be futility. We fear the power of the object in a manner akin to reverent awe. If we are afraid, we will take flight before the object, whereas sublime fear perceives the object in the knowledge that no actual harm can come. So, in the case of the fear of God, we might find ourselves afraid of the absolute power of God because of some wrongdoing that has caused offence to God. This is not the sublime, for it is a fear of harm. ‘Only when he is conscious of his upright, God-pleasing disposition do these effects of [divine] power serve to awaken in him the idea of the sublimity of this being, insofar as he recognises in himself a sublimity of disposition suitable to God’s will, and is thereby raised above fear of such effects of nature, which he does not regard as outbursts of God’s wrath.’10 The sublime, both mathematical and dynamic, therefore, is not concerned with the object as such, but with our feeling before the object. It is a state of consciousness that opens onto that which is absolutely great. GLORY AS THE TELOS OF THE STRUCTURE OF CD II.1 The doctrine of divine simplicity, simply stated, is the doctrine that God is not a composite sub- stance.
Recommended publications
  • HOLY BEAUTY a Reformed Perspective on Aesthetics Within a World of Unjust Ugliness John W. De Gruchy Much of My Theological Ende
    HOLY BEAUTY A Reformed Perspective on Aesthetics within a World of Unjust Ugliness John W. de Gruchy Robert Selby Taylor Professor of Christian Studies Director of the Graduate School in Humanities University of Cape Town Much of my theological endeavour over the years has focussed on the struggle against apartheid in South Africa. During the past decade my focus has shifted to the relationship between Christianity and democratic transformation and, more recently to theological aesthetics and to the role of art in transformation. This latter interest has clearly not meant a lessening of concern for theological engagement with public life. That remains constant both out of the conviction that theology and ethics cannot be separated, and the fact that the struggle against the legacy of apartheid and injustice more generally remains. The transition to democracy requires an ongoing struggle for social transformation. My interest in theological aesthetics, then, is not an opting out of a commitment for social justice but an attempt to address a set of issues that have previously been neglected by those of us who were engaged as theologians in the struggle against apartheid. To emphasise this point let me say that I wrote these words in the midst of a workshop of `Christianity, art and healing’ where the focus was on the new holocaust facing sub-Saharan Africa, the HIV/AIDS pandemic. Nadine Gordimer, the celebrated South African novelist, has noted that art is `at the heart of liberation.’1 The struggle against apartheid certainly produced an artistic creativity of a remarkable kind and intensity.2 It is remarkable, then, that theologians engaged in the struggle did not take this into account in doing theology.
    [Show full text]
  • The Intermediate World: a Key Concept in Beautiful Thinking
    Open Philosophy 2018; 1: 50–58 Dorthe Jørgensen* The Intermediate World: A Key Concept in Beautiful Thinking https://doi.org/10.1515/opphil-2018-0005 Received February 28, 2018; accepted April 25, 2018 Abstract: The term ‘the intermediate world’ is a key concept in Den skønne tænkning (Beautiful Thinking) and the metaphysics of experience presented by this book. The metaphysics of experience is about the experiences of transcendence and beautiful thinking that take place in the intermediate world. In the article “The Intermediate World,” this subject is introduced through a discussion of thoughts and concepts formulated by Paul Klee (Zwischenwelt), Alexander Gottlieb Baumgarten (beautiful thinking), Aristotle (phantasia), Immanuel Kant (expanded thinking), Mark C. Taylor (imagination), and Eugenio Trías (the limit). The text depicts the intermediate world as the level of experience at which the understanding does not yet distinguish between subject and object. The intermediate world is thus not a realm between human and world, nor is it something outside the world we know. The intermediate world is rather the present world in its most original state: the ‘place’ where we find the source of all experience and cognition, a source called ‘basic experience’ characterized by sensation, faith, and comprehension. In this realm, imagination is active and takes the form of an objective force rather than a subjective mental power. Imagination opens mind and world, thus allowing not-yet- actualized possibilities to become perceivable. Keywords: experience, metaphysics, Klee, aesthetics, imagination, Baumgarten, sensitivity, Trías, limit, thinking 1 Introduction The expression ‘beautiful thinking’ derives from §1 in Alexander Gottlieb Baumgarten’s Aesthetica.
    [Show full text]
  • ABSTRACT Love Itself Is Understanding: Balthasar, Truth, and the Saints Matthew A. Moser, Ph.D. Mentor: Peter M. Candler, Jr., P
    ABSTRACT Love Itself is Understanding: Balthasar, Truth, and the Saints Matthew A. Moser, Ph.D. Mentor: Peter M. Candler, Jr., Ph.D. This study examines the thought of Hans Urs von Balthasar on the post-Scholastic separation between dogmatic theology and the spirituality of Church, which he describes as the loss of the saints. Balthasar conceives of this separation as a shattering of truth — the “living exposition of theory in practice and of knowledge carried into action.” The consequence of this shattering is the impoverishment of both divine and creaturely truth. This dissertation identifies Balthasar’s attempt to overcome this divorce between theology and spirituality as a driving theme of his Theo-Logic by arguing that the “truth of Being” — divine and creaturely — is most fundamentally the love revealed by Jesus Christ, and is therefore best known by the saints. Balthasar’s attempted re-integration of speculative theology and spirituality through his theology of the saints serves as his critical response to the metaphysics of German Idealism that elevated thought over love, and, by so doing, lost the transcendental properties of Being: beauty, goodness, and truth. Balthasar constructively responds to this problem by re-appropriating the ancient and medieval spiritual tradition of the saints, as interpreted through his own theological master, Ignatius of Loyola, to develop a trinitarian and Christological ontology and a corresponding pneumatological epistemology, as expressed through the lives, and especially the prayers, of the saints. This project will follow the structure and rhythm of Balthasar’s Theo-Logic in elaborating the initiatory movement of his account of truth: phenomenological, Christological, and pneumatological.
    [Show full text]
  • Beauty As a Transcendental in the Thought of Joseph Ratzinger
    The University of Notre Dame Australia ResearchOnline@ND Theses 2015 Beauty as a transcendental in the thought of Joseph Ratzinger John Jang University of Notre Dame Australia Follow this and additional works at: https://researchonline.nd.edu.au/theses Part of the Philosophy Commons COMMONWEALTH OF AUSTRALIA Copyright Regulations 1969 WARNING The material in this communication may be subject to copyright under the Act. Any further copying or communication of this material by you may be the subject of copyright protection under the Act. Do not remove this notice. Publication Details Jang, J. (2015). Beauty as a transcendental in the thought of Joseph Ratzinger (Master of Philosophy (School of Philosophy and Theology)). University of Notre Dame Australia. https://researchonline.nd.edu.au/theses/112 This dissertation/thesis is brought to you by ResearchOnline@ND. It has been accepted for inclusion in Theses by an authorized administrator of ResearchOnline@ND. For more information, please contact [email protected]. School of Philosophy and Theology Sydney Beauty as a Transcendental in the Thought of Joseph Ratzinger Submitted by John Jang A thesis in partial fulfilment of the requirements of the degree of Master of Philosophy Supervised by Dr. Renée Köhler-Ryan July 2015 © John Jang 2015 Table of Contents Abstract v Declaration of Authorship vi Acknowledgements vii Introduction 1 Structure 3 Method 5 PART I - Metaphysical Beauty 7 1.1.1 The Integration of Philosophy and Theology 8 1.1.2 Ratzinger’s Response 11 1.2.1 Transcendental Participation 14 1.2.2 Transcendental Convertibility 18 1.2.3 Analogy of Being 25 PART II - Reason and Experience 28 2.
    [Show full text]
  • The Proof of Beauty: from Aesthetic Experience to the Beauty of God
    ISSN 1918-7351 Volume 2 (2010) The Proof of Beauty: From Aesthetic Experience to the Beauty of God John D. Dadosky I was feeling part of the scenery I walked right out of the machinery My heart going „boom boom boom‟ “Hey” he said “Grab your things I‟ve come to take you home.” Peter Gabriel, “Solsbury Hill” Introduction Hans Urs Von Balthasar (1904-1986) decries the forgetting of beauty in contemporary philosophy and theology. The loss of transcendental beauty implies a separation and collapse of the other transcendentals: unity, truth and goodness. According to Balthasar, Thomas Aquinas represents the climax of Western philosophy as one who is able to ground a philosophy of beauty for a theological aesthetics. Balthasar eschews any contemporary attempts to transpose Aquinas within a post-Kantian context and as a result, Balthasar‟s magnificent attempt to restore beauty within his multi-volume trilogy, Herrlichkeit, Theodrama, and Theologik, is not able to speak to those outside of the Christian narrative. This is because of his prior philosophical presuppositions that rely specifically on special categories (those specific to Christian theology) that do not give enough attention to general categories (those shared with other disciplines).1 For Bernard Lonergan (1904-1984), general categories are derived from human intentional consciousness. Consonant with Balthasar‟s suspicion of the philosophical turn to the subject, Lonergan labored to respond to the same turn with Insight: A Study of Human Understanding2 and provides a Catholic 1 Concerning this issue, see Robert M. Doran, “Lonergan and Balthasar: Methodological Considerations,” Theological Studies 58 (1997): 61-84.
    [Show full text]
  • Herman Bavinck's Theological Aesthetics: a Synchronic And
    TBR 2 (2011): 43–58 Herman Bavinck’s Theological Aesthetics: A Synchronic and Diachronic Analysis Robert S. Covolo PhD candidate, Fuller Theological Seminary In 1914 Herman Bavinck wrote an article for the Almanak of the Vrije Universiteit entitled, “Of Beauty and Aesthetics,” which has recently been translated and republished for the English-speaking world in Essays on Religion, Science, and Society.1 While this is not the only place where Bavinck treats the subject of beauty, this article stands out as a unique, extended glimpse into Bavinck’s theological aesthetics.2 In it we see that Bavinck was conversant with philosophical aesthetics and aware of the tensions of doing theological aesthetics from both a small “c” catholic and a distinctly Reformed perspective. There are many ways to assess Bavinck’s reflections on aesthetics. For example, one could look at the intimations in Bavinck’s works of the aesthetics formulations of later Dutch Reformed writers such as Rookmaker, Seerveld, or Wolterstorff.3 1. Herman Bavinck, “Of Beauty and Aesthetic” in Essays on Religion, Science and Society, ed. John Bolt, trans. Harry Boonstra and Gerrit Sheeres (Grand Rapids, MI: Eerdmans, 2008), 245–60. 2. See also Herman Bavinck, Reformed Dogmatics, vol. 2, God and Creation, ed. John Bolt, trans. John Vriend (Grand Rapids, MI: Baker, 2004), 252–55. 3. This in itself would prove to be a very interesting study. In one section of the essay Bavinck entertains an idea by a “Mister Berland” who maintains “the characterization of an anarchist situation in the arts.” See Bavinck, “Of Beauty and Aesthetics,” 252.
    [Show full text]
  • Four Perspectives on Karl Rahner's Theological Aesthetics, by Peter Joseph Fritz Judith Wolfe University of St
    Marquette University e-Publications@Marquette Theology Faculty Research and Publications Theology, Department of 1-1-2017 Review Symposium: Four Perspectives on Karl Rahner's Theological Aesthetics, by Peter Joseph Fritz Judith Wolfe University of St. Andrews Gesa Thiessen Trinity College Robert Masson Marquette University, [email protected] Mark F. Fischer St. John's Seminary, Camarillo, CA Accepted version. Philosophy & Theology, Vol. 29, No. 2 (2017): 485–506. DOI. © 2017 Philosophy Documentation Center. Used with permission. Marquette University e-Publications@Marquette Theology Faculty Research and Publications/College of Arts and Sciences This paper is NOT THE PUBLISHED VERSION; but the author’s final, peer-reviewed manuscript. The published version may be accessed by following the link in the citation below. Philosophy & Theology, Vol. 29, No. 2, (2017): 485-506. DOI. This article is © Philosophy Documentation Center and permission has been granted for this version to appear in e- Publications@Marquette. Philosophy Documentation Center does not grant permission for this article to be further copied/distributed or hosted elsewhere without the express permission from Philosophy Documentation Center. Contents I. .................................................................................................................................................................... 2 II. ..................................................................................................................................................................
    [Show full text]
  • Theological Aesthetics and Performatism in the Aestheticization of the Roman Catholic Liturgy
    Obsculta Volume 5 Issue 1 Article 5 July 2014 Theological Aesthetics and Performatism in the Aestheticization of the Roman Catholic Liturgy Audrey Seah College of Saint Benedict/Saint John's University, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.csbsju.edu/obsculta Part of the Christianity Commons, and the Liturgy and Worship Commons ISSN: 2472-2596 (print) ISSN: 2472-260X (online) Recommended Citation Seah, Audrey. 2012. Theological Aesthetics and Performatism in the Aestheticization of the Roman Catholic Liturgy. Obsculta 5, (1) : 16-22. https://digitalcommons.csbsju.edu/obsculta/vol5/iss1/5. This Article is brought to you for free and open access by DigitalCommons@CSB/SJU. It has been accepted for inclusion in Obsculta by an authorized administrator of DigitalCommons@CSB/SJU. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Virgin of Paplin&KDVH%HFNHU Theological Aesthetics and Performatism Audrey Seah in the Aestheticization of the Roman Catholic Liturgy 7KH ÁDXQWLQJ RI WKH Cappa Magna, a surge of interest Catholic liturgy. I will begin my examination by juxtaposing in Gregorian chant and renaissance polyphony, and the re- WKHDHVWKHWLFDOSKHQRPHQRQDJDLQVW+DQV8UVYRQ%DOWKDVDU·V turn of elaborate gothic chasubles are just three visible trends theological aesthetics to discern the potential of aesthetics among many that stir up liturgical debates today. Arguments in theology. Then, I will compare the intended outcome of for and against the new aesthetic reforms that span theologi- theological aesthetics to Perfomatism, an emerging cultural cal, philosophical, historical, social and anthropological ap- phenomenon that is manifesting itself in the Church and its proaches are aplenty. Many of these arguments attempt to liturgy.
    [Show full text]
  • The Trinitarian Theology of Irenaeus of Lyons
    Marquette University e-Publications@Marquette Dissertations, Theses, and Professional Dissertations (1934 -) Projects The Trinitarian Theology of Irenaeus of Lyons Jackson Jay Lashier Marquette University Follow this and additional works at: https://epublications.marquette.edu/dissertations_mu Part of the Religion Commons Recommended Citation Lashier, Jackson Jay, "The Trinitarian Theology of Irenaeus of Lyons" (2011). Dissertations (1934 -). 109. https://epublications.marquette.edu/dissertations_mu/109 THE TRINITARIAN THEOLOGY OF IRENAEUS OF LYONS by Jackson Lashier, B.A., M.Div. A Dissertation submitted to the Faculty of the Graduate School, Marquette University, in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy Milwaukee, Wisconsin May 2011 ABSTRACT THE TRINITARIAN THEOLOGY OF IRENAEUS OF LYONS Jackson Lashier, B.A., M.Div. Marquette University, 2011 This dissertation is a study of the Trinitarian theology of Irenaeus of Lyons. With the exception of two recent studies, Irenaeus’ Trinitarian theology, particularly in its immanent manifestation, has been devalued by scholarship due to his early dates and his stated purpose of avoiding speculative theology. In contrast to this majority opinion, I argue that Irenaeus’ works show a mature understanding of the Trinity, in both its immanent and economic manifestations, which is occasioned by Valentinianism. Moreover, his Trinitarian theology represents a significant advancement upon that of his sources, the so-called apologists, whose understanding of the divine nature converges in many respects with Valentinian theology. I display this advancement by comparing the thought of Irenaeus with that of Justin, Athenagoras, and Theophilus, on Trinitarian themes. Irenaeus develops Trinitarian theology in the following ways. First, he defines God’s nature as spirit, thus maintaining the divine transcendence through God’s higher order of being as opposed to the use of spatial imagery (God is separated/far away from creation).
    [Show full text]
  • Suffering and the Search for Wholeness: Beauty and the Cross in Hans Urs Von Balthasar and Contemporary Feminist Theologies
    Loyola University Chicago Loyola eCommons Dissertations Theses and Dissertations 2009 Suffering and the Search for Wholeness: Beauty and the Cross in Hans Urs Von Balthasar and Contemporary Feminist Theologies Elisabeth T. Vasko Loyola University Chicago Follow this and additional works at: https://ecommons.luc.edu/luc_diss Part of the Religious Thought, Theology and Philosophy of Religion Commons Recommended Citation Vasko, Elisabeth T., "Suffering and the Search for Wholeness: Beauty and the Cross in Hans Urs Von Balthasar and Contemporary Feminist Theologies" (2009). Dissertations. 282. https://ecommons.luc.edu/luc_diss/282 This Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by the Theses and Dissertations at Loyola eCommons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Dissertations by an authorized administrator of Loyola eCommons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-Noncommercial-No Derivative Works 3.0 License. Copyright © 2009 Elisabeth T. Vasko LOYOLA UNIVERSITY CHICAGO SUFFERING AND THE SEARCH FOR WHOLENESS: BEAUTY AND THE CROSS IN HANS URS VON BALTHASAR AND CONTEMPORARY FEMINIST THEOLOGIES A DISSERTATION SUBMITTED TO THE FACULTY OF THE GRADUATE SCHOOL IN CANDIDACY FOR THE DEGREE OF DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY PROGRAM IN THEOLOGY BY ELISABETH T. VASKO DECEMBER 2009 Copyright by Elisabeth T. Vasko, 2009 All rights reserved. ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS First, I want thank my doctoral committee at Loyola University of Chicago. I am grateful to all three for their time, commitment, and investment in my development as a scholar and as a person. As my director, Susan Ross saw me through the best and worst parts of this process.
    [Show full text]
  • The Strange Witness of the Saints: Hans Urs Von Balthasar's
    THE STRANGE WITNESS OF THE SAINTS: HANS URS VON BALTHASAR’S EMBODIED THEOLOGY OF MISSION Thesis Submitted to The College of Arts and Sciences of the UNIVERSITY OF DAYTON In Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for The Degree of Master of Arts in Theological Studies By Carmel Klein UNIVERSITY OF DAYTON Dayton, Ohio December 2017 THE STRANGE WITNESS OF THE SAINTS: HANS URS VON BALTHASAR’S EMBODIED THEOLOGY OF MISSION Name: Klein, Carmel F. APPROVED BY: _____________________________________________ William L. Portier, Ph.D. Thesis Advisor _____________________________________________ William Johnston, Ph.D. Reader _____________________________________________ Sandra Yocum, Ph.D. Reader ii ABSTRACT THE STRANGE WITNESS OF THE SAINTS: HANS URS VON BALTHASAR’S EMBODIED THEOLOGY OF MISSION Name: Klein, Carmel F. University of Dayton Advisor: Dr. William L. Portier The thesis surveys Hans Urs von Balthasar’s theology of mission as presented within the context of the first two parts of his trilogy: The Glory of the Lord: A Theological Aesthetics; and the Theo-Drama. Primary characteristics of his theology of mission are highlighted regarding his assessment of the state of the discipline of theology and its ability to apologize for the faith and to dialogue with contemporary culture. Balthasar envisions the transcendentals of beauty, goodness, and truth, as vital for reimagining the faith and the aggiornamento proposed by Vatican II. Balthasar identifies beauty as the transcendental that has been marginalized by an acquiescent academy deferential to modern pragmatism. For Christianity, the form of beauty that reconciles existential tensions is Jesus Christ. The crucified Christ is the concrete, awe-inspiring, counter-intuitive beauty that demands a response.
    [Show full text]
  • Hans Urs Von Balthasar's Theology of Aesthetic Form
    Theological Studies 49 (1988) CURRENT THEOLOGY HANS URS VON BALTHASARE THEOLOGY OF AESTHETIC FORM LOUIS DUPRÉ Yale University Since the recent publication in English of the first three volumes of The Glory of the Lord, it has become redundant to sing the praises of Hans Urs von Balthasars great work. Herrlichkeit, a seven-volume summa of theological aesthetics, as comprehensive as it is original, began to appear in Basel 25 years ago. What until recently had remained a cult book reserved to a small number of patient, theologically erudite readers sufficiently familiar with the German language to appreciate B.'s creative but often poetically obscure use of it, may now attract a larger but probably less critical readership in America. I have contributed to the high praise the magnum opus deserves in an essay (in Religion and Literature) that mostly deals with the literary, third volume, Studies in Theological Style: Lay Style. Here I would like to write a more critical assessment, analyzing more closely the theological issues as they emerge primarily in the first two volumes, Seeing the Form and Studies in Theological Style: Clerical Style (covering the patristic and medieval periods), with occasional references to the as yet untranslated volumes on the Old and New Testament.1 The division between clerical and lay draws us immediately into controversy. The author claims to have chosen official theologians, "so long as such were available, who were able to treat the radiant power of the revelation of Christ both influentially and originally, without any trace of decadence; but after Thomas Aquinas theologians of such stature are rare" (2:15).
    [Show full text]